4-proofs.ltx 5.8 KB

123456789101112131415161718192021222324252627282930313233343536373839404142434445464748495051525354555657585960616263646566676869707172737475767778798081828384858687888990919293949596979899100101102103104105106107108109110111112113114115116117118119120121122123124125126127128129130131132133134135136137138139140141142143144145146147148149150151152
  1. \ch{Proofs}
  2. \s{Peano Axioms}
  3. This section covers the Peano axioms. As I said in \cref{s: Motivation}, these
  4. are a way for mathematicians to understand arithmetic.
  5. Arithmetic (hopefully) seems simple enough, and easy to understand. Maybe an
  6. expression like
  7. \[ (2048282 \times 33221) + (3254 \times 11) \]
  8. seems difficult to calculate, but you hopefully understand what each of the
  9. operators mean in concept. If you don't, well. In theory, reading this chapter
  10. alone will teach you arithmetic. However, I wrote this chapter assuming you
  11. already know arithmetic.
  12. So, why is it important that you read this chapter?
  13. Arithmetic is pretty simple and easy to understand. However, later on in this
  14. book, we're going to approach concepts that aren't so simple and easy to
  15. understand. Mathematicians have a systemic approach to these problems. This
  16. approach is called ``mathematical proof.'' We prove things
  17. mathematically. Instead of approaching new concepts with proofs, I'm instead
  18. going to use proofs to illustrate some (hopefully) familiar concepts.
  19. Alright, with all that out of the way, let's get started.
  20. The basic idea of proofs is, you take a small set of obvious facts, called {\it
  21. axioms}, chain them together to make {\it theorems}. The following obvious
  22. facts, or axioms, are called the ``Peano Axioms.'' They describe what we call
  23. ``natural numbers.'' Natural numbers are the numbers
  24. $\{0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, \ldots\}$.
  25. % I got these from Landau's book, but there's nowhere where it isn't awkward to
  26. % cite him. So, instead, I'll use \nocite
  27. \nocite{landau-analysis}
  28. \begin{description}
  29. \item[Axiom 1] $0$ is a natural number. Again, obvious.
  30. I'm going to use letters in the place of numbers right here. So, if I say
  31. ``$x$ is a natural number,'' that means that $x$ is a placeholder for one of
  32. the numbers in $\{0,1,2,3,4,5,6,\ldots\}$. I could use any letter, such as
  33. $a$, $b$, $q$, $r$, $\theta$, $\Gamma$, or $\aleph$. If I use a letter instead
  34. of a number, it usually means either
  35. \begin{enumerate}
  36. \item it doesn't matter which number I choose, or
  37. \item it does matter which number I choose, but I don't know which number it
  38. is yet.
  39. \end{enumerate}
  40. \item[Axiom 2] If $x$ is a natural number, it is true that $x \equiv x$.
  41. You can read that $\equiv$ sign as $=$, for the time being. There are some
  42. subtle differences between the two, which I will get to in \cref{ch:
  43. Functions}. You are supposed to read $a \equiv b$ as one of these:
  44. \begin{enumerate}
  45. \item ``$a$ is equivalent to $b$,''
  46. \item ``$a$ is identically equivalent to $b$,''
  47. \item ``$a$ is congruent to $b$.''
  48. \end{enumerate}
  49. $=$ should be read as ``$a$ is equal to $b$,'' or ``$a$ equals $b$.'' Again
  50. the difference between $\equiv$ and $=$ isn't really important until \cref{ch:
  51. Functions}.
  52. If you don't know what either of those signs are, $a \equiv b$ or $a = b$
  53. means ``$a$ is the same thing as $b$.'' The difference can be summarized as
  54. $= = \equiv \not \equiv = $.
  55. So, in essence, this axiom says that each number is the same thing as
  56. itself. This is hopefully very obvious.
  57. A math person would state this axiom as ``congruence is reflexive.''
  58. \item[Axiom 3] If $x$ and $y$ are both natural numbers, and $x \equiv y$, then
  59. it's true that $y \equiv x$. You can phrase this axiom as ``if two numbers are
  60. the same number, then they are the same number.'' A math person would state
  61. this axiom as ``congruence is symmetric.''
  62. \item[Axiom 4] If $x$, $y$, and $z$ are all natural numbers, and $x \equiv y$,
  63. and $y \equiv z$ then it's true that $x \equiv z$. You can phrase this axiom
  64. as ``if three numbers are all the same number, then they are the same
  65. number.'' A math person would state this axiom as ``congruence is
  66. transitive.''
  67. These last three axioms mean that we can be lazy, and write things like
  68. $a \equiv b \equiv c \equiv a$.
  69. \item[Axiom 5] If $x$ is a natural number, and we know $x \equiv y$, then it's
  70. also true that $y$ is a natural number. A math person would say ``congruence
  71. forms a closure.''
  72. \item[Axiom 6] If $x$ is a natural number, then there is another number,
  73. $\suc(x)$, which is also a natural number. $\suc$ is short for ``successor.''
  74. You should read $\suc(x)$ as ``the successor of $x$.'' You can think of the
  75. successor as ``the next number.'' So, $\suc(0) \equiv 1$, $\suc(1) \equiv 2$,
  76. and so on.
  77. \item[Axiom 7] There isn't a number whose successor is $0$. Basically this means
  78. ``$0$ is the lowest natural number.''
  79. \item[Axiom 8] If $x$ and $y$ are both natural numbers, and we know
  80. $\suc(x) \equiv \suc(y)$, then it's true that $x \equiv y$. This is what we
  81. would call the ``converse'' of Axiom 6. That is, Axiom 6 tells us that we can
  82. always go ``up'' a number. This axiom (almost) tells us that we can go
  83. ``down'' a number. Axiom 7 defines the limit of this, meaning that $0$ is the
  84. only number where you can't go down any further.
  85. Now, the previous 8 axioms have basically said ``these numbers are all natural
  86. numbers.'' This next, and final axiom states ``these numbers are all {\it of}
  87. the natural numbers.''
  88. \item[Axiom 9] Let's say $K$ is a set of numbers (a bunch of numbers). If we
  89. know that
  90. \begin{enumerate}
  91. \item if $0$ is in $K$, and
  92. \item if some number $x$ is in $K$, then $\suc(x)$ is in $K$,
  93. \item then $K$ contains every single natural number.
  94. \end{enumerate}
  95. \end{description}
  96. \pg{Continue with...}
  97. \begin{enumerate}
  98. \item $\N$ is a Monoid
  99. \item Quasigroups
  100. \item Loops
  101. \item Groups
  102. \item Abelian Groups
  103. \begin{enumerate}
  104. \item $\Z$
  105. \begin{enumerate}
  106. \item $\Z$ is an Abelian Group
  107. \item $\Z$ is a ring
  108. \end{enumerate}
  109. \end{enumerate}
  110. \item Fields
  111. \begin{enumerate}
  112. \item $\R$
  113. \begin{enumerate}
  114. \item $\R$ is a field
  115. \end{enumerate}
  116. \end{enumerate}
  117. \item Categories
  118. \item Groupoids
  119. \end{enumerate}