Henri Bergson - Creative Evolution.txt 848 KB

12345678910111213141516171819202122232425262728293031323334353637383940414243444546474849505152535455565758596061626364656667686970717273747576777879808182838485868788899091929394959697989910010110210310410510610710810911011111211311411511611711811912012112212312412512612712812913013113213313413513613713813914014114214314414514614714814915015115215315415515615715815916016116216316416516616716816917017117217317417517617717817918018118218318418518618718818919019119219319419519619719819920020120220320420520620720820921021121221321421521621721821922022122222322422522622722822923023123223323423523623723823924024124224324424524624724824925025125225325425525625725825926026126226326426526626726826927027127227327427527627727827928028128228328428528628728828929029129229329429529629729829930030130230330430530630730830931031131231331431531631731831932032132232332432532632732832933033133233333433533633733833934034134234334434534634734834935035135235335435535635735835936036136236336436536636736836937037137237337437537637737837938038138238338438538638738838939039139239339439539639739839940040140240340440540640740840941041141241341441541641741841942042142242342442542642742842943043143243343443543643743843944044144244344444544644744844945045145245345445545645745845946046146246346446546646746846947047147247347447547647747847948048148248348448548648748848949049149249349449549649749849950050150250350450550650750850951051151251351451551651751851952052152252352452552652752852953053153253353453553653753853954054154254354454554654754854955055155255355455555655755855956056156256356456556656756856957057157257357457557657757857958058158258358458558658758858959059159259359459559659759859960060160260360460560660760860961061161261361461561661761861962062162262362462562662762862963063163263363463563663763863964064164264364464564664764864965065165265365465565665765865966066166266366466566666766866967067167267367467567667767867968068168268368468568668768868969069169269369469569669769869970070170270370470570670770870971071171271371471571671771871972072172272372472572672772872973073173273373473573673773873974074174274374474574674774874975075175275375475575675775875976076176276376476576676776876977077177277377477577677777877978078178278378478578678778878979079179279379479579679779879980080180280380480580680780880981081181281381481581681781881982082182282382482582682782882983083183283383483583683783883984084184284384484584684784884985085185285385485585685785885986086186286386486586686786886987087187287387487587687787887988088188288388488588688788888989089189289389489589689789889990090190290390490590690790890991091191291391491591691791891992092192292392492592692792892993093193293393493593693793893994094194294394494594694794894995095195295395495595695795895996096196296396496596696796896997097197297397497597697797897998098198298398498598698798898999099199299399499599699799899910001001100210031004100510061007100810091010101110121013101410151016101710181019102010211022102310241025102610271028102910301031103210331034103510361037103810391040104110421043104410451046104710481049105010511052105310541055105610571058105910601061106210631064106510661067106810691070107110721073107410751076107710781079108010811082108310841085108610871088108910901091109210931094109510961097109810991100110111021103110411051106110711081109111011111112111311141115111611171118111911201121112211231124112511261127112811291130113111321133113411351136113711381139114011411142114311441145114611471148114911501151115211531154115511561157115811591160116111621163116411651166116711681169117011711172117311741175117611771178117911801181118211831184118511861187118811891190119111921193119411951196119711981199120012011202120312041205120612071208120912101211121212131214121512161217121812191220122112221223122412251226122712281229123012311232123312341235123612371238123912401241124212431244124512461247124812491250125112521253125412551256125712581259126012611262126312641265126612671268126912701271127212731274127512761277127812791280128112821283128412851286128712881289129012911292129312941295129612971298129913001301130213031304130513061307130813091310131113121313131413151316131713181319132013211322132313241325132613271328132913301331133213331334133513361337133813391340134113421343134413451346134713481349135013511352135313541355135613571358135913601361136213631364136513661367136813691370137113721373137413751376137713781379138013811382138313841385138613871388138913901391139213931394139513961397139813991400140114021403140414051406140714081409141014111412141314141415141614171418141914201421142214231424142514261427142814291430143114321433143414351436143714381439144014411442144314441445144614471448144914501451145214531454145514561457145814591460146114621463146414651466146714681469147014711472147314741475147614771478147914801481148214831484148514861487148814891490149114921493149414951496149714981499150015011502150315041505150615071508150915101511151215131514151515161517151815191520152115221523152415251526152715281529153015311532153315341535153615371538153915401541154215431544154515461547154815491550155115521553155415551556155715581559156015611562156315641565156615671568156915701571157215731574157515761577157815791580158115821583158415851586158715881589159015911592159315941595159615971598159916001601160216031604160516061607160816091610161116121613161416151616161716181619162016211622162316241625162616271628162916301631163216331634163516361637163816391640164116421643164416451646164716481649165016511652165316541655165616571658165916601661166216631664166516661667166816691670167116721673167416751676167716781679168016811682168316841685168616871688168916901691169216931694169516961697169816991700170117021703170417051706170717081709171017111712171317141715171617171718171917201721172217231724172517261727172817291730173117321733173417351736173717381739174017411742174317441745174617471748174917501751175217531754175517561757175817591760176117621763176417651766176717681769177017711772177317741775177617771778177917801781178217831784178517861787178817891790179117921793179417951796179717981799180018011802180318041805180618071808180918101811181218131814181518161817181818191820182118221823182418251826182718281829183018311832183318341835183618371838183918401841184218431844184518461847184818491850185118521853185418551856185718581859186018611862186318641865186618671868186918701871187218731874187518761877187818791880188118821883188418851886188718881889189018911892189318941895189618971898189919001901190219031904190519061907190819091910191119121913191419151916191719181919192019211922192319241925192619271928192919301931193219331934193519361937193819391940194119421943194419451946194719481949195019511952195319541955195619571958195919601961196219631964196519661967196819691970197119721973197419751976197719781979198019811982198319841985198619871988198919901991199219931994199519961997199819992000200120022003200420052006200720082009201020112012201320142015201620172018201920202021202220232024202520262027202820292030203120322033203420352036203720382039204020412042204320442045204620472048204920502051205220532054205520562057205820592060206120622063206420652066206720682069207020712072207320742075207620772078207920802081208220832084208520862087208820892090209120922093209420952096209720982099210021012102210321042105210621072108210921102111211221132114211521162117211821192120212121222123212421252126212721282129213021312132213321342135213621372138213921402141214221432144214521462147214821492150215121522153215421552156215721582159216021612162216321642165216621672168216921702171217221732174217521762177217821792180218121822183218421852186218721882189219021912192219321942195219621972198219922002201220222032204220522062207220822092210221122122213221422152216221722182219222022212222222322242225222622272228222922302231223222332234223522362237223822392240224122422243224422452246224722482249225022512252225322542255225622572258225922602261226222632264226522662267226822692270227122722273227422752276227722782279228022812282228322842285228622872288228922902291229222932294229522962297229822992300230123022303230423052306230723082309231023112312231323142315231623172318231923202321232223232324232523262327232823292330233123322333233423352336233723382339234023412342234323442345234623472348234923502351235223532354235523562357235823592360236123622363236423652366236723682369237023712372237323742375237623772378237923802381238223832384238523862387238823892390239123922393239423952396239723982399240024012402240324042405240624072408240924102411241224132414241524162417241824192420242124222423242424252426242724282429243024312432243324342435243624372438243924402441244224432444244524462447244824492450245124522453245424552456245724582459246024612462246324642465246624672468246924702471247224732474247524762477247824792480248124822483248424852486248724882489249024912492249324942495249624972498249925002501250225032504250525062507250825092510251125122513251425152516251725182519252025212522252325242525252625272528252925302531253225332534253525362537253825392540254125422543254425452546254725482549255025512552255325542555255625572558255925602561256225632564256525662567256825692570257125722573257425752576257725782579258025812582258325842585258625872588258925902591259225932594259525962597259825992600260126022603260426052606260726082609261026112612261326142615261626172618261926202621262226232624262526262627262826292630263126322633263426352636263726382639264026412642264326442645264626472648264926502651265226532654265526562657265826592660266126622663266426652666266726682669267026712672267326742675267626772678267926802681268226832684268526862687268826892690269126922693269426952696269726982699270027012702270327042705270627072708270927102711271227132714271527162717271827192720272127222723272427252726272727282729273027312732273327342735273627372738273927402741274227432744274527462747274827492750275127522753275427552756275727582759276027612762276327642765276627672768276927702771277227732774277527762777277827792780278127822783278427852786278727882789279027912792279327942795279627972798279928002801280228032804280528062807280828092810281128122813281428152816281728182819282028212822282328242825282628272828282928302831283228332834283528362837283828392840284128422843284428452846284728482849285028512852285328542855285628572858285928602861286228632864286528662867286828692870287128722873287428752876287728782879288028812882288328842885288628872888288928902891289228932894289528962897289828992900290129022903290429052906290729082909291029112912291329142915291629172918291929202921292229232924292529262927292829292930293129322933293429352936293729382939294029412942294329442945294629472948294929502951295229532954295529562957295829592960296129622963296429652966296729682969297029712972297329742975297629772978297929802981298229832984298529862987298829892990299129922993299429952996299729982999300030013002300330043005300630073008300930103011301230133014301530163017301830193020302130223023302430253026302730283029303030313032303330343035303630373038303930403041304230433044304530463047304830493050305130523053305430553056305730583059306030613062306330643065306630673068306930703071307230733074307530763077307830793080308130823083308430853086308730883089309030913092309330943095309630973098309931003101310231033104310531063107310831093110311131123113311431153116311731183119312031213122312331243125312631273128312931303131313231333134313531363137313831393140314131423143314431453146314731483149315031513152315331543155315631573158315931603161316231633164316531663167316831693170317131723173317431753176317731783179318031813182318331843185318631873188318931903191319231933194319531963197319831993200320132023203320432053206320732083209321032113212321332143215321632173218321932203221322232233224322532263227322832293230323132323233323432353236323732383239324032413242324332443245324632473248324932503251325232533254325532563257325832593260326132623263326432653266326732683269327032713272327332743275327632773278327932803281328232833284328532863287328832893290329132923293329432953296329732983299330033013302330333043305330633073308330933103311331233133314331533163317331833193320332133223323332433253326332733283329333033313332333333343335333633373338333933403341334233433344334533463347334833493350335133523353335433553356335733583359336033613362336333643365336633673368336933703371337233733374337533763377337833793380338133823383338433853386338733883389339033913392339333943395339633973398339934003401340234033404340534063407340834093410341134123413341434153416341734183419342034213422342334243425342634273428342934303431343234333434343534363437343834393440344134423443344434453446344734483449345034513452345334543455345634573458345934603461346234633464346534663467346834693470347134723473347434753476347734783479348034813482348334843485348634873488348934903491349234933494349534963497349834993500350135023503350435053506350735083509351035113512351335143515351635173518351935203521352235233524352535263527352835293530353135323533353435353536353735383539354035413542354335443545354635473548354935503551355235533554355535563557355835593560356135623563356435653566356735683569357035713572357335743575357635773578357935803581358235833584358535863587358835893590359135923593359435953596359735983599360036013602360336043605360636073608360936103611361236133614361536163617361836193620362136223623362436253626362736283629363036313632363336343635363636373638363936403641364236433644364536463647364836493650365136523653365436553656365736583659366036613662366336643665366636673668366936703671367236733674367536763677367836793680368136823683368436853686368736883689369036913692369336943695369636973698369937003701370237033704370537063707370837093710371137123713371437153716371737183719372037213722372337243725372637273728372937303731373237333734373537363737373837393740374137423743374437453746374737483749375037513752375337543755375637573758375937603761376237633764376537663767376837693770377137723773377437753776377737783779378037813782378337843785378637873788378937903791379237933794379537963797379837993800380138023803380438053806380738083809381038113812381338143815381638173818381938203821382238233824382538263827382838293830383138323833383438353836383738383839384038413842384338443845384638473848384938503851385238533854385538563857385838593860386138623863386438653866386738683869387038713872387338743875387638773878387938803881388238833884388538863887388838893890389138923893389438953896389738983899390039013902390339043905390639073908390939103911391239133914391539163917391839193920392139223923392439253926392739283929393039313932393339343935393639373938393939403941394239433944394539463947394839493950395139523953395439553956395739583959396039613962396339643965396639673968396939703971397239733974397539763977397839793980398139823983398439853986398739883989399039913992399339943995399639973998399940004001400240034004400540064007400840094010401140124013401440154016401740184019402040214022402340244025402640274028402940304031403240334034403540364037403840394040404140424043404440454046404740484049405040514052405340544055405640574058405940604061406240634064406540664067406840694070407140724073407440754076407740784079408040814082408340844085408640874088408940904091409240934094409540964097409840994100410141024103410441054106410741084109411041114112411341144115411641174118411941204121412241234124412541264127412841294130413141324133413441354136413741384139414041414142414341444145414641474148414941504151415241534154415541564157415841594160416141624163416441654166416741684169417041714172417341744175417641774178417941804181418241834184418541864187418841894190419141924193419441954196419741984199420042014202420342044205420642074208420942104211421242134214421542164217421842194220422142224223422442254226422742284229423042314232423342344235423642374238423942404241424242434244424542464247424842494250425142524253425442554256425742584259426042614262426342644265426642674268426942704271427242734274427542764277427842794280428142824283428442854286428742884289429042914292429342944295429642974298429943004301430243034304430543064307430843094310431143124313431443154316431743184319432043214322432343244325432643274328432943304331433243334334433543364337433843394340434143424343434443454346434743484349435043514352435343544355435643574358435943604361436243634364436543664367436843694370437143724373437443754376437743784379438043814382438343844385438643874388438943904391439243934394439543964397439843994400440144024403440444054406440744084409441044114412441344144415441644174418441944204421442244234424442544264427442844294430443144324433443444354436443744384439444044414442444344444445444644474448444944504451445244534454445544564457445844594460446144624463446444654466446744684469447044714472447344744475447644774478447944804481448244834484448544864487448844894490449144924493449444954496449744984499450045014502450345044505450645074508450945104511451245134514451545164517451845194520452145224523452445254526452745284529453045314532453345344535453645374538453945404541454245434544454545464547454845494550455145524553455445554556455745584559456045614562456345644565456645674568456945704571457245734574457545764577457845794580458145824583458445854586458745884589459045914592459345944595459645974598459946004601460246034604460546064607460846094610461146124613461446154616461746184619462046214622462346244625462646274628462946304631463246334634463546364637463846394640464146424643464446454646464746484649465046514652465346544655465646574658465946604661466246634664466546664667466846694670467146724673467446754676467746784679468046814682468346844685468646874688468946904691469246934694469546964697469846994700470147024703470447054706470747084709471047114712471347144715471647174718471947204721472247234724472547264727472847294730473147324733473447354736473747384739474047414742474347444745474647474748474947504751475247534754475547564757475847594760476147624763476447654766476747684769477047714772477347744775477647774778477947804781478247834784478547864787478847894790479147924793479447954796479747984799480048014802480348044805480648074808480948104811481248134814481548164817481848194820482148224823482448254826482748284829483048314832483348344835483648374838483948404841484248434844484548464847484848494850485148524853485448554856485748584859486048614862486348644865486648674868486948704871487248734874487548764877487848794880488148824883488448854886488748884889489048914892489348944895489648974898489949004901490249034904490549064907490849094910491149124913491449154916491749184919492049214922492349244925492649274928492949304931493249334934493549364937493849394940494149424943494449454946494749484949495049514952495349544955495649574958495949604961496249634964496549664967496849694970497149724973497449754976497749784979498049814982498349844985498649874988498949904991499249934994499549964997499849995000500150025003500450055006500750085009501050115012501350145015501650175018501950205021502250235024502550265027502850295030503150325033503450355036503750385039504050415042504350445045504650475048504950505051505250535054505550565057505850595060506150625063506450655066506750685069507050715072507350745075507650775078507950805081508250835084508550865087508850895090509150925093509450955096509750985099510051015102510351045105510651075108510951105111511251135114511551165117511851195120512151225123512451255126512751285129513051315132513351345135513651375138513951405141514251435144514551465147514851495150515151525153515451555156515751585159516051615162516351645165516651675168516951705171517251735174517551765177517851795180518151825183518451855186518751885189519051915192519351945195519651975198519952005201520252035204520552065207520852095210521152125213521452155216521752185219522052215222522352245225522652275228522952305231523252335234523552365237523852395240524152425243524452455246524752485249525052515252525352545255525652575258525952605261526252635264526552665267526852695270527152725273527452755276527752785279528052815282528352845285528652875288528952905291529252935294529552965297529852995300530153025303530453055306530753085309531053115312531353145315531653175318531953205321532253235324532553265327532853295330533153325333533453355336533753385339534053415342534353445345534653475348534953505351535253535354535553565357535853595360536153625363536453655366536753685369537053715372537353745375537653775378537953805381538253835384538553865387538853895390539153925393539453955396539753985399540054015402540354045405540654075408540954105411541254135414541554165417541854195420542154225423542454255426542754285429543054315432543354345435543654375438543954405441544254435444544554465447544854495450545154525453545454555456545754585459546054615462546354645465546654675468546954705471547254735474547554765477547854795480548154825483548454855486548754885489549054915492549354945495549654975498549955005501550255035504550555065507550855095510551155125513551455155516551755185519552055215522552355245525552655275528552955305531553255335534553555365537553855395540554155425543554455455546554755485549555055515552555355545555555655575558555955605561556255635564556555665567556855695570557155725573557455755576557755785579558055815582558355845585558655875588558955905591559255935594559555965597559855995600560156025603560456055606560756085609561056115612561356145615561656175618561956205621562256235624562556265627562856295630563156325633563456355636563756385639564056415642564356445645564656475648564956505651565256535654565556565657565856595660566156625663566456655666566756685669567056715672567356745675567656775678567956805681568256835684568556865687568856895690569156925693569456955696569756985699570057015702570357045705570657075708570957105711571257135714571557165717571857195720572157225723572457255726572757285729573057315732573357345735573657375738573957405741574257435744574557465747574857495750575157525753575457555756575757585759576057615762576357645765576657675768576957705771577257735774577557765777577857795780578157825783578457855786578757885789579057915792579357945795579657975798579958005801580258035804580558065807580858095810581158125813581458155816581758185819582058215822582358245825582658275828582958305831583258335834583558365837583858395840584158425843584458455846584758485849585058515852585358545855585658575858585958605861586258635864586558665867586858695870587158725873587458755876587758785879588058815882588358845885588658875888588958905891589258935894589558965897589858995900590159025903590459055906590759085909591059115912591359145915591659175918591959205921592259235924592559265927592859295930593159325933593459355936593759385939594059415942594359445945594659475948594959505951595259535954595559565957595859595960596159625963596459655966596759685969597059715972597359745975597659775978597959805981598259835984598559865987598859895990599159925993599459955996599759985999600060016002600360046005600660076008600960106011601260136014601560166017601860196020602160226023602460256026602760286029603060316032603360346035603660376038603960406041604260436044604560466047604860496050605160526053605460556056605760586059606060616062606360646065606660676068606960706071607260736074607560766077607860796080608160826083608460856086608760886089609060916092609360946095609660976098609961006101610261036104610561066107610861096110611161126113611461156116611761186119612061216122612361246125612661276128612961306131613261336134613561366137613861396140614161426143614461456146614761486149615061516152615361546155615661576158615961606161616261636164616561666167616861696170617161726173617461756176617761786179618061816182618361846185618661876188618961906191619261936194619561966197619861996200620162026203620462056206620762086209621062116212621362146215621662176218621962206221622262236224622562266227622862296230623162326233623462356236623762386239624062416242624362446245624662476248624962506251625262536254625562566257625862596260626162626263626462656266626762686269627062716272627362746275627662776278627962806281628262836284628562866287628862896290629162926293629462956296629762986299630063016302630363046305630663076308630963106311631263136314631563166317631863196320632163226323632463256326632763286329633063316332633363346335633663376338633963406341634263436344634563466347634863496350635163526353635463556356635763586359636063616362636363646365636663676368636963706371637263736374637563766377637863796380638163826383638463856386638763886389639063916392639363946395639663976398639964006401640264036404640564066407640864096410641164126413641464156416641764186419642064216422642364246425642664276428642964306431643264336434643564366437643864396440644164426443644464456446644764486449645064516452645364546455645664576458645964606461646264636464646564666467646864696470647164726473647464756476647764786479648064816482648364846485648664876488648964906491649264936494649564966497649864996500650165026503650465056506650765086509651065116512651365146515651665176518651965206521652265236524652565266527652865296530653165326533653465356536653765386539654065416542654365446545654665476548654965506551655265536554655565566557655865596560656165626563656465656566656765686569657065716572657365746575657665776578657965806581658265836584658565866587658865896590659165926593659465956596659765986599660066016602660366046605660666076608660966106611661266136614661566166617661866196620662166226623662466256626662766286629663066316632663366346635663666376638663966406641664266436644664566466647664866496650665166526653665466556656665766586659666066616662666366646665666666676668666966706671667266736674667566766677667866796680668166826683668466856686668766886689669066916692669366946695669666976698669967006701670267036704670567066707670867096710671167126713671467156716671767186719672067216722672367246725672667276728672967306731673267336734673567366737673867396740674167426743674467456746674767486749675067516752675367546755675667576758675967606761676267636764676567666767676867696770677167726773677467756776677767786779678067816782678367846785678667876788678967906791679267936794679567966797679867996800680168026803680468056806680768086809681068116812681368146815681668176818681968206821682268236824682568266827682868296830683168326833683468356836683768386839684068416842684368446845684668476848684968506851685268536854685568566857685868596860686168626863686468656866686768686869687068716872687368746875687668776878687968806881688268836884688568866887688868896890689168926893689468956896689768986899690069016902690369046905690669076908690969106911691269136914691569166917691869196920692169226923692469256926692769286929693069316932693369346935693669376938693969406941694269436944694569466947694869496950695169526953695469556956695769586959696069616962696369646965696669676968696969706971697269736974697569766977697869796980698169826983698469856986698769886989699069916992699369946995699669976998699970007001700270037004700570067007700870097010701170127013701470157016701770187019702070217022702370247025702670277028702970307031703270337034703570367037703870397040704170427043704470457046704770487049705070517052705370547055705670577058705970607061706270637064706570667067706870697070707170727073707470757076707770787079708070817082708370847085708670877088708970907091709270937094709570967097709870997100710171027103710471057106710771087109711071117112711371147115711671177118711971207121712271237124712571267127712871297130713171327133713471357136713771387139714071417142714371447145714671477148714971507151715271537154715571567157715871597160716171627163716471657166716771687169717071717172717371747175717671777178717971807181718271837184718571867187718871897190719171927193719471957196719771987199720072017202720372047205720672077208720972107211721272137214721572167217721872197220722172227223722472257226722772287229723072317232723372347235723672377238723972407241724272437244724572467247724872497250725172527253725472557256725772587259726072617262726372647265726672677268726972707271727272737274727572767277727872797280728172827283728472857286728772887289729072917292729372947295729672977298729973007301730273037304730573067307730873097310731173127313731473157316731773187319732073217322732373247325732673277328732973307331733273337334733573367337733873397340734173427343734473457346734773487349735073517352735373547355735673577358735973607361736273637364736573667367736873697370737173727373737473757376737773787379738073817382738373847385738673877388738973907391739273937394739573967397739873997400740174027403740474057406740774087409741074117412741374147415741674177418741974207421742274237424742574267427742874297430743174327433743474357436743774387439744074417442744374447445744674477448744974507451745274537454745574567457745874597460746174627463746474657466746774687469747074717472747374747475747674777478747974807481748274837484748574867487748874897490749174927493749474957496749774987499750075017502750375047505750675077508750975107511751275137514751575167517751875197520752175227523752475257526752775287529753075317532753375347535753675377538753975407541754275437544754575467547754875497550755175527553755475557556755775587559756075617562756375647565756675677568756975707571757275737574757575767577757875797580758175827583758475857586758775887589759075917592759375947595759675977598759976007601760276037604760576067607760876097610761176127613761476157616761776187619762076217622762376247625762676277628762976307631763276337634763576367637763876397640764176427643764476457646764776487649765076517652765376547655765676577658765976607661766276637664766576667667766876697670767176727673767476757676767776787679768076817682768376847685768676877688768976907691769276937694769576967697769876997700770177027703770477057706770777087709771077117712771377147715771677177718771977207721772277237724772577267727772877297730773177327733773477357736773777387739774077417742774377447745774677477748774977507751775277537754775577567757775877597760776177627763776477657766776777687769777077717772777377747775777677777778777977807781778277837784778577867787778877897790779177927793779477957796779777987799780078017802780378047805780678077808780978107811781278137814781578167817781878197820782178227823782478257826782778287829783078317832783378347835783678377838783978407841784278437844784578467847784878497850785178527853785478557856785778587859786078617862786378647865786678677868786978707871787278737874787578767877787878797880788178827883788478857886788778887889789078917892789378947895789678977898789979007901790279037904790579067907790879097910791179127913791479157916791779187919792079217922792379247925792679277928792979307931793279337934793579367937793879397940794179427943794479457946794779487949795079517952795379547955795679577958795979607961796279637964796579667967796879697970797179727973797479757976797779787979798079817982798379847985798679877988798979907991799279937994799579967997799879998000800180028003800480058006800780088009801080118012801380148015801680178018801980208021802280238024802580268027802880298030803180328033803480358036803780388039804080418042804380448045804680478048804980508051805280538054805580568057805880598060806180628063806480658066806780688069807080718072807380748075807680778078807980808081808280838084808580868087808880898090809180928093809480958096809780988099810081018102810381048105810681078108810981108111811281138114811581168117811881198120812181228123812481258126812781288129813081318132813381348135813681378138813981408141814281438144814581468147814881498150815181528153815481558156815781588159816081618162816381648165816681678168816981708171817281738174817581768177817881798180818181828183818481858186818781888189819081918192819381948195819681978198819982008201820282038204820582068207820882098210821182128213821482158216821782188219822082218222822382248225822682278228822982308231823282338234823582368237823882398240824182428243824482458246824782488249825082518252825382548255825682578258825982608261826282638264826582668267826882698270827182728273827482758276827782788279828082818282828382848285828682878288828982908291829282938294829582968297829882998300830183028303830483058306830783088309831083118312831383148315831683178318831983208321832283238324832583268327832883298330833183328333833483358336833783388339834083418342834383448345834683478348834983508351835283538354835583568357835883598360836183628363836483658366836783688369837083718372837383748375837683778378837983808381838283838384838583868387838883898390839183928393839483958396839783988399840084018402840384048405840684078408840984108411841284138414841584168417841884198420842184228423842484258426842784288429843084318432843384348435843684378438843984408441844284438444844584468447844884498450845184528453845484558456845784588459846084618462846384648465846684678468846984708471847284738474847584768477847884798480848184828483848484858486848784888489849084918492849384948495849684978498849985008501850285038504850585068507850885098510851185128513851485158516851785188519852085218522852385248525852685278528852985308531853285338534853585368537853885398540854185428543854485458546854785488549855085518552855385548555855685578558855985608561856285638564856585668567856885698570857185728573857485758576857785788579858085818582858385848585858685878588858985908591859285938594859585968597859885998600860186028603860486058606860786088609861086118612861386148615861686178618861986208621862286238624862586268627862886298630863186328633863486358636863786388639864086418642864386448645864686478648864986508651865286538654865586568657865886598660866186628663866486658666866786688669867086718672867386748675867686778678867986808681868286838684868586868687868886898690869186928693869486958696869786988699870087018702870387048705870687078708870987108711871287138714871587168717871887198720872187228723872487258726872787288729873087318732873387348735873687378738873987408741874287438744874587468747874887498750875187528753875487558756875787588759876087618762876387648765876687678768876987708771877287738774877587768777877887798780878187828783878487858786878787888789879087918792879387948795879687978798879988008801880288038804880588068807880888098810881188128813881488158816881788188819882088218822882388248825882688278828882988308831883288338834883588368837883888398840884188428843884488458846884788488849885088518852885388548855885688578858885988608861886288638864886588668867886888698870887188728873887488758876887788788879888088818882888388848885888688878888888988908891889288938894889588968897889888998900890189028903890489058906890789088909891089118912891389148915891689178918891989208921892289238924892589268927892889298930893189328933893489358936893789388939894089418942894389448945894689478948894989508951895289538954895589568957895889598960896189628963896489658966896789688969897089718972897389748975897689778978897989808981898289838984898589868987898889898990899189928993899489958996899789988999900090019002900390049005900690079008900990109011901290139014901590169017901890199020902190229023902490259026902790289029903090319032903390349035903690379038903990409041904290439044904590469047904890499050905190529053905490559056905790589059906090619062906390649065906690679068906990709071907290739074907590769077907890799080908190829083908490859086908790889089909090919092909390949095909690979098909991009101910291039104910591069107910891099110911191129113911491159116911791189119912091219122912391249125912691279128912991309131913291339134913591369137913891399140914191429143914491459146914791489149915091519152915391549155915691579158915991609161916291639164916591669167916891699170917191729173917491759176917791789179918091819182918391849185918691879188918991909191919291939194919591969197919891999200920192029203920492059206920792089209921092119212921392149215921692179218921992209221922292239224922592269227922892299230923192329233923492359236923792389239924092419242924392449245924692479248924992509251925292539254925592569257925892599260926192629263926492659266926792689269927092719272927392749275927692779278927992809281928292839284928592869287928892899290929192929293929492959296929792989299930093019302930393049305930693079308930993109311931293139314931593169317931893199320932193229323932493259326932793289329933093319332933393349335933693379338933993409341934293439344934593469347934893499350935193529353935493559356935793589359936093619362936393649365936693679368936993709371937293739374937593769377937893799380938193829383938493859386938793889389939093919392939393949395939693979398939994009401940294039404940594069407940894099410941194129413941494159416941794189419942094219422942394249425942694279428942994309431943294339434943594369437943894399440944194429443944494459446944794489449945094519452945394549455945694579458945994609461946294639464946594669467946894699470947194729473947494759476947794789479948094819482948394849485948694879488948994909491949294939494949594969497949894999500950195029503950495059506950795089509951095119512951395149515951695179518951995209521952295239524952595269527952895299530953195329533953495359536953795389539954095419542954395449545954695479548954995509551955295539554955595569557955895599560956195629563956495659566956795689569957095719572957395749575957695779578957995809581958295839584958595869587958895899590959195929593959495959596959795989599960096019602960396049605960696079608960996109611961296139614961596169617961896199620962196229623962496259626962796289629963096319632963396349635963696379638963996409641964296439644964596469647964896499650965196529653965496559656965796589659966096619662966396649665966696679668966996709671967296739674967596769677967896799680968196829683968496859686968796889689969096919692969396949695969696979698969997009701970297039704970597069707970897099710971197129713971497159716971797189719972097219722972397249725972697279728972997309731973297339734973597369737973897399740974197429743974497459746974797489749975097519752975397549755975697579758975997609761976297639764976597669767976897699770977197729773977497759776977797789779978097819782978397849785978697879788978997909791979297939794979597969797979897999800980198029803980498059806980798089809981098119812981398149815981698179818981998209821982298239824982598269827982898299830983198329833983498359836983798389839984098419842984398449845984698479848984998509851985298539854985598569857985898599860986198629863986498659866986798689869987098719872987398749875987698779878987998809881988298839884988598869887988898899890989198929893989498959896989798989899990099019902990399049905990699079908990999109911991299139914991599169917991899199920992199229923992499259926992799289929993099319932993399349935993699379938993999409941994299439944994599469947994899499950995199529953995499559956995799589959996099619962996399649965996699679968996999709971997299739974997599769977997899799980998199829983998499859986998799889989999099919992999399949995999699979998999910000100011000210003100041000510006100071000810009100101001110012100131001410015100161001710018100191002010021100221002310024100251002610027100281002910030100311003210033100341003510036100371003810039100401004110042100431004410045100461004710048100491005010051100521005310054100551005610057100581005910060100611006210063100641006510066100671006810069100701007110072100731007410075100761007710078100791008010081100821008310084100851008610087100881008910090100911009210093100941009510096100971009810099101001010110102101031010410105101061010710108101091011010111101121011310114101151011610117101181011910120101211012210123101241012510126101271012810129101301013110132101331013410135101361013710138101391014010141101421014310144101451014610147101481014910150101511015210153101541015510156101571015810159101601016110162101631016410165101661016710168101691017010171101721017310174101751017610177101781017910180101811018210183101841018510186101871018810189101901019110192101931019410195101961019710198101991020010201102021020310204102051020610207102081020910210102111021210213102141021510216102171021810219102201022110222102231022410225102261022710228102291023010231102321023310234102351023610237102381023910240102411024210243102441024510246102471024810249102501025110252102531025410255102561025710258102591026010261102621026310264102651026610267102681026910270102711027210273102741027510276102771027810279102801028110282102831028410285102861028710288102891029010291102921029310294102951029610297102981029910300103011030210303103041030510306103071030810309103101031110312103131031410315103161031710318103191032010321103221032310324103251032610327103281032910330103311033210333103341033510336103371033810339103401034110342103431034410345103461034710348103491035010351103521035310354103551035610357103581035910360103611036210363103641036510366103671036810369103701037110372103731037410375103761037710378103791038010381103821038310384103851038610387103881038910390103911039210393103941039510396103971039810399104001040110402104031040410405104061040710408104091041010411104121041310414104151041610417104181041910420104211042210423104241042510426104271042810429104301043110432104331043410435104361043710438104391044010441104421044310444104451044610447104481044910450104511045210453104541045510456104571045810459104601046110462104631046410465104661046710468104691047010471104721047310474104751047610477104781047910480104811048210483104841048510486104871048810489104901049110492104931049410495104961049710498104991050010501105021050310504105051050610507105081050910510105111051210513105141051510516105171051810519105201052110522105231052410525105261052710528105291053010531105321053310534105351053610537105381053910540105411054210543105441054510546105471054810549105501055110552105531055410555105561055710558105591056010561105621056310564105651056610567105681056910570105711057210573105741057510576105771057810579105801058110582105831058410585105861058710588105891059010591105921059310594105951059610597105981059910600106011060210603106041060510606106071060810609106101061110612106131061410615106161061710618106191062010621106221062310624106251062610627106281062910630106311063210633106341063510636106371063810639106401064110642106431064410645106461064710648106491065010651106521065310654106551065610657106581065910660106611066210663106641066510666106671066810669106701067110672106731067410675106761067710678106791068010681106821068310684106851068610687106881068910690106911069210693106941069510696106971069810699107001070110702107031070410705107061070710708107091071010711107121071310714107151071610717107181071910720107211072210723107241072510726107271072810729107301073110732107331073410735107361073710738107391074010741107421074310744107451074610747107481074910750107511075210753107541075510756107571075810759107601076110762107631076410765107661076710768107691077010771107721077310774107751077610777107781077910780107811078210783107841078510786107871078810789107901079110792107931079410795107961079710798107991080010801108021080310804108051080610807108081080910810108111081210813108141081510816108171081810819108201082110822108231082410825108261082710828108291083010831108321083310834108351083610837108381083910840108411084210843108441084510846108471084810849108501085110852108531085410855108561085710858108591086010861108621086310864108651086610867108681086910870108711087210873108741087510876108771087810879108801088110882108831088410885108861088710888108891089010891108921089310894108951089610897108981089910900109011090210903109041090510906109071090810909109101091110912109131091410915109161091710918109191092010921109221092310924109251092610927109281092910930109311093210933109341093510936109371093810939109401094110942109431094410945109461094710948109491095010951109521095310954109551095610957109581095910960109611096210963109641096510966109671096810969109701097110972109731097410975109761097710978109791098010981109821098310984109851098610987109881098910990109911099210993109941099510996109971099810999110001100111002110031100411005110061100711008110091101011011110121101311014110151101611017110181101911020110211102211023110241102511026110271102811029110301103111032110331103411035110361103711038110391104011041110421104311044110451104611047110481104911050110511105211053110541105511056110571105811059110601106111062110631106411065110661106711068110691107011071110721107311074110751107611077110781107911080110811108211083110841108511086110871108811089110901109111092110931109411095110961109711098110991110011101111021110311104111051110611107111081110911110111111111211113111141111511116111171111811119111201112111122111231112411125111261112711128111291113011131111321113311134111351113611137111381113911140111411114211143111441114511146111471114811149111501115111152111531115411155111561115711158111591116011161111621116311164111651116611167111681116911170111711117211173111741117511176111771117811179111801118111182111831118411185111861118711188111891119011191111921119311194111951119611197111981119911200112011120211203112041120511206112071120811209112101121111212112131121411215112161121711218112191122011221112221122311224112251122611227112281122911230112311123211233112341123511236112371123811239112401124111242112431124411245112461124711248112491125011251112521125311254112551125611257112581125911260112611126211263112641126511266112671126811269112701127111272112731127411275112761127711278112791128011281112821128311284112851128611287112881128911290112911129211293112941129511296112971129811299113001130111302113031130411305113061130711308113091131011311113121131311314113151131611317113181131911320113211132211323113241132511326113271132811329113301133111332113331133411335113361133711338113391134011341113421134311344113451134611347113481134911350113511135211353113541135511356113571135811359113601136111362113631136411365113661136711368113691137011371113721137311374113751137611377113781137911380113811138211383113841138511386113871138811389113901139111392113931139411395113961139711398113991140011401114021140311404114051140611407114081140911410114111141211413114141141511416114171141811419114201142111422114231142411425114261142711428114291143011431114321143311434114351143611437114381143911440114411144211443114441144511446114471144811449114501145111452114531145411455114561145711458114591146011461114621146311464114651146611467114681146911470114711147211473114741147511476114771147811479114801148111482114831148411485114861148711488114891149011491114921149311494114951149611497114981149911500115011150211503115041150511506115071150811509115101151111512115131151411515115161151711518115191152011521115221152311524115251152611527115281152911530115311153211533115341153511536115371153811539115401154111542115431154411545115461154711548115491155011551115521155311554115551155611557115581155911560115611156211563115641156511566115671156811569115701157111572115731157411575115761157711578115791158011581115821158311584115851158611587115881158911590115911159211593115941159511596115971159811599116001160111602116031160411605116061160711608116091161011611116121161311614116151161611617116181161911620116211162211623116241162511626116271162811629116301163111632116331163411635116361163711638116391164011641116421164311644116451164611647116481164911650116511165211653116541165511656116571165811659116601166111662116631166411665116661166711668116691167011671116721167311674116751167611677116781167911680116811168211683116841168511686116871168811689116901169111692116931169411695116961169711698116991170011701117021170311704117051170611707117081170911710117111171211713117141171511716117171171811719117201172111722117231172411725117261172711728117291173011731117321173311734117351173611737117381173911740117411174211743117441174511746117471174811749117501175111752117531175411755117561175711758117591176011761117621176311764117651176611767117681176911770117711177211773117741177511776117771177811779117801178111782117831178411785117861178711788117891179011791117921179311794117951179611797117981179911800118011180211803118041180511806118071180811809118101181111812118131181411815118161181711818118191182011821118221182311824118251182611827118281182911830118311183211833118341183511836118371183811839118401184111842118431184411845118461184711848118491185011851118521185311854118551185611857118581185911860118611186211863118641186511866118671186811869118701187111872118731187411875118761187711878118791188011881118821188311884118851188611887118881188911890118911189211893118941189511896118971189811899119001190111902119031190411905119061190711908119091191011911119121191311914119151191611917119181191911920119211192211923119241192511926119271192811929119301193111932119331193411935119361193711938119391194011941119421194311944119451194611947119481194911950119511195211953119541195511956119571195811959119601196111962119631196411965119661196711968119691197011971119721197311974119751197611977119781197911980119811198211983119841198511986119871198811989119901199111992119931199411995119961199711998119991200012001120021200312004120051200612007120081200912010120111201212013120141201512016120171201812019120201202112022120231202412025120261202712028120291203012031120321203312034120351203612037120381203912040120411204212043120441204512046120471204812049120501205112052120531205412055120561205712058120591206012061120621206312064120651206612067120681206912070120711207212073120741207512076120771207812079120801208112082120831208412085120861208712088120891209012091120921209312094120951209612097120981209912100121011210212103121041210512106121071210812109121101211112112121131211412115121161211712118121191212012121121221212312124121251212612127121281212912130121311213212133121341213512136121371213812139121401214112142121431214412145121461214712148121491215012151121521215312154121551215612157121581215912160121611216212163121641216512166121671216812169121701217112172121731217412175121761217712178121791218012181121821218312184121851218612187121881218912190121911219212193121941219512196121971219812199122001220112202122031220412205122061220712208122091221012211122121221312214122151221612217122181221912220122211222212223122241222512226122271222812229122301223112232122331223412235122361223712238122391224012241122421224312244122451224612247122481224912250122511225212253122541225512256122571225812259122601226112262122631226412265122661226712268122691227012271122721227312274122751227612277122781227912280122811228212283122841228512286122871228812289122901229112292122931229412295122961229712298122991230012301123021230312304123051230612307123081230912310123111231212313123141231512316123171231812319123201232112322123231232412325123261232712328123291233012331123321233312334123351233612337123381233912340123411234212343123441234512346123471234812349123501235112352123531235412355123561235712358123591236012361123621236312364123651236612367123681236912370123711237212373123741237512376123771237812379123801238112382123831238412385123861238712388123891239012391123921239312394123951239612397123981239912400124011240212403124041240512406124071240812409124101241112412124131241412415124161241712418124191242012421124221242312424124251242612427124281242912430124311243212433124341243512436124371243812439124401244112442124431244412445124461244712448124491245012451124521245312454124551245612457124581245912460124611246212463124641246512466124671246812469124701247112472124731247412475124761247712478124791248012481124821248312484124851248612487124881248912490124911249212493124941249512496124971249812499125001250112502125031250412505125061250712508125091251012511125121251312514125151251612517125181251912520125211252212523125241252512526125271252812529125301253112532125331253412535125361253712538125391254012541125421254312544125451254612547125481254912550125511255212553125541255512556125571255812559125601256112562125631256412565125661256712568125691257012571125721257312574125751257612577125781257912580125811258212583125841258512586125871258812589125901259112592125931259412595125961259712598125991260012601126021260312604126051260612607126081260912610126111261212613126141261512616126171261812619126201262112622126231262412625126261262712628126291263012631126321263312634126351263612637126381263912640126411264212643126441264512646126471264812649126501265112652126531265412655126561265712658126591266012661126621266312664126651266612667126681266912670126711267212673126741267512676126771267812679126801268112682126831268412685126861268712688126891269012691126921269312694126951269612697126981269912700127011270212703127041270512706127071270812709127101271112712127131271412715127161271712718127191272012721127221272312724127251272612727127281272912730127311273212733127341273512736127371273812739127401274112742127431274412745127461274712748127491275012751127521275312754127551275612757127581275912760127611276212763127641276512766127671276812769127701277112772127731277412775127761277712778127791278012781127821278312784127851278612787127881278912790127911279212793127941279512796127971279812799128001280112802128031280412805128061280712808128091281012811128121281312814128151281612817128181281912820128211282212823128241282512826128271282812829128301283112832128331283412835128361283712838128391284012841128421284312844128451284612847128481284912850128511285212853128541285512856128571285812859128601286112862128631286412865128661286712868128691287012871128721287312874128751287612877128781287912880128811288212883128841288512886128871288812889128901289112892128931289412895128961289712898128991290012901129021290312904129051290612907129081290912910129111291212913129141291512916129171291812919129201292112922129231292412925129261292712928129291293012931129321293312934129351293612937129381293912940129411294212943129441294512946129471294812949129501295112952129531295412955129561295712958129591296012961129621296312964129651296612967129681296912970129711297212973129741297512976129771297812979129801298112982129831298412985129861298712988129891299012991129921299312994129951299612997129981299913000130011300213003130041300513006130071300813009130101301113012130131301413015130161301713018130191302013021130221302313024130251302613027130281302913030130311303213033130341303513036130371303813039130401304113042130431304413045130461304713048130491305013051130521305313054130551305613057130581305913060130611306213063130641306513066130671306813069130701307113072130731307413075130761307713078130791308013081130821308313084130851308613087130881308913090130911309213093130941309513096130971309813099131001310113102131031310413105131061310713108131091311013111131121311313114131151311613117131181311913120131211312213123131241312513126131271312813129131301313113132131331313413135131361313713138131391314013141131421314313144131451314613147131481314913150131511315213153131541315513156131571315813159131601316113162131631316413165131661316713168131691317013171131721317313174131751317613177131781317913180131811318213183131841318513186131871318813189131901319113192131931319413195131961319713198131991320013201132021320313204132051320613207132081320913210132111321213213132141321513216132171321813219132201322113222132231322413225132261322713228132291323013231132321323313234132351323613237132381323913240132411324213243132441324513246132471324813249132501325113252132531325413255132561325713258132591326013261132621326313264132651326613267132681326913270132711327213273132741327513276132771327813279132801328113282132831328413285132861328713288132891329013291132921329313294132951329613297132981329913300133011330213303133041330513306133071330813309133101331113312133131331413315133161331713318133191332013321133221332313324133251332613327133281332913330133311333213333133341333513336133371333813339133401334113342133431334413345133461334713348133491335013351133521335313354133551335613357133581335913360133611336213363133641336513366133671336813369133701337113372133731337413375133761337713378133791338013381133821338313384133851338613387133881338913390133911339213393133941339513396133971339813399134001340113402134031340413405134061340713408134091341013411134121341313414134151341613417134181341913420134211342213423134241342513426134271342813429134301343113432134331343413435134361343713438134391344013441134421344313444134451344613447134481344913450134511345213453134541345513456134571345813459134601346113462134631346413465134661346713468134691347013471134721347313474134751347613477134781347913480134811348213483134841348513486134871348813489134901349113492134931349413495134961349713498134991350013501135021350313504135051350613507135081350913510135111351213513135141351513516135171351813519135201352113522135231352413525135261352713528135291353013531135321353313534135351353613537135381353913540135411354213543135441354513546135471354813549135501355113552135531355413555135561355713558135591356013561135621356313564135651356613567135681356913570135711357213573135741357513576135771357813579135801358113582135831358413585135861358713588135891359013591135921359313594135951359613597135981359913600136011360213603136041360513606136071360813609136101361113612136131361413615136161361713618136191362013621136221362313624136251362613627136281362913630136311363213633136341363513636136371363813639136401364113642136431364413645136461364713648136491365013651136521365313654136551365613657136581365913660136611366213663136641366513666136671366813669136701367113672136731367413675136761367713678136791368013681136821368313684136851368613687136881368913690136911369213693136941369513696136971369813699137001370113702137031370413705137061370713708137091371013711137121371313714137151371613717137181371913720137211372213723137241372513726137271372813729137301373113732137331373413735137361373713738137391374013741137421374313744137451374613747137481374913750137511375213753137541375513756137571375813759137601376113762137631376413765137661376713768137691377013771137721377313774137751377613777137781377913780137811378213783137841378513786137871378813789137901379113792137931379413795137961379713798137991380013801138021380313804138051380613807138081380913810138111381213813138141381513816138171381813819138201382113822138231382413825138261382713828138291383013831138321383313834138351383613837138381383913840138411384213843138441384513846138471384813849138501385113852138531385413855138561385713858138591386013861138621386313864138651386613867138681386913870138711387213873138741387513876138771387813879138801388113882138831388413885138861388713888138891389013891138921389313894138951389613897138981389913900139011390213903139041390513906139071390813909139101391113912139131391413915139161391713918139191392013921139221392313924139251392613927139281392913930139311393213933139341393513936139371393813939139401394113942139431394413945139461394713948139491395013951139521395313954139551395613957139581395913960139611396213963139641396513966139671396813969139701397113972139731397413975139761397713978139791398013981139821398313984139851398613987139881398913990139911399213993139941399513996139971399813999140001400114002140031400414005140061400714008140091401014011140121401314014140151401614017140181401914020140211402214023140241402514026140271402814029140301403114032140331403414035140361403714038140391404014041140421404314044140451404614047140481404914050140511405214053140541405514056140571405814059140601406114062140631406414065140661406714068140691407014071140721407314074140751407614077140781407914080140811408214083140841408514086140871408814089140901409114092140931409414095140961409714098140991410014101141021410314104141051410614107141081410914110141111411214113141141411514116141171411814119141201412114122141231412414125141261412714128141291413014131141321413314134141351413614137141381413914140141411414214143141441414514146141471414814149141501415114152141531415414155141561415714158141591416014161141621416314164141651416614167141681416914170141711417214173141741417514176141771417814179141801418114182141831418414185141861418714188141891419014191141921419314194141951419614197141981419914200142011420214203142041420514206142071420814209142101421114212142131421414215142161421714218142191422014221142221422314224142251422614227142281422914230142311423214233142341423514236142371423814239142401424114242142431424414245142461424714248142491425014251142521425314254142551425614257142581425914260142611426214263142641426514266142671426814269142701427114272142731427414275142761427714278142791428014281142821428314284142851428614287142881428914290142911429214293142941429514296142971429814299143001430114302143031430414305143061430714308143091431014311143121431314314143151431614317143181431914320143211432214323143241432514326143271432814329143301433114332143331433414335143361433714338143391434014341143421434314344143451434614347143481434914350143511435214353143541435514356143571435814359143601436114362143631436414365143661436714368143691437014371143721437314374143751437614377143781437914380143811438214383143841438514386143871438814389143901439114392143931439414395143961439714398143991440014401144021440314404144051440614407144081440914410144111441214413144141441514416144171441814419144201442114422144231442414425144261442714428144291443014431144321443314434144351443614437144381443914440144411444214443144441444514446144471444814449144501445114452144531445414455144561445714458144591446014461144621446314464144651446614467144681446914470144711447214473144741447514476144771447814479144801448114482144831448414485144861448714488144891449014491144921449314494144951449614497144981449914500145011450214503145041450514506145071450814509145101451114512145131451414515145161451714518145191452014521145221452314524145251452614527145281452914530145311453214533145341453514536145371453814539145401454114542145431454414545145461454714548145491455014551145521455314554145551455614557145581455914560145611456214563145641456514566145671456814569145701457114572145731457414575145761457714578145791458014581145821458314584145851458614587145881458914590145911459214593145941459514596145971459814599146001460114602146031460414605146061460714608146091461014611146121461314614146151461614617146181461914620146211462214623146241462514626146271462814629146301463114632146331463414635146361463714638146391464014641146421464314644146451464614647146481464914650146511465214653146541465514656146571465814659146601466114662146631466414665146661466714668146691467014671146721467314674146751467614677146781467914680146811468214683146841468514686146871468814689146901469114692146931469414695146961469714698146991470014701147021470314704147051470614707147081470914710147111471214713147141471514716147171471814719147201472114722147231472414725147261472714728147291473014731147321473314734147351473614737147381473914740147411474214743147441474514746147471474814749147501475114752147531475414755147561475714758147591476014761147621476314764147651476614767147681476914770147711477214773147741477514776147771477814779147801478114782147831478414785147861478714788147891479014791147921479314794147951479614797147981479914800148011480214803148041480514806148071480814809148101481114812148131481414815148161481714818148191482014821148221482314824148251482614827148281482914830148311483214833148341483514836148371483814839148401484114842148431484414845148461484714848148491485014851148521485314854148551485614857148581485914860148611486214863148641486514866148671486814869148701487114872148731487414875148761487714878148791488014881148821488314884148851488614887148881488914890148911489214893148941489514896148971489814899149001490114902149031490414905149061490714908149091491014911149121491314914149151491614917149181491914920149211492214923149241492514926149271492814929149301493114932149331493414935149361493714938149391494014941149421494314944149451494614947149481494914950149511495214953149541495514956149571495814959149601496114962149631496414965149661496714968149691497014971149721497314974149751497614977149781497914980149811498214983149841498514986149871498814989149901499114992149931499414995149961499714998149991500015001150021500315004150051500615007150081500915010150111501215013150141501515016150171501815019150201502115022150231502415025150261502715028150291503015031150321503315034150351503615037150381503915040150411504215043150441504515046150471504815049150501505115052150531505415055150561505715058150591506015061150621506315064150651506615067150681506915070150711507215073150741507515076150771507815079150801508115082150831508415085150861508715088150891509015091150921509315094150951509615097150981509915100151011510215103151041510515106151071510815109151101511115112151131511415115151161511715118151191512015121151221512315124151251512615127151281512915130151311513215133151341513515136151371513815139151401514115142151431514415145151461514715148151491515015151151521515315154151551515615157151581515915160151611516215163151641516515166151671516815169151701517115172151731517415175151761517715178151791518015181151821518315184151851518615187151881518915190151911519215193151941519515196151971519815199152001520115202152031520415205152061520715208152091521015211152121521315214152151521615217152181521915220152211522215223152241522515226152271522815229152301523115232152331523415235152361523715238152391524015241152421524315244152451524615247152481524915250152511525215253152541525515256152571525815259152601526115262152631526415265152661526715268152691527015271152721527315274152751527615277152781527915280152811528215283152841528515286152871528815289152901529115292152931529415295152961529715298152991530015301153021530315304153051530615307153081530915310153111531215313153141531515316153171531815319153201532115322153231532415325153261532715328153291533015331153321533315334153351533615337153381533915340153411534215343153441534515346153471534815349153501535115352153531535415355153561535715358153591536015361153621536315364153651536615367
  1. The Project Gutenberg EBook of Creative Evolution, by Henri Bergson
  2. This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
  3. almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
  4. re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
  5. with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
  6. Title: Creative Evolution
  7. Author: Henri Bergson
  8. Translator: Arthur Mitchell
  9. Release Date: August 1, 2008 [EBook #26163]
  10. Language: English
  11. *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CREATIVE EVOLUTION ***
  12. Produced by Rick Niles, Graeme Mackreth and the Online
  13. Distributed Proofreading Team at http://www.pgdp.net
  14. CREATIVE EVOLUTION
  15. BY HENRI BERGSON
  16. MEMBER OF THE INSTITUTE PROFESSOR AT THE COLLEGE DE FRANCE
  17. AUTHORIZED TRANSLATION BY ARTHUR MITCHELL, PH.D.
  18. NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1911
  19. COPYRIGHT, 1911,
  20. by
  21. HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
  22. CAMELOT PRESS, 18-20 OAK STREET, NEW YORK
  23. TRANSLATOR'S NOTE
  24. In the writing of this English translation of Professor Bergson's most
  25. important work, I was helped by the friendly interest of Professor
  26. William James, to whom I owe the illumination of much that was dark to
  27. me as well as the happy rendering of certain words and phrases for which
  28. an English equivalent was difficult to find. His sympathetic
  29. appreciation of Professor Bergson's thought is well known, and he has
  30. expressed his admiration for it in one of the chapters of _A Pluralistic
  31. Universe_. It was his intention, had he lived to see the completion of
  32. this translation, himself to introduce it to English readers in a
  33. prefatory note.
  34. I wish to thank my friend, Dr. George Clarke Cox, for many valuable
  35. suggestions.
  36. I have endeavored to follow the text as closely as possible, and at the
  37. same time to preserve the living union of diction and thought. Professor
  38. Bergson has himself carefully revised the whole work. We both of us wish
  39. to acknowledge the great assistance of Miss Millicent Murby. She has
  40. kindly studied the translation phrase by phrase, weighing each word, and
  41. her revision has resulted in many improvements.
  42. But above all we must express our acknowledgment to Mr. H. Wildon Carr,
  43. the Honorary Secretary of the Aristotelian Society of London, and the
  44. writer of several studies of "Evolution Creatrice."[1] We asked him to
  45. be kind enough to revise the proofs of our work. He has done much more
  46. than revise them: they have come from his hands with his personal mark
  47. in many places. We cannot express all that the present work owes to him.
  48. ARTHUR MITCHELL
  49. HARVARD UNIVERSITY
  50. CONTENTS
  51. PAGE
  52. INTRODUCTION ix
  53. CHAPTER I
  54. THE EVOLUTION OF LIFE--MECHANISM AND TELEOLOGY
  55. Of duration in general--Unorganized bodies and abstract
  56. time--Organized bodies and real duration--Individuality and
  57. the process of growing old 1
  58. Of transformism and the different ways of interpreting it--Radical
  59. mechanism and real duration: the relation of biology to
  60. physics and chemistry--Radical finalism and real duration:
  61. the relation of biology to philosophy 23
  62. The quest of a criterion--Examination of the various theories
  63. with regard to a particular example--Darwin and insensible
  64. variation--De Vries and sudden variation--Eimer and
  65. orthogenesis--Neo-Lamarckism and the hereditability of
  66. acquired characters 59
  67. Result of the inquiry--The _vital impetus_ 87
  68. CHAPTER II
  69. THE DIVERGENT DIRECTIONS OF THE EVOLUTION OF
  70. LIFE--TORPOR, INTELLIGENCE, INSTINCT
  71. General idea of the evolutionary process--Growth--Divergent
  72. and complementary tendencies--The meaning of progress and of
  73. adaptation 98
  74. The relation of the animal to the plant--General tendency of
  75. animal life--The development of animal life 105
  76. The main directions of the evolution of life: torpor, intelligence,
  77. instinct 135
  78. The nature of the intellect 151
  79. The nature of instinct 165
  80. Life and consciousness--The apparent place of man in nature 176
  81. CHAPTER III
  82. ON THE MEANING OF LIFE--THE ORDER OF NATURE
  83. AND THE FORM OF INTELLIGENCE
  84. Relation of the problem of life to the problem of knowledge--The
  85. method of philosophy--Apparent vicious circle of the method
  86. proposed--Real vicious circle of the opposite method 186
  87. Simultaneous genesis of matter and intelligence--Geometry
  88. inherent in matter--Geometrical tendency of the intellect--Geometry
  89. and deduction--Geometry and induction--Physical laws 199
  90. Sketch of a theory of knowledge based on the analysis of the
  91. idea of Disorder--Two opposed forms of order: the problem
  92. of _genera_ and the problem of _laws_--The idea of
  93. "disorder" an oscillation of the intellect between the two
  94. kinds of order 220
  95. Creation and evolution--Ideal genesis of matter--The origin
  96. and function of life--The essential and the accidental in the
  97. vital process and in the evolutionary movement--Mankind--The
  98. life of the body and the life of the spirit 236
  99. CHAPTER IV
  100. THE CINEMATOGRAPHICAL MECHANISM OF THOUGHT AND THE
  101. MECHANISTIC ILLUSION--A GLANCE AT THE HISTORY OF
  102. SYSTEMS--REAL BECOMING AND FALSE EVOLUTIONISM
  103. Sketch of a criticism of philosophical systems, based on the
  104. analysis of the idea of Immutability and of the idea of
  105. "Nothing"--Relation of metaphysical problems to the idea
  106. of "Nothing"--Real meaning of this idea 272
  107. Form and Becoming 298
  108. The philosophy of Forms and its conception of Becoming--Plato
  109. and Aristotle--The natural trend of the intellect 304
  110. Becoming in modern science: two views of Time 329
  111. The metaphysical interpretation of modern science: Descartes,
  112. Spinoza, Leibniz 345
  113. The Criticism of Kant 356
  114. The evolutionism of Spencer 363
  115. INDEX 371
  116. INTRODUCTION
  117. The history of the evolution of life, incomplete as it yet is, already
  118. reveals to us how the intellect has been formed, by an uninterrupted
  119. progress, along a line which ascends through the vertebrate series up to
  120. man. It shows us in the faculty of understanding an appendage of the
  121. faculty of acting, a more and more precise, more and more complex and
  122. supple adaptation of the consciousness of living beings to the
  123. conditions of existence that are made for them. Hence should result this
  124. consequence that our intellect, in the narrow sense of the word, is
  125. intended to secure the perfect fitting of our body to its environment,
  126. to represent the relations of external things among themselves--in
  127. short, to think matter. Such will indeed be one of the conclusions of
  128. the present essay. We shall see that the human intellect feels at home
  129. among inanimate objects, more especially among solids, where our action
  130. finds its fulcrum and our industry its tools; that our concepts have
  131. been formed on the model of solids; that our logic is, pre-eminently,
  132. the logic of solids; that, consequently, our intellect triumphs in
  133. geometry, wherein is revealed the kinship of logical thought with
  134. unorganized matter, and where the intellect has only to follow its
  135. natural movement, after the lightest possible contact with experience,
  136. in order to go from discovery to discovery, sure that experience is
  137. following behind it and will justify it invariably.
  138. But from this it must also follow that our thought, in its purely
  139. logical form, is incapable of presenting the true nature of life, the
  140. full meaning of the evolutionary movement. Created by life, in definite
  141. circumstances, to act on definite things, how can it embrace life, of
  142. which it is only an emanation or an aspect? Deposited by the
  143. evolutionary movement in the course of its way, how can it be applied to
  144. the evolutionary movement itself? As well contend that the part is equal
  145. to the whole, that the effect can reabsorb its cause, or that the pebble
  146. left on the beach displays the form of the wave that brought it there.
  147. In fact, we do indeed feel that not one of the categories of our
  148. thought--unity, multiplicity, mechanical causality, intelligent
  149. finality, etc.--applies exactly to the things of life: who can say where
  150. individuality begins and ends, whether the living being is one or many,
  151. whether it is the cells which associate themselves into the organism or
  152. the organism which dissociates itself into cells? In vain we force the
  153. living into this or that one of our molds. All the molds crack. They are
  154. too narrow, above all too rigid, for what we try to put into them. Our
  155. reasoning, so sure of itself among things inert, feels ill at ease on
  156. this new ground. It would be difficult to cite a biological discovery
  157. due to pure reasoning. And most often, when experience has finally shown
  158. us how life goes to work to obtain a certain result, we find its way of
  159. working is just that of which we should never have thought.
  160. Yet evolutionist philosophy does not hesitate to extend to the things of
  161. life the same methods of explanation which have succeeded in the case of
  162. unorganized matter. It begins by showing us in the intellect a local
  163. effect of evolution, a flame, perhaps accidental, which lights up the
  164. coming and going of living beings in the narrow passage open to their
  165. action; and lo! forgetting what it has just told us, it makes of this
  166. lantern glimmering in a tunnel a Sun which can illuminate the world.
  167. Boldly it proceeds, with the powers of conceptual thought alone, to the
  168. ideal reconstruction of all things, even of life. True, it hurtles in
  169. its course against such formidable difficulties, it sees its logic end
  170. in such strange contradictions, that it very speedily renounces its
  171. first ambition. "It is no longer reality itself," it says, "that it will
  172. reconstruct, but only an imitation of the real, or rather a symbolical
  173. image; the essence of things escapes us, and will escape us always; we
  174. move among relations; the absolute is not in our province; we are
  175. brought to a stand before the Unknowable."--But for the human intellect,
  176. after too much pride, this is really an excess of humility. If the
  177. intellectual form of the living being has been gradually modeled on the
  178. reciprocal actions and reactions of certain bodies and their material
  179. environment, how should it not reveal to us something of the very
  180. essence of which these bodies are made? Action cannot move in the
  181. unreal. A mind born to speculate or to dream, I admit, might remain
  182. outside reality, might deform or transform the real, perhaps even create
  183. it--as we create the figures of men and animals that our imagination
  184. cuts out of the passing cloud. But an intellect bent upon the act to be
  185. performed and the reaction to follow, feeling its object so as to get
  186. its mobile impression at every instant, is an intellect that touches
  187. something of the absolute. Would the idea ever have occurred to us to
  188. doubt this absolute value of our knowledge if philosophy had not shown
  189. us what contradictions our speculation meets, what dead-locks it ends
  190. in? But these difficulties and contradictions all arise from trying to
  191. apply the usual forms of our thought to objects with which our industry
  192. has nothing to do, and for which, therefore, our molds are not made.
  193. Intellectual knowledge, in so far as it relates to a certain aspect of
  194. inert matter, ought, on the contrary, to give us a faithful imprint of
  195. it, having been stereotyped on this particular object. It becomes
  196. relative only if it claims, such as it is, to present to us life--that
  197. is to say, the maker of the stereotype-plate.
  198. * * * * *
  199. Must we then give up fathoming the depths of life? Must we keep to that
  200. mechanistic idea of it which the understanding will always give us--an
  201. idea necessarily artificial and symbolical, since it makes the total
  202. activity of life shrink to the form of a certain human activity which is
  203. only a partial and local manifestation of life, a result or by-product
  204. of the vital process? We should have to do so, indeed, if life had
  205. employed all the psychical potentialities it possesses in producing pure
  206. understandings--that is to say, in making geometricians. But the line of
  207. evolution that ends in man is not the only one. On other paths,
  208. divergent from it, other forms of consciousness have been developed,
  209. which have not been able to free themselves from external constraints or
  210. to regain control over themselves, as the human intellect has done, but
  211. which, none the less, also express something that is immanent and
  212. essential in the evolutionary movement. Suppose these other forms of
  213. consciousness brought together and amalgamated with intellect: would not
  214. the result be a consciousness as wide as life? And such a consciousness,
  215. turning around suddenly against the push of life which it feels behind,
  216. would have a vision of life complete--would it not?--even though the
  217. vision were fleeting.
  218. It will be said that, even so, we do not transcend our intellect, for it
  219. is still with our intellect, and through our intellect, that we see the
  220. other forms of consciousness. And this would be right if we were pure
  221. intellects, if there did not remain, around our conceptual and logical
  222. thought, a vague nebulosity, made of the very substance out of which has
  223. been formed the luminous nucleus that we call the intellect. Therein
  224. reside certain powers that are complementary to the understanding,
  225. powers of which we have only an indistinct feeling when we remain shut
  226. up in ourselves, but which will become clear and distinct when they
  227. perceive themselves at work, so to speak, in the evolution of nature.
  228. They will thus learn what sort of effort they must make to be
  229. intensified and expanded in the very direction of life.
  230. * * * * *
  231. This amounts to saying that _theory of knowledge_ and _theory of life_
  232. seem to us inseparable. A theory of life that is not accompanied by a
  233. criticism of knowledge is obliged to accept, as they stand, the concepts
  234. which the understanding puts at its disposal: it can but enclose the
  235. facts, willing or not, in pre-existing frames which it regards as
  236. ultimate. It thus obtains a symbolism which is convenient, perhaps even
  237. necessary to positive science, but not a direct vision of its object. On
  238. the other hand, a theory of knowledge which does not replace the
  239. intellect in the general evolution of life will teach us neither how the
  240. frames of knowledge have been constructed nor how we can enlarge or go
  241. beyond them. It is necessary that these two inquiries, theory of
  242. knowledge and theory of life, should join each other, and, by a circular
  243. process, push each other on unceasingly.
  244. Together, they may solve by a method more sure, brought nearer to
  245. experience, the great problems that philosophy poses. For, if they
  246. should succeed in their common enterprise, they would show us the
  247. formation of the intellect, and thereby the genesis of that matter of
  248. which our intellect traces the general configuration. They would dig to
  249. the very root of nature and of mind. They would substitute for the false
  250. evolutionism of Spencer--which consists in cutting up present reality,
  251. already evolved, into little bits no less evolved, and then recomposing
  252. it with these fragments, thus positing in advance everything that is to
  253. be explained--a true evolutionism, in which reality would be followed in
  254. its generation and its growth.
  255. But a philosophy of this kind will not be made in a day. Unlike the
  256. philosophical systems properly so called, each of which was the
  257. individual work of a man of genius and sprang up as a whole, to be taken
  258. or left, it will only be built up by the collective and progressive
  259. effort of many thinkers, of many observers also, completing, correcting
  260. and improving one another. So the present essay does not aim at
  261. resolving at once the greatest problems. It simply desires to define the
  262. method and to permit a glimpse, on some essential points, of the
  263. possibility of its application.
  264. Its plan is traced by the subject itself. In the first chapter, we try
  265. on the evolutionary progress the two ready-made garments that our
  266. understanding puts at our disposal, mechanism and finality;[2] we show
  267. that they do not fit, neither the one nor the other, but that one of
  268. them might be recut and resewn, and in this new form fit less badly than
  269. the other. In order to transcend the point of view of the understanding,
  270. we try, in our second chapter, to reconstruct the main lines of
  271. evolution along which life has traveled by the side of that which has
  272. led to the human intellect. The intellect is thus brought back to its
  273. generating cause, which we then have to grasp in itself and follow in
  274. its movement. It is an effort of this kind that we attempt--incompletely
  275. indeed--in our third chapter. A fourth and last part is meant to show
  276. how our understanding itself, by submitting to a certain discipline,
  277. might prepare a philosophy which transcends it. For that, a glance over
  278. the history of systems became necessary, together with an analysis of
  279. the two great illusions to which, as soon as it speculates on reality in
  280. general, the human understanding is exposed.
  281. FOOTNOTES:
  282. [Footnote 1: _Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society_, vols. ix. and
  283. x., and _Hibbert Journal_ for July, 1910.]
  284. [Footnote 2: The idea of regarding life as transcending teleology as
  285. well as mechanism is far from being a new idea. Notably in three
  286. articles by Ch. Dunan on "Le problème de la vie" (_Revue philosophique_,
  287. 1892) it is profoundly treated. In the development of this idea, we
  288. agree with Ch. Dunan on more than one point. But the views we are
  289. presenting on this matter, as on the questions attaching to it, are
  290. those that we expressed long ago in our _Essai sur les données
  291. immédiates de la conscience_ (Paris, 1889). One of the principal objects
  292. of that essay was, in fact, to show that the psychical life is neither
  293. unity nor multiplicity, that it transcends both the _mechanical_ and the
  294. _intellectual_, mechanism and finalism having meaning only where there
  295. is "distinct multiplicity," "spatiality," and consequently assemblage of
  296. pre-existing parts: "real duration" signifies both undivided continuity
  297. and creation. In the present work we apply these same ideas to life in
  298. general, regarded, moreover, itself from the psychological point of
  299. view.]
  300. CHAPTER I
  301. THE EVOLUTION OF LIFE--MECHANISM AND TELEOLOGY
  302. The existence of which we are most assured and which we know best is
  303. unquestionably our own, for of every other object we have notions which
  304. may be considered external and superficial, whereas, of ourselves, our
  305. perception is internal and profound. What, then, do we find? In this
  306. privileged case, what is the precise meaning of the word "exist"? Let us
  307. recall here briefly the conclusions of an earlier work.
  308. I find, first of all, that I pass from state to state. I am warm or
  309. cold, I am merry or sad, I work or I do nothing, I look at what is
  310. around me or I think of something else. Sensations, feelings, volitions,
  311. ideas--such are the changes into which my existence is divided and which
  312. color it in turns. I change, then, without ceasing. But this is not
  313. saying enough. Change is far more radical than we are at first inclined
  314. to suppose.
  315. For I speak of each of my states as if it formed a block and were a
  316. separate whole. I say indeed that I change, but the change seems to me
  317. to reside in the passage from one state to the next: of each state,
  318. taken separately, I am apt to think that it remains the same during all
  319. the time that it prevails. Nevertheless, a slight effort of attention
  320. would reveal to me that there is no feeling, no idea, no volition which
  321. is not undergoing change every moment: if a mental state ceased to vary,
  322. its duration would cease to flow. Let us take the most stable of
  323. internal states, the visual perception of a motionless external object.
  324. The object may remain the same, I may look at it from the same side, at
  325. the same angle, in the same light; nevertheless the vision I now have of
  326. it differs from that which I have just had, even if only because the one
  327. is an instant older than the other. My memory is there, which conveys
  328. something of the past into the present. My mental state, as it advances
  329. on the road of time, is continually swelling with the duration which it
  330. accumulates: it goes on increasing--rolling upon itself, as a snowball
  331. on the snow. Still more is this the case with states more deeply
  332. internal, such as sensations, feelings, desires, etc., which do not
  333. correspond, like a simple visual perception, to an unvarying external
  334. object. But it is expedient to disregard this uninterrupted change, and
  335. to notice it only when it becomes sufficient to impress a new attitude
  336. on the body, a new direction on the attention. Then, and then only, we
  337. find that our state has changed. The truth is that we change without
  338. ceasing, and that the state itself is nothing but change.
  339. This amounts to saying that there is no essential difference between
  340. passing from one state to another and persisting in the same state. If
  341. the state which "remains the same" is more varied than we think, on the
  342. other hand the passing from one state to another resembles, more than we
  343. imagine, a single state being prolonged; the transition is continuous.
  344. But, just because we close our eyes to the unceasing variation of every
  345. psychical state, we are obliged, when the change has become so
  346. considerable as to force itself on our attention, to speak as if a new
  347. state were placed alongside the previous one. Of this new state we
  348. assume that it remains unvarying in its turn, and so on endlessly. The
  349. apparent discontinuity of the psychical life is then due to our
  350. attention being fixed on it by a series of separate acts: actually there
  351. is only a gentle slope; but in following the broken line of our acts of
  352. attention, we think we perceive separate steps. True, our psychic life
  353. is full of the unforeseen. A thousand incidents arise, which seem to be
  354. cut off from those which precede them, and to be disconnected from those
  355. which follow. Discontinuous though they appear, however, in point of
  356. fact they stand out against the continuity of a background on which they
  357. are designed, and to which indeed they owe the intervals that separate
  358. them; they are the beats of the drum which break forth here and there in
  359. the symphony. Our attention fixes on them because they interest it more,
  360. but each of them is borne by the fluid mass of our whole psychical
  361. existence. Each is only the best illuminated point of a moving zone
  362. which comprises all that we feel or think or will--all, in short, that
  363. we are at any given moment. It is this entire zone which in reality
  364. makes up our state. Now, states thus defined cannot be regarded as
  365. distinct elements. They continue each other in an endless flow.
  366. But, as our attention has distinguished and separated them artificially,
  367. it is obliged next to reunite them by an artificial bond. It imagines,
  368. therefore, a formless _ego_, indifferent and unchangeable, on which it
  369. threads the psychic states which it has set up as independent entities.
  370. Instead of a flux of fleeting shades merging into each other, it
  371. perceives distinct and, so to speak, _solid_ colors, set side by side
  372. like the beads of a necklace; it must perforce then suppose a thread,
  373. also itself solid, to hold the beads together. But if this colorless
  374. substratum is perpetually colored by that which covers it, it is for us,
  375. in its indeterminateness, as if it did not exist, since we only perceive
  376. what is colored, or, in other words, psychic states. As a matter of
  377. fact, this substratum has no reality; it is merely a symbol intended to
  378. recall unceasingly to our consciousness the artificial character of the
  379. process by which the attention places clean-cut states side by side,
  380. where actually there is a continuity which unfolds. If our existence
  381. were composed of separate states with an impassive ego to unite them,
  382. for us there would be no duration. For an ego which does not change does
  383. not _endure_, and a psychic state which remains the same so long as it
  384. is not replaced by the following state does not _endure_ either. Vain,
  385. therefore, is the attempt to range such states beside each other on the
  386. ego supposed to sustain them: never can these solids strung upon a solid
  387. make up that duration which flows. What we actually obtain in this way
  388. is an artificial imitation of the internal life, a static equivalent
  389. which will lend itself better to the requirements of logic and language,
  390. just because we have eliminated from it the element of real time. But,
  391. as regards the psychical life unfolding beneath the symbols which
  392. conceal it, we readily perceive that time is just the stuff it is made
  393. of.
  394. There is, moreover, no stuff more resistant nor more substantial. For
  395. our duration is not merely one instant replacing another; if it were,
  396. there would never be anything but the present--no prolonging of the past
  397. into the actual, no evolution, no concrete duration. Duration is the
  398. continuous progress of the past which gnaws into the future and which
  399. swells as it advances. And as the past grows without ceasing, so also
  400. there is no limit to its preservation. Memory, as we have tried to
  401. prove,[3] is not a faculty of putting away recollections in a drawer, or
  402. of inscribing them in a register. There is no register, no drawer; there
  403. is not even, properly speaking, a faculty, for a faculty works
  404. intermittently, when it will or when it can, whilst the piling up of the
  405. past upon the past goes on without relaxation. In reality, the past is
  406. preserved by itself, automatically. In its entirety, probably, it
  407. follows us at every instant; all that we have felt, thought and willed
  408. from our earliest infancy is there, leaning over the present which is
  409. about to join it, pressing against the portals of consciousness that
  410. would fain leave it outside. The cerebral mechanism is arranged just so
  411. as to drive back into the unconscious almost the whole of this past, and
  412. to admit beyond the threshold only that which can cast light on the
  413. present situation or further the action now being prepared--in short,
  414. only that which can give _useful_ work. At the most, a few superfluous
  415. recollections may succeed in smuggling themselves through the half-open
  416. door. These memories, messengers from the unconscious, remind us of what
  417. we are dragging behind us unawares. But, even though we may have no
  418. distinct idea of it, we feel vaguely that our past remains present to
  419. us. What are we, in fact, what is our _character_, if not the
  420. condensation of the history that we have lived from our birth--nay, even
  421. before our birth, since we bring with us prenatal dispositions?
  422. Doubtless we think with only a small part of our past, but it is with
  423. our entire past, including the original bent of our soul, that we
  424. desire, will and act. Our past, then, as a whole, is made manifest to us
  425. in its impulse; it is felt in the form of tendency, although a small
  426. part of it only is known in the form of idea.
  427. From this survival of the past it follows that consciousness cannot go
  428. through the same state twice. The circumstances may still be the same,
  429. but they will act no longer on the same person, since they find him at a
  430. new moment of his history. Our personality, which is being built up each
  431. instant with its accumulated experience, changes without ceasing. By
  432. changing, it prevents any state, although superficially identical with
  433. another, from ever repeating it in its very depth. That is why our
  434. duration is irreversible. We could not live over again a single moment,
  435. for we should have to begin by effacing the memory of all that had
  436. followed. Even could we erase this memory from our intellect, we could
  437. not from our will.
  438. Thus our personality shoots, grows and ripens without ceasing. Each of
  439. its moments is something new added to what was before. We may go
  440. further: it is not only something new, but something unforeseeable.
  441. Doubtless, my present state is explained by what was in me and by what
  442. was acting on me a moment ago. In analyzing it I should find no other
  443. elements. But even a superhuman intelligence would not have been able to
  444. foresee the simple indivisible form which gives to these purely abstract
  445. elements their concrete organization. For to foresee consists of
  446. projecting into the future what has been perceived in the past, or of
  447. imagining for a later time a new grouping, in a new order, of elements
  448. already perceived. But that which has never been perceived, and which is
  449. at the same time simple, is necessarily unforeseeable. Now such is the
  450. case with each of our states, regarded as a moment in a history that is
  451. gradually unfolding: it is simple, and it cannot have been already
  452. perceived, since it concentrates in its indivisibility all that has been
  453. perceived and what the present is adding to it besides. It is an
  454. original moment of a no less original history.
  455. The finished portrait is explained by the features of the model, by the
  456. nature of the artist, by the colors spread out on the palette; but, even
  457. with the knowledge of what explains it, no one, not even the artist,
  458. could have foreseen exactly what the portrait would be, for to predict
  459. it would have been to produce it before it was produced--an absurd
  460. hypothesis which is its own refutation. Even so with regard to the
  461. moments of our life, of which we are the artisans. Each of them is a
  462. kind of creation. And just as the talent of the painter is formed or
  463. deformed--in any case, is modified--under the very influence of the
  464. works he produces, so each of our states, at the moment of its issue,
  465. modifies our personality, being indeed the new form that we are just
  466. assuming. It is then right to say that what we do depends on what we
  467. are; but it is necessary to add also that we are, to a certain extent,
  468. what we do, and that we are creating ourselves continually. This
  469. creation of self by self is the more complete, the more one reasons on
  470. what one does. For reason does not proceed in such matters as in
  471. geometry, where impersonal premisses are given once for all, and an
  472. impersonal conclusion must perforce be drawn. Here, on the contrary, the
  473. same reasons may dictate to different persons, or to the same person at
  474. different moments, acts profoundly different, although equally
  475. reasonable. The truth is that they are not quite the same reasons, since
  476. they are not those of the same person, nor of the same moment. That is
  477. why we cannot deal with them in the abstract, from outside, as in
  478. geometry, nor solve for another the problems by which he is faced in
  479. life. Each must solve them from within, on his own account. But we need
  480. not go more deeply into this. We are seeking only the precise meaning
  481. that our consciousness gives to this word "exist," and we find that, for
  482. a conscious being, to exist is to change, to change is to mature, to
  483. mature is to go on creating oneself endlessly. Should the same be said
  484. of existence in general?
  485. * * * * *
  486. A material object, of whatever kind, presents opposite characters to
  487. those which we have just been describing. Either it remains as it is, or
  488. else, if it changes under the influence of an external force, our idea
  489. of this change is that of a displacement of parts which themselves do
  490. not change. If these parts took to changing, we should split them up in
  491. their turn. We should thus descend to the molecules of which the
  492. fragments are made, to the atoms that make up the molecules, to the
  493. corpuscles that generate the atoms, to the "imponderable" within which
  494. the corpuscle is perhaps a mere vortex. In short, we should push the
  495. division or analysis as far as necessary. But we should stop only before
  496. the unchangeable.
  497. Now, we say that a composite object changes by the displacement of its
  498. parts. But when a part has left its position, there is nothing to
  499. prevent its return to it. A group of elements which has gone through a
  500. state can therefore always find its way back to that state, if not by
  501. itself, at least by means of an external cause able to restore
  502. everything to its place. This amounts to saying that any state of the
  503. group may be repeated as often as desired, and consequently that the
  504. group does not grow old. It has no history.
  505. Thus nothing is created therein, neither form nor matter. What the group
  506. will be is already present in what it is, provided "what it is" includes
  507. all the points of the universe with which it is related. A superhuman
  508. intellect could calculate, for any moment of time, the position of any
  509. point of the system in space. And as there is nothing more in the form
  510. of the whole than the arrangement of its parts, the future forms of the
  511. system are theoretically visible in its present configuration.
  512. All our belief in objects, all our operations on the systems that
  513. science isolates, rest in fact on the idea that time does not bite into
  514. them. We have touched on this question in an earlier work, and shall
  515. return to it in the course of the present study. For the moment, we will
  516. confine ourselves to pointing out that the abstract time _t_ attributed
  517. by science to a material object or to an isolated system consists only
  518. in a certain number of simultaneities or more generally of
  519. correspondences, and that this number remains the same, whatever be the
  520. nature of the intervals between the correspondences. With these
  521. intervals we are never concerned when dealing with inert matter; or, if
  522. they are considered, it is in order to count therein fresh
  523. correspondences, between which again we shall not care what happens.
  524. Common sense, which is occupied with detached objects, and also science,
  525. which considers isolated systems, are concerned only with the ends of
  526. the intervals and not with the intervals themselves. Therefore the flow
  527. of time might assume an infinite rapidity, the entire past, present, and
  528. future of material objects or of isolated systems might be spread out
  529. all at once in space, without there being anything to change either in
  530. the formulae of the scientist or even in the language of common sense.
  531. The number _t_ would always stand for the same thing; it would still
  532. count the same number of correspondences between the states of the
  533. objects or systems and the points of the line, ready drawn, which would
  534. be then the "course of time."
  535. Yet succession is an undeniable fact, even in the material world. Though
  536. our reasoning on isolated systems may imply that their history, past,
  537. present, and future, might be instantaneously unfurled like a fan, this
  538. history, in point of fact, unfolds itself gradually, as if it occupied a
  539. duration like our own. If I want to mix a glass of sugar and water, I
  540. must, willy nilly, wait until the sugar melts. This little fact is big
  541. with meaning. For here the time I have to wait is not that mathematical
  542. time which would apply equally well to the entire history of the
  543. material world, even if that history were spread out instantaneously in
  544. space. It coincides with my impatience, that is to say, with a certain
  545. portion of my own duration, which I cannot protract or contract as I
  546. like. It is no longer something _thought_, it is something _lived_. It
  547. is no longer a relation, it is an absolute. What else can this mean than
  548. that the glass of water, the sugar, and the process of the sugar's
  549. melting in the water are abstractions, and that the Whole within which
  550. they have been cut out by my senses and understanding progresses, it may
  551. be in the manner of a consciousness?
  552. Certainly, the operation by which science isolates and closes a system
  553. is not altogether artificial. If it had no objective foundation, we
  554. could not explain why it is clearly indicated in some cases and
  555. impossible in others. We shall see that matter has a tendency to
  556. constitute _isolable_ systems, that can be treated geometrically. In
  557. fact, we shall define matter by just this tendency. But it is only a
  558. tendency. Matter does not go to the end, and the isolation is never
  559. complete. If science does go to the end and isolate completely, it is
  560. for convenience of study; it is understood that the so-called isolated
  561. system remains subject to certain external influences. Science merely
  562. leaves these alone, either because it finds them slight enough to be
  563. negligible, or because it intends to take them into account later on. It
  564. is none the less true that these influences are so many threads which
  565. bind up the system to another more extensive, and to this a third which
  566. includes both, and so on to the system most objectively isolated and
  567. most independent of all, the solar system complete. But, even here, the
  568. isolation is not absolute. Our sun radiates heat and light beyond the
  569. farthest planet. And, on the other hand, it moves in a certain fixed
  570. direction, drawing with it the planets and their satellites. The thread
  571. attaching it to the rest of the universe is doubtless very tenuous.
  572. Nevertheless it is along this thread that is transmitted down to the
  573. smallest particle of the world in which we live the duration immanent to
  574. the whole of the universe.
  575. The universe _endures_. The more we study the nature of time, the more
  576. we shall comprehend that duration means invention, the creation of
  577. forms, the continual elaboration of the absolutely new. The systems
  578. marked off by science _endure_ only because they are bound up
  579. inseparably with the rest of the universe. It is true that in the
  580. universe itself two opposite movements are to be distinguished, as we
  581. shall see later on, "descent" and "ascent." The first only unwinds a
  582. roll ready prepared. In principle, it might be accomplished almost
  583. instantaneously, like releasing a spring. But the ascending movement,
  584. which corresponds to an inner work of ripening or creating, _endures_
  585. essentially, and imposes its rhythm on the first, which is inseparable
  586. from it.
  587. There is no reason, therefore, why a duration, and so a form of
  588. existence like our own, should not be attributed to the systems that
  589. science isolates, provided such systems are reintegrated into the Whole.
  590. But they must be so reintegrated. The same is even more obviously true
  591. of the objects cut out by our perception. The distinct outlines which we
  592. see in an object, and which give it its individuality, are only the
  593. design of a certain kind of _influence_ that we might exert on a certain
  594. point of space: it is the plan of our eventual actions that is sent back
  595. to our eyes, as though by a mirror, when we see the surfaces and edges
  596. of things. Suppress this action, and with it consequently those main
  597. directions which by perception are traced out for it in the entanglement
  598. of the real, and the individuality of the body is reabsorbed in the
  599. universal interaction which, without doubt, is reality itself.
  600. Now, we have considered material objects generally. Are there not some
  601. objects privileged? The bodies we perceive are, so to speak, cut out of
  602. the stuff of nature by our _perception_, and the scissors follow, in
  603. some way, the marking of lines along which _action_ might be taken. But
  604. the body which is to perform this action, the body which marks out upon
  605. matter the design of its eventual actions even before they are actual,
  606. the body that has only to point its sensory organs on the flow of the
  607. real in order to make that flow crystallize into definite forms and thus
  608. to create all the other bodies--in short, the _living_ body--is this a
  609. body as others are?
  610. Doubtless it, also, consists in a portion of extension bound up with the
  611. rest of extension, an intimate part of the Whole, subject to the same
  612. physical and chemical laws that govern any and every portion of matter.
  613. But, while the subdivision of matter into separate bodies is relative to
  614. our perception, while the building up of closed-off systems of material
  615. points is relative to our science, the living body has been separated
  616. and closed off by nature herself. It is composed of unlike parts that
  617. complete each other. It performs diverse functions that involve each
  618. other. It is an _individual_, and of no other object, not even of the
  619. crystal, can this be said, for a crystal has neither difference of parts
  620. nor diversity of functions. No doubt, it is hard to decide, even in the
  621. organized world, what is individual and what is not. The difficulty is
  622. great, even in the animal kingdom; with plants it is almost
  623. insurmountable. This difficulty is, moreover, due to profound causes, on
  624. which we shall dwell later. We shall see that individuality admits of
  625. any number of degrees, and that it is not fully realized anywhere, even
  626. in man. But that is no reason for thinking it is not a characteristic
  627. property of life. The biologist who proceeds as a geometrician is too
  628. ready to take advantage here of our inability to give a precise and
  629. general definition of individuality. A perfect definition applies only
  630. to a _completed_ reality; now, vital properties are never entirely
  631. realized, though always on the way to become so; they are not so much
  632. _states_ as _tendencies_. And a tendency achieves all that it aims at
  633. only if it is not thwarted by another tendency. How, then, could this
  634. occur in the domain of life, where, as we shall show, the interaction of
  635. antagonistic tendencies is always implied? In particular, it may be said
  636. of individuality that, while the tendency to individuate is everywhere
  637. present in the organized world, it is everywhere opposed by the tendency
  638. towards reproduction. For the individuality to be perfect, it would be
  639. necessary that no detached part of the organism could live separately.
  640. But then reproduction would be impossible. For what is reproduction, but
  641. the building up of a new organism with a detached fragment of the old?
  642. Individuality therefore harbors its enemy at home. Its very need of
  643. perpetuating itself in time condemns it never to be complete in space.
  644. The biologist must take due account of both tendencies in every
  645. instance, and it is therefore useless to ask him for a definition of
  646. individuality that shall fit all cases and work automatically.
  647. But too often one reasons about the things of life in the same way as
  648. about the conditions of crude matter. Nowhere is the confusion so
  649. evident as in discussions about individuality. We are shown the stumps
  650. of a Lumbriculus, each regenerating its head and living thence-forward
  651. as an independent individual; a hydra whose pieces become so many fresh
  652. hydras; a sea-urchin's egg whose fragments develop complete embryos:
  653. where then, we are asked, was the individuality of the egg, the hydra,
  654. the worm?--But, because there are several individuals now, it does not
  655. follow that there was not a single individual just before. No doubt,
  656. when I have seen several drawers fall from a chest, I have no longer the
  657. right to say that the article was all of one piece. But the fact is that
  658. there can be nothing more in the present of the chest of drawers than
  659. there was in its past, and if it is made up of several different pieces
  660. now, it was so from the date of its manufacture. Generally speaking,
  661. unorganized bodies, which are what we have need of in order that we may
  662. act, and on which we have modelled our fashion of thinking, are
  663. regulated by this simple law: _the present contains nothing more than
  664. the past, and what is found in the effect was already in the cause_. But
  665. suppose that the distinctive feature of the organized body is that it
  666. grows and changes without ceasing, as indeed the most superficial
  667. observation testifies, there would be nothing astonishing in the fact
  668. that it was _one_ in the first instance, and afterwards _many_. The
  669. reproduction of unicellular organisms consists in just this--the living
  670. being divides into two halves, of which each is a complete individual.
  671. True, in the more complex animals, nature localizes in the almost
  672. independent sexual cells the power of producing the whole anew. But
  673. something of this power may remain diffused in the rest of the organism,
  674. as the facts of regeneration prove, and it is conceivable that in
  675. certain privileged cases the faculty may persist integrally in a latent
  676. condition and manifest itself on the first opportunity. In truth, that I
  677. may have the right to speak of individuality, it is not necessary that
  678. the organism should be without the power to divide into fragments that
  679. are able to live. It is sufficient that it should have presented a
  680. certain systematization of parts before the division, and that the same
  681. systematization tend to be reproduced in each separate portion
  682. afterwards. Now, that is precisely what we observe in the organic
  683. world. We may conclude, then, that individuality is never perfect, and
  684. that it is often difficult, sometimes impossible, to tell what is an
  685. individual, and what is not, but that life nevertheless manifests a
  686. search for individuality, as if it strove to constitute systems
  687. naturally isolated, naturally closed.
  688. * * * * *
  689. By this is a living being distinguished from all that our perception or
  690. our science isolates or closes artificially. It would therefore be wrong
  691. to compare it to an _object_. Should we wish to find a term of
  692. comparison in the inorganic world, it is not to a determinate material
  693. object, but much rather to the totality of the material universe that we
  694. ought to compare the living organism. It is true that the comparison
  695. would not be worth much, for a living being is observable, whilst the
  696. whole of the universe is constructed or reconstructed by thought. But at
  697. least our attention would thus have been called to the essential
  698. character of organization. Like the universe as a whole, like each
  699. conscious being taken separately, the organism which lives is a thing
  700. that _endures_. Its past, in its entirety, is prolonged into its
  701. present, and abides there, actual and acting. How otherwise could we
  702. understand that it passes through distinct and well-marked phases, that
  703. it changes its age--in short, that it has a history? If I consider my
  704. body in particular, I find that, like my consciousness, it matures
  705. little by little from infancy to old age; like myself, it grows old.
  706. Indeed, maturity and old age are, properly speaking, attributes only of
  707. my body; it is only metaphorically that I apply the same names to the
  708. corresponding changes of my conscious self. Now, if I pass from the top
  709. to the bottom of the scale of living beings, from one of the most to one
  710. of the least differentiated, from the multicellular organism of man to
  711. the unicellular organism of the Infusorian, I find, even in this simple
  712. cell, the same process of growing old. The Infusorian is exhausted at
  713. the end of a certain number of divisions, and though it may be possible,
  714. by modifying the environment, to put off the moment when a rejuvenation
  715. by conjugation becomes necessary, this cannot be indefinitely
  716. postponed.[4] It is true that between these two extreme cases, in which
  717. the organism is completely individualized, there might be found a
  718. multitude of others in which the individuality is less well marked, and
  719. in which, although there is doubtless an ageing somewhere, one cannot
  720. say exactly what it is that grows old. Once more, there is no universal
  721. biological law which applies precisely and automatically to every living
  722. thing. There are only _directions_ in which life throws out species in
  723. general. Each particular species, in the very act by which it is
  724. constituted, affirms its independence, follows its caprice, deviates
  725. more or less from the straight line, sometimes even remounts the slope
  726. and seems to turn its back on its original direction. It is easy enough
  727. to argue that a tree never grows old, since the tips of its branches are
  728. always equally young, always equally capable of engendering new trees by
  729. budding. But in such an organism--which is, after all, a society rather
  730. than an individual--_something_ ages, if only the leaves and the
  731. interior of the trunk. And each cell, considered separately, evolves in
  732. a specific way. _Wherever anything lives, there is, open somewhere, a
  733. register in which time is being inscribed._
  734. This, it will be said, is only a metaphor.--It is of the very essence of
  735. mechanism, in fact, to consider as metaphorical every expression which
  736. attributes to time an effective action and a reality of its own. In vain
  737. does immediate experience show us that the very basis of our conscious
  738. existence is memory, that is to say, the prolongation of the past into
  739. the present, or, in a word, _duration_, acting and irreversible. In vain
  740. does reason prove to us that the more we get away from the objects cut
  741. out and the systems isolated by common sense and by science and the
  742. deeper we dig beneath them, the more we have to do with a reality which
  743. changes as a whole in its inmost states, as if an accumulative memory of
  744. the past made it impossible to go back again. The mechanistic instinct
  745. of the mind is stronger than reason, stronger than immediate experience.
  746. The metaphysician that we each carry unconsciously within us, and the
  747. presence of which is explained, as we shall see later on, by the very
  748. place that man occupies amongst the living beings, has its fixed
  749. requirements, its ready-made explanations, its irreducible propositions:
  750. all unite in denying concrete duration. Change _must_ be reducible to an
  751. arrangement or rearrangement of parts; the irreversibility of time
  752. _must_ be an appearance relative to our ignorance; the impossibility of
  753. turning back _must_ be only the inability of man to put things in place
  754. again. So growing old can be nothing more than the gradual gain or loss
  755. of certain substances, perhaps both together. Time is assumed to have
  756. just as much reality for a living being as for an hour-glass, in which
  757. the top part empties while the lower fills, and all goes where it was
  758. before when you turn the glass upside down.
  759. True, biologists are not agreed on what is gained and what is lost
  760. between the day of birth and the day of death. There are those who hold
  761. to the continual growth in the volume of protoplasm from the birth of
  762. the cell right on to its death.[5] More probable and more profound is
  763. the theory according to which the diminution bears on the quantity of
  764. nutritive substance contained in that "inner environment" in which the
  765. organism is being renewed, and the increase on the quantity of unexcreted
  766. residual substances which, accumulating in the body, finally "crust it
  767. over."[6] Must we however--with an eminent bacteriologist--declare any
  768. explanation of growing old insufficient that does not take account of
  769. phagocytosis?[7] We do not feel qualified to settle the question. But
  770. the fact that the two theories agree in affirming the constant accumulation
  771. or loss of a certain kind of matter, even though they have little in common
  772. as to what is gained and lost, shows pretty well that the frame of the
  773. explanation has been furnished _a priori_. We shall see this more and more
  774. as we proceed with our study: it is not easy, in thinking of time, to
  775. escape the image of the hour-glass.
  776. The cause of growing old must lie deeper. We hold that there is unbroken
  777. continuity between the evolution of the embryo and that of the complete
  778. organism. The impetus which causes a living being to grow larger, to
  779. develop and to age, is the same that has caused it to pass through the
  780. phases of the embryonic life. The development of the embryo is a
  781. perpetual change of form. Any one who attempts to note all its
  782. successive aspects becomes lost in an infinity, as is inevitable in
  783. dealing with a continuum. Life does but prolong this prenatal evolution.
  784. The proof of this is that it is often impossible for us to say whether
  785. we are dealing with an organism growing old or with an embryo continuing
  786. to evolve; such is the case, for example, with the larvae of insects
  787. and crustacea. On the other hand, in an organism such as our own, crises
  788. like puberty or the menopause, in which the individual is completely
  789. transformed, are quite comparable to changes in the course of larval or
  790. embryonic life--yet they are part and parcel of the process of our
  791. ageing. Although they occur at a definite age and within a time that may
  792. be quite short, no one would maintain that they appear then _ex
  793. abrupto_, from without, simply because a certain age is reached, just as
  794. a legal right is granted to us on our one-and-twentieth birthday. It is
  795. evident that a change like that of puberty is in course of preparation
  796. at every instant from birth, and even before birth, and that the ageing
  797. up to that crisis consists, in part at least, of this gradual
  798. preparation. In short, what is properly vital in growing old is the
  799. insensible, infinitely graduated, continuance of the change of form.
  800. Now, this change is undoubtedly accompanied by phenomena of organic
  801. destruction: to these, and to these alone, will a mechanistic
  802. explanation of ageing be confined. It will note the facts of sclerosis,
  803. the gradual accumulation of residual substances, the growing hypertrophy
  804. of the protoplasm of the cell. But under these visible effects an inner
  805. cause lies hidden. The evolution of the living being, like that of the
  806. embryo, implies a continual recording of duration, a persistence of the
  807. past in the present, and so an appearance, at least, of organic memory.
  808. The present state of an unorganized body depends exclusively on what
  809. happened at the previous instant; and likewise the position of the
  810. material points of a system defined and isolated by science is
  811. determined by the position of these same points at the moment
  812. immediately before. In other words, the laws that govern unorganized
  813. matter are expressible, in principle, by differential equations in
  814. which time (in the sense in which the mathematician takes this word)
  815. would play the rôle of independent variable. Is it so with the laws of
  816. life? Does the state of a living body find its complete explanation in
  817. the state immediately before? Yes, if it is agreed _a priori_ to liken
  818. the living body to other bodies, and to identify it, for the sake of the
  819. argument, with the artificial systems on which the chemist, physicist,
  820. and astronomer operate. But in astronomy, physics, and chemistry the
  821. proposition has a perfectly definite meaning: it signifies that certain
  822. aspects of the present, important for science, are calculable as
  823. functions of the immediate past. Nothing of the sort in the domain of
  824. life. Here calculation touches, at most, certain phenomena of organic
  825. _destruction_. Organic _creation_, on the contrary, the evolutionary
  826. phenomena which properly constitute life, we cannot in any way subject
  827. to a mathematical treatment. It will be said that this impotence is due
  828. only to our ignorance. But it may equally well express the fact that the
  829. present moment of a living body does not find its explanation in the
  830. moment immediately before, that _all_ the past of the organism must be
  831. added to that moment, its heredity--in fact, the whole of a very long
  832. history. In the second of these two hypotheses, not in the first, is
  833. really expressed the present state of the biological sciences, as well
  834. as their direction. As for the idea that the living body might be
  835. treated by some superhuman calculator in the same mathematical way as
  836. our solar system, this has gradually arisen from a metaphysic which has
  837. taken a more precise form since the physical discoveries of Galileo, but
  838. which, as we shall show, was always the natural metaphysic of the human
  839. mind. Its apparent clearness, our impatient desire to find it true, the
  840. enthusiasm with which so many excellent minds accept it without
  841. proof--all the seductions, in short, that it exercises on our thought,
  842. should put us on our guard against it. The attraction it has for us
  843. proves well enough that it gives satisfaction to an innate inclination.
  844. But, as will be seen further on, the intellectual tendencies innate
  845. to-day, which life must have created in the course of its evolution, are
  846. not at all meant to supply us with an explanation of life: they have
  847. something else to do.
  848. Any attempt to distinguish between an artificial and a natural system,
  849. between the dead and the living, runs counter to this tendency at once.
  850. Thus it happens that we find it equally difficult to imagine that the
  851. organized has duration and that the unorganized has not. When we say
  852. that the state of an artificial system depends exclusively on its state
  853. at the moment before, does it not seem as if we were bringing time in,
  854. as if the system had something to do with real duration? And, on the
  855. other hand, though the whole of the past goes into the making of the
  856. living being's present moment, does not organic memory press it into the
  857. moment immediately before the present, so that the moment immediately
  858. before becomes the sole cause of the present one?--To speak thus is to
  859. ignore the cardinal difference between _concrete_ time, along which a
  860. real system develops, and that _abstract_ time which enters into our
  861. speculations on artificial systems. What does it mean, to say that the
  862. state of an artificial system depends on what it was at the moment
  863. immediately before? There is no instant immediately before another
  864. instant; there could not be, any more than there could be one
  865. mathematical point touching another. The instant "immediately before"
  866. is, in reality, that which is connected with the present instant by the
  867. interval _dt_. All that you mean to say, therefore, is that the present
  868. state of the system is defined by equations into which differential
  869. coefficients enter, such as _ds_|_dt_, _dv_|_dt_, that is to say, at
  870. bottom, _present_ velocities and _present_ accelerations. You are
  871. therefore really speaking only of the present--a present, it is true,
  872. considered along with its _tendency_. The systems science works with
  873. are, in fact, in an instantaneous present that is always being renewed;
  874. such systems are never in that real, concrete duration in which the past
  875. remains bound up with the present. When the mathematician calculates the
  876. future state of a system at the end of a time _t_, there is nothing to
  877. prevent him from supposing that the universe vanishes from this moment
  878. till that, and suddenly reappears. It is the _t_-th moment only that
  879. counts--and that will be a mere instant. What will flow on in the
  880. interval--that is to say, real time--does not count, and cannot enter
  881. into the calculation. If the mathematician says that he puts himself
  882. inside this interval, he means that he is placing himself at a certain
  883. point, at a particular moment, therefore at the extremity again of a
  884. certain time _t'_; with the interval up to _T'_ he is not concerned. If
  885. he divides the interval into infinitely small parts by considering the
  886. differential _dt_, he thereby expresses merely the fact that he will
  887. consider accelerations and velocities--that is to say, numbers which
  888. denote tendencies and enable him to calculate the state of the system at
  889. a given moment. But he is always speaking of a given moment--a static
  890. moment, that is--and not of flowing time. In short, _the world the
  891. mathematician deals with is a world that dies and is reborn at every
  892. instant--the world which Descartes was thinking of when he spoke of
  893. continued creation_. But, in time thus conceived, how could evolution,
  894. which is the very essence of life, ever take place? Evolution implies a
  895. real persistence of the past in the present, a duration which is, as it
  896. were, a hyphen, a connecting link. In other words, to know a living
  897. being or _natural system_ is to get at the very interval of duration,
  898. while the knowledge of an _artificial_ or _mathematical system_ applies
  899. only to the extremity.
  900. Continuity of change, preservation of the past in the present, real
  901. duration--the living being seems, then, to share these attributes with
  902. consciousness. Can we go further and say that life, like conscious
  903. activity, is invention, is unceasing creation?
  904. * * * * *
  905. It does not enter into our plan to set down here the proofs of
  906. transformism. We wish only to explain in a word or two why we shall
  907. accept it, in the present work, as a sufficiently exact and precise
  908. expression of the facts actually known. The idea of transformism is
  909. already in germ in the natural classification of organized beings. The
  910. naturalist, in fact, brings together the organisms that are like each
  911. other, then divides the group into sub-groups within which the likeness
  912. is still greater, and so on: all through the operation, the characters
  913. of the group appear as general themes on which each of the sub-groups
  914. performs its particular variation. Now, such is just the relation we
  915. find, in the animal and in the vegetable world between the generator and
  916. the generated: on the canvas which the ancestor passes on, and which his
  917. descendants possess in common, each puts his own original embroidery.
  918. True, the differences between the descendant and the ancestor are
  919. slight, and it may be asked whether the same living matter presents
  920. enough plasticity to take in turn such different forms as those of a
  921. fish, a reptile and a bird. But, to this question, observation gives a
  922. peremptory answer. It shows that up to a certain period in its
  923. development the embryo of the bird is hardly distinguishable from that
  924. of the reptile, and that the individual develops, throughout the
  925. embryonic life in general, a series of transformations comparable to
  926. those through which, according to the theory of evolution, one species
  927. passes into another. A single cell, the result of the combination of two
  928. cells, male and female, accomplishes this work by dividing. Every day,
  929. before our eyes, the highest forms of life are springing from a very
  930. elementary form. Experience, then, shows that the most complex has been
  931. able to issue from the most simple by way of evolution. Now, has it
  932. arisen so, as a matter of fact? Paleontology, in spite of the
  933. insufficiency of its evidence, invites us to believe it has; for, where
  934. it makes out the order of succession of species with any precision, this
  935. order is just what considerations drawn from embryogeny and comparative
  936. anatomy would lead any one to suppose, and each new paleontological
  937. discovery brings transformism a new confirmation. Thus, the proof drawn
  938. from mere observation is ever being strengthened, while, on the other
  939. hand, experiment is removing the objections one by one. The recent
  940. experiments of H. de Vries, for instance, by showing that important
  941. variations can be produced suddenly and transmitted regularly, have
  942. overthrown some of the greatest difficulties raised by the theory. They
  943. have enabled us greatly to shorten the time biological evolution seems
  944. to demand. They also render us less exacting toward paleontology. So
  945. that, all things considered, the transformist hypothesis looks more and
  946. more like a close approximation to the truth. It is not rigorously
  947. demonstrable; but, failing the certainty of theoretical or experimental
  948. demonstration, there is a probability which is continually growing, due
  949. to evidence which, while coming short of direct proof, seems to point
  950. persistently in its direction: such is the kind of probability that the
  951. theory of transformism offers.
  952. Let us admit, however, that transformism may be wrong. Let us suppose
  953. that species are proved, by inference or by experiment, to have arisen
  954. by a discontinuous process, of which to-day we have no idea. Would the
  955. doctrine be affected in so far as it has a special interest or
  956. importance for us? Classification would probably remain, in its broad
  957. lines. The actual data of embryology would also remain. The
  958. correspondence between comparative embryogeny and comparative anatomy
  959. would remain too. Therefore biology could and would continue to
  960. establish between living forms the same relations and the same kinship
  961. as transformism supposes to-day. It would be, it is true, an _ideal_
  962. kinship, and no longer a _material_ affiliation. But, as the actual data
  963. of paleontology would also remain, we should still have to admit that it
  964. is successively, not simultaneously, that the forms between which we
  965. find an ideal kinship have appeared. Now, the evolutionist theory, so
  966. far as it has any importance for philosophy, requires no more. It
  967. consists above all in establishing relations of ideal kinship, and in
  968. maintaining that wherever there is this relation of, so to speak,
  969. _logical_ affiliation between forms, there is also a relation of
  970. _chronological_ succession between the species in which these forms are
  971. materialized. Both arguments would hold in any case. And hence, an
  972. evolution _somewhere_ would still have to be supposed, whether in a
  973. creative Thought in which the ideas of the different species are
  974. generated by each other exactly as transformism holds that species
  975. themselves are generated on the earth; or in a plan of vital
  976. organization immanent in nature, which gradually works itself out, in
  977. which the relations of logical and chronological affiliation between
  978. pure forms are just those which transformism presents as relations of
  979. real affiliation between living individuals; or, finally, in some
  980. unknown cause of life, which develops its effects _as if_ they generated
  981. one another. Evolution would then simply have been _transposed_, made
  982. to pass from the visible to the invisible. Almost all that transformism
  983. tells us to-day would be preserved, open to interpretation in another
  984. way. Will it not, therefore, be better to stick to the letter of
  985. transformism as almost all scientists profess it? Apart from the
  986. question to what extent the theory of evolution describes the facts and
  987. to what extent it symbolizes them, there is nothing in it that is
  988. irreconcilable with the doctrines it has claimed to replace, even with
  989. that of special creations, to which it is usually opposed. For this
  990. reason we think the language of transformism forces itself now upon all
  991. philosophy, as the dogmatic affirmation of transformism forces itself
  992. upon science.
  993. But then, we must no longer speak of _life in general_ as an
  994. abstraction, or as a mere heading under which all living beings are
  995. inscribed. At a certain moment, in certain points of space, a visible
  996. current has taken rise; this current of life, traversing the bodies it
  997. has organized one after another, passing from generation to generation,
  998. has become divided amongst species and distributed amongst individuals
  999. without losing anything of its force, rather intensifying in proportion
  1000. to its advance. It is well known that, on the theory of the "continuity
  1001. of the germ-plasm," maintained by Weismann, the sexual elements of the
  1002. generating organism pass on their properties directly to the sexual
  1003. elements of the organism engendered. In this extreme form, the theory
  1004. has seemed debatable, for it is only in exceptional cases that there are
  1005. any signs of sexual glands at the time of segmentation of the fertilized
  1006. egg. But, though the cells that engender the sexual elements do not
  1007. generally appear at the beginning of the embryonic life, it is none the
  1008. less true that they are always formed out of those tissues of the embryo
  1009. which have not undergone any particular functional differentiation, and
  1010. whose cells are made of unmodified protoplasm.[8] In other words, the
  1011. genetic power of the fertilized ovum weakens, the more it is spread over
  1012. the growing mass of the tissues of the embryo; but, while it is being
  1013. thus diluted, it is concentrating anew something of itself on a certain
  1014. special point, to wit, the cells, from which the ova or spermatozoa will
  1015. develop. It might therefore be said that, though the germ-plasm is not
  1016. continuous, there is at least continuity of genetic energy, this energy
  1017. being expended only at certain instants, for just enough time to give
  1018. the requisite impulsion to the embryonic life, and being recouped as
  1019. soon as possible in new sexual elements, in which, again, it bides its
  1020. time. Regarded from this point of view, _life is like a current passing
  1021. from germ to germ through the medium of a developed organism_. It is as
  1022. if the organism itself were only an excrescence, a bud caused to sprout
  1023. by the former germ endeavoring to continue itself in a new germ. The
  1024. essential thing is the _continuous progress_ indefinitely pursued, an
  1025. invisible progress, on which each visible organism rides during the
  1026. short interval of time given it to live.
  1027. Now, the more we fix our attention on this continuity of life, the more
  1028. we see that organic evolution resembles the evolution of a
  1029. consciousness, in which the past presses against the present and causes
  1030. the upspringing of a new form of consciousness, incommensurable with its
  1031. antecedents. That the appearance of a vegetable or animal species is due
  1032. to specific causes, nobody will gainsay. But this can only mean that if,
  1033. after the fact, we could know these causes in detail, we could explain
  1034. by them the form that has been produced; foreseeing the form is out of
  1035. the question.[9] It may perhaps be said that the form could be foreseen
  1036. if we could know, in all their details, the conditions under which it
  1037. will be produced. But these conditions are built up into it and are part
  1038. and parcel of its being; they are peculiar to that phase of its history
  1039. in which life finds itself at the moment of producing the form: how
  1040. could we know beforehand a situation that is unique of its kind, that
  1041. has never yet occurred and will never occur again? Of the future, only
  1042. that is foreseen which is like the past or can be made up again with
  1043. elements like those of the past. Such is the case with astronomical,
  1044. physical and chemical facts, with all facts which form part of a system
  1045. in which elements supposed to be unchanging are merely put together, in
  1046. which the only changes are changes of position, in which there is no
  1047. theoretical absurdity in imagining that things are restored to their
  1048. place; in which, consequently, the same total phenomenon, or at least
  1049. the same elementary phenomena, can be repeated. But an original
  1050. situation, which imparts something of its own originality to its
  1051. elements, that is to say, to the partial views that are taken of it, how
  1052. can such a situation be pictured as given before it is actually
  1053. produced?[10] All that can be said is that, once produced, it will be
  1054. explained by the elements that analysis will then carve out of it. Now,
  1055. what is true of the production of a new species is also true of the
  1056. production of a new individual, and, more generally, of any moment of
  1057. any living form. For, though the variation must reach a certain
  1058. importance and a certain generality in order to give rise to a new
  1059. species, it is being produced every moment, continuously and insensibly,
  1060. in every living being. And it is evident that even the sudden
  1061. "mutations" which we now hear of are possible only if a process of
  1062. incubation, or rather of maturing, is going on throughout a series of
  1063. generations that do not seem to change. In this sense it might be said
  1064. of life, as of consciousness, that at every moment it is creating
  1065. something.[11]
  1066. But against this idea of the absolute originality and unforeseeability
  1067. of forms our whole intellect rises in revolt. The essential function of
  1068. our intellect, as the evolution of life has fashioned it, is to be a
  1069. light for our conduct, to make ready for our action on things, to
  1070. foresee, for a given situation, the events, favorable or unfavorable,
  1071. which may follow thereupon. Intellect therefore instinctively selects in
  1072. a given situation whatever is like something already known; it seeks
  1073. this out, in order that it may apply its principle that "like produces
  1074. like." In just this does the prevision of the future by common sense
  1075. consist. Science carries this faculty to the highest possible degree of
  1076. exactitude and precision, but does not alter its essential character.
  1077. Like ordinary knowledge, in dealing with things science is concerned
  1078. only with the aspect of _repetition_. Though the whole be original,
  1079. science will always manage to analyze it into elements or aspects which
  1080. are approximately a reproduction of the past. Science can work only on
  1081. what is supposed to repeat itself--that is to say, on what is withdrawn,
  1082. by hypothesis, from the action of real time. Anything that is
  1083. irreducible and irreversible in the successive moments of a history
  1084. eludes science. To get a notion of this irreducibility and
  1085. irreversibility, we must break with scientific habits which are adapted
  1086. to the fundamental requirements of thought, we must do violence to the
  1087. mind, go counter to the natural bent of the intellect. But that is just
  1088. the function of philosophy.
  1089. In vain, therefore, does life evolve before our eyes as a continuous
  1090. creation of unforeseeable form: the idea always persists that form,
  1091. unforeseeability and continuity are mere appearance--the outward
  1092. reflection of our own ignorance. What is presented to the senses as a
  1093. continuous history would break up, we are told, into a series of
  1094. successive states. "What gives you the impression of an original state
  1095. resolves, upon analysis, into elementary facts, each of which is the
  1096. repetition of a fact already known. What you call an unforeseeable form
  1097. is only a new arrangement of old elements. The elementary causes, which
  1098. in their totality have determined this arrangement, are themselves old
  1099. causes repeated in a new order. Knowledge of the elements and of the
  1100. elementary causes would have made it possible to foretell the living
  1101. form which is their sum and their resultant. When we have resolved the
  1102. biological aspect of phenomena into physico-chemical factors, we will
  1103. leap, if necessary, over physics and chemistry themselves; we will go
  1104. from masses to molecules, from molecules to atoms, from atoms to
  1105. corpuscles: we must indeed at last come to something that can be treated
  1106. as a kind of solar system, astronomically. If you deny it, you oppose
  1107. the very principle of scientific mechanism, and you arbitrarily affirm
  1108. that living matter is not made of the same elements as other
  1109. matter."--We reply that we do not question the fundamental identity of
  1110. inert matter and organized matter. The only question is whether the
  1111. natural systems which we call living beings must be assimilated to the
  1112. artificial systems that science cuts out within inert matter, or whether
  1113. they must not rather be compared to that natural system which is the
  1114. whole of the universe. That life is a kind of mechanism I cordially
  1115. agree. But is it the mechanism of parts artificially isolated within the
  1116. whole of the universe, or is it the mechanism of the real whole? The
  1117. real whole might well be, we conceive, an indivisible continuity. The
  1118. systems we cut out within it would, properly speaking, not then be
  1119. _parts_ at all; they would be _partial views_ of the whole. And, with
  1120. these partial views put end to end, you will not make even a beginning
  1121. of the reconstruction of the whole, any more than, by multiplying
  1122. photographs of an object in a thousand different aspects, you will
  1123. reproduce the object itself. So of life and of the physico-chemical
  1124. phenomena to which you endeavor to reduce it. Analysis will undoubtedly
  1125. resolve the process of organic creation into an ever-growing number of
  1126. physico-chemical phenomena, and chemists and physicists will have to do,
  1127. of course, with nothing but these. But it does not follow that chemistry
  1128. and physics will ever give us the key to life.
  1129. A very small element of a curve is very near being a straight line. And
  1130. the smaller it is, the nearer. In the limit, it may be termed a part of
  1131. the curve or a part of the straight line, as you please, for in each of
  1132. its points a curve coincides with its tangent. So likewise "vitality" is
  1133. tangent, at any and every point, to physical and chemical forces; but
  1134. such points are, as a fact, only views taken by a mind which imagines
  1135. stops at various moments of the movement that generates the curve. In
  1136. reality, life is no more made of physico-chemical elements than a curve
  1137. is composed of straight lines.
  1138. In a general way, the most radical progress a science can achieve is
  1139. the working of the completed results into a new scheme of the whole, by
  1140. relation to which they become instantaneous and motionless views taken
  1141. at intervals along the continuity of a movement. Such, for example, is
  1142. the relation of modern to ancient geometry. The latter, purely static,
  1143. worked with figures drawn once for all; the former studies the varying
  1144. of a function--that is, the continuous movement by which the figure is
  1145. described. No doubt, for greater strictness, all considerations of
  1146. motion may be eliminated from mathematical processes; but the
  1147. introduction of motion into the genesis of figures is nevertheless the
  1148. origin of modern mathematics. We believe that if biology could ever get
  1149. as close to its object as mathematics does to its own, it would become,
  1150. to the physics and chemistry of organized bodies, what the mathematics
  1151. of the moderns has proved to be in relation to ancient geometry. The
  1152. wholly superficial displacements of masses and molecules studied in
  1153. physics and chemistry would become, by relation to that inner vital
  1154. movement (which is transformation and not translation) what the position
  1155. of a moving object is to the movement of that object in space. And, so
  1156. far as we can see, the procedure by which we should then pass from the
  1157. definition of a certain vital action to the system of physico-chemical
  1158. facts which it implies would be like passing from the function to its
  1159. derivative, from the equation of the curve (_i.e._ the law of the
  1160. continuous movement by which the curve is generated) to the equation of
  1161. the tangent giving its instantaneous direction. Such a science would be
  1162. a _mechanics of transformation_, of which our _mechanics of translation_
  1163. would become a particular case, a simplification, a projection on the
  1164. plane of pure quantity. And just as an infinity of functions have the
  1165. same differential, these functions differing from each other by a
  1166. constant, so perhaps the integration of the physico-chemical elements
  1167. of properly vital action might determine that action only in part--a
  1168. part would be left to indetermination. But such an integration can be no
  1169. more than dreamed of; we do not pretend that the dream will ever be
  1170. realized. We are only trying, by carrying a certain comparison as far as
  1171. possible, to show up to what point our theory goes along with pure
  1172. mechanism, and where they part company.
  1173. Imitation of the living by the unorganized may, however, go a good way.
  1174. Not only does chemistry make organic syntheses, but we have succeeded in
  1175. reproducing artificially the external appearance of certain facts of
  1176. organization, such as indirect cell-division and protoplasmic
  1177. circulation. It is well known that the protoplasm of the cell effects
  1178. various movements within its envelope; on the other hand, indirect
  1179. cell-division is the outcome of very complex operations, some involving
  1180. the nucleus and others the cytoplasm. These latter commence by the
  1181. doubling of the centrosome, a small spherical body alongside the
  1182. nucleus. The two centrosomes thus obtained draw apart, attract the
  1183. broken and doubled ends of the filament of which the original nucleus
  1184. mainly consisted, and join them to form two fresh nuclei about which the
  1185. two new cells are constructed which will succeed the first. Now, in
  1186. their broad lines and in their external appearance, some at least of
  1187. these operations have been successfully imitated. If some sugar or table
  1188. salt is pulverized and some very old oil is added, and a drop of the
  1189. mixture is observed under the microscope, a froth of alveolar structure
  1190. is seen whose configuration is like that of protoplasm, according to
  1191. certain theories, and in which movements take place which are decidedly
  1192. like those of protoplasmic circulation.[12] If, in a froth of the same
  1193. kind, the air is extracted from an alveolus, a cone of attraction is
  1194. seen to form, like those about the centrosomes which result in the
  1195. division of the nucleus.[13] Even the external motions of a unicellular
  1196. organism--of an amoeba, at any rate--are sometimes explained
  1197. mechanically. The displacements of an amoeba in a drop of water would be
  1198. comparable to the motion to and fro of a grain of dust in a draughty
  1199. room. Its mass is all the time absorbing certain soluble matters
  1200. contained in the surrounding water, and giving back to it certain
  1201. others; these continual exchanges, like those between two vessels
  1202. separated by a porous partition, would create an everchanging vortex
  1203. around the little organism. As for the temporary prolongations or
  1204. pseudopodia which the amoeba seems to make, they would be not so much
  1205. given out by it as attracted from it by a kind of inhalation or suction
  1206. of the surrounding medium.[14] In the same way we may perhaps come to
  1207. explain the more complex movements which the Infusorian makes with its
  1208. vibratory cilia, which, moreover, are probably only fixed pseudopodia.
  1209. But scientists are far from agreed on the value of explanations and
  1210. schemas of this sort. Chemists have pointed out that even in the
  1211. organic--not to go so far as the organized--science has reconstructed
  1212. hitherto nothing but waste products of vital activity; the peculiarly
  1213. active plastic substances obstinately defy synthesis. One of the most
  1214. notable naturalists of our time has insisted on the opposition of two
  1215. orders of phenomena observed in living tissues, _anagenesis_ and
  1216. _katagenesis_. The rôle of the anagenetic energies is to raise the
  1217. inferior energies to their own level by assimilating inorganic
  1218. substances. They _construct_ the tissues. On the other hand, the actual
  1219. functioning of life (excepting, of course, assimilation, growth, and
  1220. reproduction) is of the katagenetic order, exhibiting the fall, not the
  1221. rise, of energy. It is only with these facts of katagenetic order that
  1222. physico-chemistry deals--that is, in short, with the dead and not with
  1223. the living.[15] The other kind of facts certainly seem to defy
  1224. physico-chemical analysis, even if they are not anagenetic in the proper
  1225. sense of the word. As for the artificial imitation of the outward
  1226. appearance of protoplasm, should a real theoretic importance be attached
  1227. to this when the question of the physical framework of protoplasm is not
  1228. yet settled? We are still further from compounding protoplasm
  1229. chemically. Finally, a physico-chemical explanation of the motions of
  1230. the amoeba, and _a fortiori_ of the behavior of the Infusoria, seems
  1231. impossible to many of those who have closely observed these rudimentary
  1232. organisms. Even in these humblest manifestations of life they discover
  1233. traces of an effective psychological activity.[16] But instructive above
  1234. all is the fact that the tendency to explain everything by physics and
  1235. chemistry is discouraged rather than strengthened by deep study of
  1236. histological phenomena. Such is the conclusion of the truly admirable
  1237. book which the histologist E.B. Wilson has devoted to the development
  1238. of the cell: "The study of the cell has, on the whole, seemed to widen
  1239. rather than to narrow the enormous gap that separates even the lowest
  1240. forms of life from the inorganic world.[17]"
  1241. To sum up, those who are concerned only with the functional activity of
  1242. the living being are inclined to believe that physics and chemistry will
  1243. give us the key to biological processes.[18] They have chiefly to do, as
  1244. a fact, with phenomena that are _repeated_ continually in the living
  1245. being, as in a chemical retort. This explains, in some measure, the
  1246. mechanistic tendencies of physiology. On the contrary, those whose
  1247. attention is concentrated on the minute structure of living tissues, on
  1248. their genesis and evolution, histologists and embryogenists on the one
  1249. hand, naturalists on the other, are interested in the retort itself, not
  1250. merely in its contents. They find that this retort creates its own form
  1251. through a _unique_ series of acts that really constitute a _history_.
  1252. Thus, histologists, embryogenists, and naturalists believe far less
  1253. readily than physiologists in the physico-chemical character of vital
  1254. actions.
  1255. The fact is, neither one nor the other of these two theories, neither
  1256. that which affirms nor that which denies the possibility of chemically
  1257. producing an elementary organism, can claim the authority of experiment.
  1258. They are both unverifiable, the former because science has not yet
  1259. advanced a step toward the chemical synthesis of a living substance, the
  1260. second because there is no conceivable way of proving experimentally the
  1261. impossibility of a fact. But we have set forth the theoretical reasons
  1262. which prevent us from likening the living being, a system closed off by
  1263. nature, to the systems which our science isolates. These reasons have
  1264. less force, we acknowledge, in the case of a rudimentary organism like
  1265. the amoeba, which hardly evolves at all. But they acquire more when we
  1266. consider a complex organism which goes through a regular cycle of
  1267. transformations. The more duration marks the living being with its
  1268. imprint, the more obviously the organism differs from a mere mechanism,
  1269. over which duration glides without penetrating. And the demonstration
  1270. has most force when it applies to the evolution of life as a whole, from
  1271. its humblest origins to its highest forms, inasmuch as this evolution
  1272. constitutes, through the unity and continuity of the animated matter
  1273. which supports it, a single indivisible history. Thus viewed, the
  1274. evolutionist hypothesis does not seem so closely akin to the mechanistic
  1275. conception of life as it is generally supposed to be. Of this
  1276. mechanistic conception we do not claim, of course, to furnish a
  1277. mathematical and final refutation. But the refutation which we draw from
  1278. the consideration of real time, and which is, in our opinion, the only
  1279. refutation possible, becomes the more rigorous and cogent the more
  1280. frankly the evolutionist hypothesis is assumed. We must dwell a good
  1281. deal more on this point. But let us first show more clearly the notion
  1282. of life to which we are leading up.
  1283. The mechanistic explanations, we said, hold good for the systems that
  1284. our thought artificially detaches from the whole. But of the whole
  1285. itself and of the systems which, within this whole, seem to take after
  1286. it, we cannot admit _a priori_ that they are mechanically explicable,
  1287. for then time would be useless, and even unreal. The essence of
  1288. mechanical explanation, in fact, is to regard the future and the past as
  1289. calculable functions of the present, and thus to claim that _all is
  1290. given_. On this hypothesis, past, present and future would be open at a
  1291. glance to a superhuman intellect capable of making the calculation.
  1292. Indeed, the scientists who have believed in the universality and
  1293. perfect objectivity of mechanical explanations have, consciously or
  1294. unconsciously, acted on a hypothesis of this kind. Laplace formulated it
  1295. with the greatest precision: "An intellect which at a given instant knew
  1296. all the forces with which nature is animated, and the respective
  1297. situations of the beings that compose nature--supposing the said
  1298. intellect were vast enough to subject these data to analysis--would
  1299. embrace in the same formula the motions of the greatest bodies in the
  1300. universe and those of the slightest atom: nothing would be uncertain for
  1301. it, and the future, like the past, would be present to its eyes."[19]
  1302. And Du Bois-Reymond: "We can imagine the knowledge of nature arrived at
  1303. a point where the universal process of the world might be represented by
  1304. a single mathematical formula, by one immense system of simultaneous
  1305. differential equations, from which could be deduced, for each moment,
  1306. the position, direction, and velocity of every atom of the world."[20]
  1307. Huxley has expressed the same idea in a more concrete form: "If the
  1308. fundamental proposition of evolution is true, that the entire world,
  1309. living and not living, is the result of the mutual interaction,
  1310. according to definite laws, of the forces possessed by the molecules of
  1311. which the primitive nebulosity of the universe was composed, it is no
  1312. less certain that the existing world lay, potentially, in the cosmic
  1313. vapor, and that a sufficient intellect could, from a knowledge of the
  1314. properties of the molecules of that vapor, have predicted, say the state
  1315. of the Fauna of Great Britain in 1869, with as much certainty as one can
  1316. say what will happen to the vapor of the breath in a cold winter's day."
  1317. In such a doctrine, time is still spoken of: one pronounces the word,
  1318. but one does not think of the thing. For time is here deprived of
  1319. efficacy, and if it _does_ nothing, it _is_ nothing. Radical mechanism
  1320. implies a metaphysic in which the totality of the real is postulated
  1321. complete in eternity, and in which the apparent duration of things
  1322. expresses merely the infirmity of a mind that cannot know everything at
  1323. once. But duration is something very different from this for our
  1324. consciousness, that is to say, for that which is most indisputable in
  1325. our experience. We perceive duration as a stream against which we cannot
  1326. go. It is the foundation of our being, and, as we feel, the very
  1327. substance of the world in which we live. It is of no use to hold up
  1328. before our eyes the dazzling prospect of a universal mathematic; we
  1329. cannot sacrifice experience to the requirements of a system. That is why
  1330. we reject radical mechanism.
  1331. * * * * *
  1332. But radical finalism is quite as unacceptable, and for the same reason.
  1333. The doctrine of teleology, in its extreme form, as we find it in Leibniz
  1334. for example, implies that things and beings merely realize a programme
  1335. previously arranged. But if there is nothing unforeseen, no invention or
  1336. creation in the universe, time is useless again. As in the mechanistic
  1337. hypothesis, here again it is supposed that _all is given_. Finalism thus
  1338. understood is only inverted mechanism. It springs from the same
  1339. postulate, with this sole difference, that in the movement of our finite
  1340. intellects along successive things, whose successiveness is reduced to a
  1341. mere appearance, it holds in front of us the light with which it claims
  1342. to guide us, instead of putting it behind. It substitutes the attraction
  1343. of the future for the impulsion of the past. But succession remains none
  1344. the less a mere appearance, as indeed does movement itself. In the
  1345. doctrine of Leibniz, time is reduced to a confused perception, relative
  1346. to the human standpoint, a perception which would vanish, like a rising
  1347. mist, for a mind seated at the centre of things.
  1348. Yet finalism is not, like mechanism, a doctrine with fixed rigid
  1349. outlines. It admits of as many inflections as we like. The mechanistic
  1350. philosophy is to be taken or left: it must be left if the least grain of
  1351. dust, by straying from the path foreseen by mechanics, should show the
  1352. slightest trace of spontaneity. The doctrine of final causes, on the
  1353. contrary, will never be definitively refuted. If one form of it be put
  1354. aside, it will take another. Its principle, which is essentially
  1355. psychological, is very flexible. It is so extensible, and thereby so
  1356. comprehensive, that one accepts something of it as soon as one rejects
  1357. pure mechanism. The theory we shall put forward in this book will
  1358. therefore necessarily partake of finalism to a certain extent. For that
  1359. reason it is important to intimate exactly what we are going to take of
  1360. it, and what we mean to leave.
  1361. Let us say at once that to thin out the Leibnizian finalism by breaking
  1362. it into an infinite number of pieces seems to us a step in the wrong
  1363. direction. This is, however, the tendency of the doctrine of finality.
  1364. It fully realizes that if the universe as a whole is the carrying out of
  1365. a plan, this cannot be demonstrated empirically, and that even of the
  1366. organized world alone it is hardly easier to prove all harmonious: facts
  1367. would equally well testify to the contrary. Nature sets living beings at
  1368. discord with one another. She everywhere presents disorder alongside of
  1369. order, retrogression alongside of progress. But, though finality cannot
  1370. be affirmed either of the whole of matter or of the whole of life, might
  1371. it not yet be true, says the finalist, of each organism taken
  1372. separately? Is there not a wonderful division of labor, a marvellous
  1373. solidarity among the parts of an organism, perfect order in infinite
  1374. complexity? Does not each living being thus realize a plan immanent in
  1375. its substance?--This theory consists, at bottom, in breaking up the
  1376. original notion of finality into bits. It does not accept, indeed it
  1377. ridicules, the idea of an _external_ finality, according to which living
  1378. beings are ordered with regard to each other: to suppose the grass made
  1379. for the cow, the lamb for the wolf--that is all acknowledged to be
  1380. absurd. But there is, we are told, an _internal_ finality: each being is
  1381. made for itself, all its parts conspire for the greatest good of the
  1382. whole and are intelligently organized in view of that end. Such is the
  1383. notion of finality which has long been classic. Finalism has shrunk to
  1384. the point of never embracing more than one living being at a time. By
  1385. making itself smaller, it probably thought it would offer less surface
  1386. for blows.
  1387. The truth is, it lay open to them a great deal more. Radical as our own
  1388. theory may appear, finality is external or it is nothing at all.
  1389. Consider the most complex and the most harmonious organism. All the
  1390. elements, we are told, conspire for the greatest good of the whole. Very
  1391. well, but let us not forget that each of these elements may itself be an
  1392. organism in certain cases, and that in subordinating the existence of
  1393. this small organism to the life of the great one we accept the principle
  1394. of an _external_ finality. The idea of a finality that is _always_
  1395. internal is therefore a self-destructive notion. An organism is composed
  1396. of tissues, each of which lives for itself. The cells of which the
  1397. tissues are made have also a certain independence. Strictly speaking, if
  1398. the subordination of all the elements of the individual to the
  1399. individual itself were complete, we might contend that they are not
  1400. organisms, reserve the name organism for the individual, and recognize
  1401. only internal finality. But every one knows that these elements may
  1402. possess a true autonomy. To say nothing of phagocytes, which push
  1403. independence to the point of attacking the organism that nourishes them,
  1404. or of germinal cells, which have their own life alongside the somatic
  1405. cells--the facts of regeneration are enough: here an element or a group
  1406. of elements suddenly reveals that, however limited its normal space and
  1407. function, it can transcend them occasionally; it may even, in certain
  1408. cases, be regarded as the equivalent of the whole.
  1409. There lies the stumbling-block of the vitalistic theories. We shall not
  1410. reproach them, as is ordinarily done, with replying to the question by
  1411. the question itself: the "vital principle" may indeed not explain much,
  1412. but it is at least a sort of label affixed to our ignorance, so as to
  1413. remind us of this occasionally,[21] while mechanism invites us to ignore
  1414. that ignorance. But the position of vitalism is rendered very difficult
  1415. by the fact that, in nature, there is neither purely internal finality
  1416. nor absolutely distinct individuality. The organized elements composing
  1417. the individual have themselves a certain individuality, and each will
  1418. claim its vital principle if the individual pretends to have its own.
  1419. But, on the other hand, the individual itself is not sufficiently
  1420. independent, not sufficiently cut off from other things, for us to allow
  1421. it a "vital principle" of its own. An organism such as a higher
  1422. vertebrate is the most individuated of all organisms; yet, if we take
  1423. into account that it is only the development of an ovum forming part of
  1424. the body of its mother and of a spermatozoon belonging to the body of
  1425. its father, that the egg (_i.e._ the ovum fertilized) is a connecting
  1426. link between the two progenitors since it is common to their two
  1427. substances, we shall realize that every individual organism, even that
  1428. of a man, is merely a bud that has sprouted on the combined body of both
  1429. its parents. Where, then, does the vital principle of the individual
  1430. begin or end? Gradually we shall be carried further and further back, up
  1431. to the individual's remotest ancestors: we shall find him solidary with
  1432. each of them, solidary with that little mass of protoplasmic jelly which
  1433. is probably at the root of the genealogical tree of life. Being, to a
  1434. certain extent, one with this primitive ancestor, he is also solidary
  1435. with all that descends from the ancestor in divergent directions. In
  1436. this sense each individual may be said to remain united with the
  1437. totality of living beings by invisible bonds. So it is of no use to try
  1438. to restrict finality to the individuality of the living being. If there
  1439. is finality in the world of life, it includes the whole of life in a
  1440. single indivisible embrace. This life common to all the living
  1441. undoubtedly presents many gaps and incoherences, and again it is not so
  1442. mathematically _one_ that it cannot allow each being to become
  1443. individualized to a certain degree. But it forms a single whole, none
  1444. the less; and we have to choose between the out-and-out negation of
  1445. finality and the hypothesis which co-ordinates not only the parts of an
  1446. organism with the organism itself, but also each living being with the
  1447. collective whole of all others.
  1448. Finality will not go down any easier for being taken as a powder. Either
  1449. the hypothesis of a finality immanent in life should be rejected as a
  1450. whole, or it must undergo a treatment very different from pulverization.
  1451. * * * * *
  1452. The error of radical finalism, as also that of radical mechanism, is to
  1453. extend too far the application of certain concepts that are natural to
  1454. our intellect. Originally, we think only in order to act. Our intellect
  1455. has been cast in the mold of action. Speculation is a luxury, while
  1456. action is a necessity. Now, in order to act, we begin by proposing an
  1457. end; we make a plan, then we go on to the detail of the mechanism which
  1458. will bring it to pass. This latter operation is possible only if we know
  1459. what we can reckon on. We must therefore have managed to extract
  1460. resemblances from nature, which enable us to anticipate the future. Thus
  1461. we must, consciously or unconsciously, have made use of the law of
  1462. causality. Moreover, the more sharply the idea of efficient causality is
  1463. defined in our mind, the more it takes the form of a _mechanical_
  1464. causality. And this scheme, in its turn, is the more mathematical
  1465. according as it expresses a more rigorous necessity. That is why we have
  1466. only to follow the bent of our mind to become mathematicians. But, on
  1467. the other hand, this natural mathematics is only the rigid unconscious
  1468. skeleton beneath our conscious supple habit of linking the same causes
  1469. to the same effects; and the usual object of this habit is to guide
  1470. actions inspired by intentions, or, what comes to the same, to direct
  1471. movements combined with a view to reproducing a pattern. We are born
  1472. artisans as we are born geometricians, and indeed we are geometricians
  1473. only because we are artisans. Thus the human intellect, inasmuch as it
  1474. is fashioned for the needs of human action, is an intellect which
  1475. proceeds at the same time by intention and by calculation, by adapting
  1476. means to ends and by thinking out mechanisms of more and more
  1477. geometrical form. Whether nature be conceived as an immense machine
  1478. regulated by mathematical laws, or as the realization of a plan, these
  1479. two ways of regarding it are only the consummation of two tendencies of
  1480. mind which are complementary to each other, and which have their origin
  1481. in the same vital necessities.
  1482. For that reason, radical finalism is very near radical mechanism on many
  1483. points. Both doctrines are reluctant to see in the course of things
  1484. generally, or even simply in the development of life, an unforeseeable
  1485. creation of form. In considering reality, mechanism regards only the
  1486. aspect of similarity or repetition. It is therefore dominated by this
  1487. law, that in nature there is only _like_ reproducing _like_. The more
  1488. the geometry in mechanism is emphasized, the less can mechanism admit
  1489. that anything is ever created, even pure form. In so far as we are
  1490. geometricians, then, we reject the unforeseeable. We might accept it,
  1491. assuredly, in so far as we are artists, for art lives on creation and
  1492. implies a latent belief in the spontaneity of nature. But disinterested
  1493. art is a luxury, like pure speculation. Long before being artists, we
  1494. are artisans; and all fabrication, however rudimentary, lives on
  1495. likeness and repetition, like the natural geometry which serves as its
  1496. fulcrum. Fabrication works on models which it sets out to reproduce; and
  1497. even when it invents, it proceeds, or imagines itself to proceed, by a
  1498. new arrangement of elements already known. Its principle is that "we
  1499. must have like to produce like." In short, the strict application of the
  1500. principle of finality, like that of the principle of mechanical
  1501. causality, leads to the conclusion that "all is given." Both principles
  1502. say the same thing in their respective languages, because they respond
  1503. to the same need.
  1504. That is why again they agree in doing away with time. Real duration is
  1505. that duration which gnaws on things, and leaves on them the mark of its
  1506. tooth. If everything is in time, everything changes inwardly, and the
  1507. same concrete reality never recurs. Repetition is therefore possible
  1508. only in the abstract: what is repeated is some aspect that our senses,
  1509. and especially our intellect, have singled out from reality, just
  1510. because our action, upon which all the effort of our intellect is
  1511. directed, can move only among repetitions. Thus, concentrated on that
  1512. which repeats, solely preoccupied in welding the same to the same,
  1513. intellect turns away from the vision of time. It dislikes what is fluid,
  1514. and solidifies everything it touches. We do not _think_ real time. But
  1515. we _live_ it, because life transcends intellect. The feeling we have of
  1516. our evolution and of the evolution of all things in pure duration is
  1517. there, forming around the intellectual concept properly so-called an
  1518. indistinct fringe that fades off into darkness. Mechanism and finalism
  1519. agree in taking account only of the bright nucleus shining in the
  1520. centre. They forget that this nucleus has been formed out of the rest by
  1521. condensation, and that the whole must be used, the fluid as well as and
  1522. more than the condensed, in order to grasp the inner movement of life.
  1523. Indeed, if the fringe exists, however delicate and indistinct, it should
  1524. have more importance for philosophy than the bright nucleus it
  1525. surrounds. For it is its presence that enables us to affirm that the
  1526. nucleus is a nucleus, that pure intellect is a contraction, by
  1527. condensation, of a more extensive power. And, just because this vague
  1528. intuition is of no help in directing our action on things, which action
  1529. takes place exclusively on the surface of reality, we may presume that
  1530. it is to be exercised not merely on the surface, but below.
  1531. As soon as we go out of the encasings in which radical mechanism and
  1532. radical finalism confine our thought, reality appears as a ceaseless
  1533. upspringing of something new, which has no sooner arisen to make the
  1534. present than it has already fallen back into the past; at this exact
  1535. moment it falls under the glance of the intellect, whose eyes are ever
  1536. turned to the rear. This is already the case with our inner life. For
  1537. each of our acts we shall easily find antecedents of which it may in
  1538. some sort be said to be the mechanical resultant. And it may equally
  1539. well be said that each action is the realization of an intention. In
  1540. this sense mechanism is everywhere, and finality everywhere, in the
  1541. evolution of our conduct. But if our action be one that involves the
  1542. whole of our person and is truly ours, it could not have been foreseen,
  1543. even though its antecedents explain it when once it has been
  1544. accomplished. And though it be the realizing of an intention, it
  1545. differs, as a present and _new_ reality, from the intention, which can
  1546. never aim at anything but recommencing or rearranging the past.
  1547. Mechanism and finalism are therefore, here, only external views of our
  1548. conduct. They extract its intellectuality. But our conduct slips between
  1549. them and extends much further. Once again, this does not mean that free
  1550. action is capricious, unreasonable action. To behave according to
  1551. caprice is to oscillate mechanically between two or more ready-made
  1552. alternatives and at length to settle on one of them; it is no real
  1553. maturing of an internal state, no real evolution; it is merely--however
  1554. paradoxical the assertion may seem--bending the will to imitate the
  1555. mechanism of the intellect. A conduct that is truly our own, on the
  1556. contrary, is that of a will which does not try to counterfeit intellect,
  1557. and which, remaining itself--that is to say, evolving--ripens gradually
  1558. into acts which the intellect will be able to resolve indefinitely into
  1559. intelligible elements without ever reaching its goal. The free act is
  1560. incommensurable with the idea, and its "rationality" must be defined by
  1561. this very incommensurability, which admits the discovery of as much
  1562. intelligibility within it as we will. Such is the character of our own
  1563. evolution; and such also, without doubt, that of the evolution of life.
  1564. Our reason, incorrigibly presumptuous, imagines itself possessed, by
  1565. right of birth or by right of conquest, innate or acquired, of all the
  1566. essential elements of the knowledge of truth. Even where it confesses
  1567. that it does not know the object presented to it, it believes that its
  1568. ignorance consists only in not knowing which one of its time-honored
  1569. categories suits the new object. In what drawer, ready to open, shall we
  1570. put it? In what garment, already cut out, shall we clothe it? Is it
  1571. this, or that, or the other thing? And "this," and "that," and "the
  1572. other thing" are always something already conceived, already known. The
  1573. idea that for a new object we might have to create a new concept,
  1574. perhaps a new method of thinking, is deeply repugnant to us. The history
  1575. of philosophy is there, however, and shows us the eternal conflict of
  1576. systems, the impossibility of satisfactorily getting the real into the
  1577. ready-made garments of our ready-made concepts, the necessity of making
  1578. to measure. But, rather than go to this extremity, our reason prefers to
  1579. announce once for all, with a proud modesty, that it has to do only with
  1580. the relative, and that the absolute is not in its province. This
  1581. preliminary declaration enables it to apply its habitual method of
  1582. thought without any scruple, and thus, under pretense that it does not
  1583. touch the absolute, to make absolute judgments upon everything. Plato
  1584. was the first to set up the theory that to know the real consists in
  1585. finding its Idea, that is to say, in forcing it into a pre-existing
  1586. frame already at our disposal--as if we implicitly possessed universal
  1587. knowledge. But this belief is natural to the human intellect, always
  1588. engaged as it is in determining under what former heading it shall
  1589. catalogue any new object; and it may be said that, in a certain sense,
  1590. we are all born Platonists.
  1591. Nowhere is the inadequacy of this method so obvious as in theories of
  1592. life. If, in evolving in the direction of the vertebrates in general, of
  1593. man and intellect in particular, life has had to abandon by the way many
  1594. elements incompatible with this particular mode of organization and
  1595. consign them, as we shall show, to other lines of development, it is the
  1596. totality of these elements that we must find again and rejoin to the
  1597. intellect proper, in order to grasp the true nature of vital activity.
  1598. And we shall probably be aided in this by the fringe of vague intuition
  1599. that surrounds our distinct--that is, intellectual--representation. For
  1600. what can this useless fringe be, if not that part of the evolving
  1601. principle which has not shrunk to the peculiar form of our organization,
  1602. but has settled around it unasked for, unwanted? It is there,
  1603. accordingly, that we must look for hints to expand the intellectual form
  1604. of our thought; from there shall we derive the impetus necessary to lift
  1605. us above ourselves. To form an idea of the whole of life cannot consist
  1606. in combining simple ideas that have been left behind in us by life
  1607. itself in the course of its evolution. How could the part be equivalent
  1608. to the whole, the content to the container, a by-product of the vital
  1609. operation to the operation itself? Such, however, is our illusion when
  1610. we define the evolution of life as a "passage from the homogeneous to
  1611. the heterogeneous," or by any other concept obtained by putting
  1612. fragments of intellect side by side. We place ourselves in one of the
  1613. points where evolution comes to a head--the principal one, no doubt, but
  1614. not the only one; and there we do not even take all we find, for of the
  1615. intellect we keep only one or two of the concepts by which it expresses
  1616. itself; and it is this part of a part that we declare representative of
  1617. the whole, of something indeed which goes beyond the concrete whole, I
  1618. mean of the evolution movement of which this "whole" is only the present
  1619. stage! The truth is, that to represent this the entire intellect would
  1620. not be too much--nay, it would not be enough. It would be necessary to
  1621. add to it what we find in every other terminal point of evolution. And
  1622. these diverse and divergent elements must be considered as so many
  1623. extracts which are, or at least which were, in their humblest form,
  1624. mutually complementary. Only then might we have an inkling of the real
  1625. nature of the evolution movement; and even then we should fail to grasp
  1626. it completely, for we should still be dealing only with the evolved,
  1627. which is a result, and not with evolution itself, which is the act by
  1628. which the result is obtained.
  1629. Such is the philosophy of life to which we are leading up. It claims to
  1630. transcend both mechanism and finalism; but, as we announced at the
  1631. beginning, it is nearer the second doctrine than the first. It will not
  1632. be amiss to dwell on this point, and show more precisely how far this
  1633. philosophy of life resembles finalism and wherein it is different.
  1634. Like radical finalism, although in a vaguer form, our philosophy
  1635. represents the organized world as a harmonious whole. But this harmony
  1636. is far from being as perfect as it has been claimed to be. It admits of
  1637. much discord, because each species, each individual even, retains only a
  1638. certain impetus from the universal vital impulsion and tends to use this
  1639. energy in its own interest. In this consists _adaptation_. The species
  1640. and the individual thus think only of themselves--whence arises a
  1641. possible conflict with other forms of life. Harmony, therefore, does
  1642. not exist in fact; it exists rather in principle; I mean that the
  1643. original impetus is a _common_ impetus, and the higher we ascend the
  1644. stream of life the more do diverse tendencies appear complementary to
  1645. each other. Thus the wind at a street-corner divides into diverging
  1646. currents which are all one and the same gust. Harmony, or rather
  1647. "complementarity," is revealed only in the mass, in tendencies rather
  1648. than in states. Especially (and this is the point on which finalism has
  1649. been most seriously mistaken) harmony is rather behind us than before.
  1650. It is due to an identity of impulsion and not to a common aspiration. It
  1651. would be futile to try to assign to life an end, in the human sense of
  1652. the word. To speak of an end is to think of a pre-existing model which
  1653. has only to be realized. It is to suppose, therefore, that all is given,
  1654. and that the future can be read in the present. It is to believe that
  1655. life, in its movement and in its entirety, goes to work like our
  1656. intellect, which is only a motionless and fragmentary view of life, and
  1657. which naturally takes its stand outside of time. Life, on the contrary,
  1658. progresses and _endures_ in time. Of course, when once the road has been
  1659. traveled, we can glance over it, mark its direction, note this in
  1660. psychological terms and speak as if there had been pursuit of an end.
  1661. Thus shall we speak ourselves. But, of the road which was going to be
  1662. traveled, the human mind could have nothing to say, for the road has
  1663. been created _pari passu_ with the act of traveling over it, being
  1664. nothing but the direction of this act itself. At every instant, then,
  1665. evolution must admit of a psychological interpretation which is, from
  1666. our point of view, the best interpretation; but this explanation has
  1667. neither value nor even significance except retrospectively. Never could
  1668. the finalistic interpretation, such as we shall propose it, be taken for
  1669. an anticipation of the future. It is a particular mode of viewing the
  1670. past in the light of the present. In short, the classic conception of
  1671. finality postulates at once too much and too little: it is both too wide
  1672. and too narrow. In explaining life by intellect, it limits too much the
  1673. meaning of life: intellect, such at least as we find it in ourselves,
  1674. has been fashioned by evolution during the course of progress; it is cut
  1675. out of something larger, or, rather, it is only the projection,
  1676. necessarily on a plane, of a reality that possesses both relief and
  1677. depth. It is this more comprehensive reality that true finalism ought to
  1678. reconstruct, or, rather, if possible, embrace in one view. But, on the
  1679. other hand, just because it goes beyond intellect--the faculty of
  1680. connecting the same with the same, of perceiving and also of producing
  1681. repetitions--this reality is undoubtedly creative, _i.e._ productive of
  1682. effects in which it expands and transcends its own being. These effects
  1683. were therefore not given in it in advance, and so it could not take them
  1684. for ends, although, when once produced, they admit of a rational
  1685. interpretation, like that of the manufactured article that has
  1686. reproduced a model. In short, the theory of final causes does not go far
  1687. enough when it confines itself to ascribing some intelligence to nature,
  1688. and it goes too far when it supposes a pre-existence of the future in
  1689. the present in the form of idea. And the second theory, which sins by
  1690. excess, is the outcome of the first, which sins by defect. In place of
  1691. intellect proper must be substituted the more comprehensive reality of
  1692. which intellect is only the contraction. The future then appears as
  1693. expanding the present: it was not, therefore, contained in the present
  1694. in the form of a represented end. And yet, once realized, it will
  1695. explain the present as much as the present explains it, and even more;
  1696. it must be viewed as an end as much as, and more than, a result. Our
  1697. intellect has a right to consider the future abstractly from its
  1698. habitual point of view, being itself an abstract view of the cause of
  1699. its own being.
  1700. It is true that the cause may then seem beyond our grasp. Already the
  1701. finalist theory of life eludes all precise verification. What if we go
  1702. beyond it in one of its directions? Here, in fact, after a necessary
  1703. digression, we are back at the question which we regard as essential:
  1704. can the insufficiency of mechanism be proved by facts? We said that if
  1705. this demonstration is possible, it is on condition of frankly accepting
  1706. the evolutionist hypothesis. We must now show that if mechanism is
  1707. insufficient to account for evolution, the way of proving this
  1708. insufficiency is not to stop at the classic conception of finality,
  1709. still less to contract or attenuate it, but, on the contrary, to go
  1710. further.
  1711. Let us indicate at once the principle of our demonstration. We said of
  1712. life that, from its origin, it is the continuation of one and the same
  1713. impetus, divided into divergent lines of evolution. Something has grown,
  1714. something has developed by a series of additions which have been so many
  1715. creations. This very development has brought about a dissociation of
  1716. tendencies which were unable to grow beyond a certain point without
  1717. becoming mutually incompatible. Strictly speaking, there is nothing to
  1718. prevent our imagining that the evolution of life might have taken place
  1719. in one single individual by means of a series of transformations spread
  1720. over thousands of ages. Or, instead of a single individual, any number
  1721. might be supposed, succeeding each other in a unilinear series. In both
  1722. cases evolution would have had, so to speak, one dimension only. But
  1723. evolution has actually taken place through millions of individuals, on
  1724. divergent lines, each ending at a crossing from which new paths radiate,
  1725. and so on indefinitely. If our hypothesis is justified, if the
  1726. essential causes working along these diverse roads are of psychological
  1727. nature, they must keep something in common in spite of the divergence of
  1728. their effects, as school-fellows long separated keep the same memories
  1729. of boyhood. Roads may fork or by-ways be opened along which dissociated
  1730. elements may evolve in an independent manner, but nevertheless it is in
  1731. virtue of the primitive impetus of the whole that the movement of the
  1732. parts continues. Something of the whole, therefore, must abide in the
  1733. parts; and this common element will be evident to us in some way,
  1734. perhaps by the presence of identical organs in very different organisms.
  1735. Suppose, for an instant, that the mechanistic explanation is the true
  1736. one: evolution must then have occurred through a series of accidents
  1737. added to one another, each new accident being preserved by selection if
  1738. it is advantageous to that sum of former advantageous accidents which
  1739. the present form of the living being represents. What likelihood is
  1740. there that, by two entirely different series of accidents being added
  1741. together, two entirely different evolutions will arrive at similar
  1742. results? The more two lines of evolution diverge, the less probability
  1743. is there that accidental outer influences or accidental inner variations
  1744. bring about the construction of the same apparatus upon them, especially
  1745. if there was no trace of this apparatus at the moment of divergence. But
  1746. such similarity of the two products would be natural, on the contrary,
  1747. on a hypothesis like ours: even in the latest channel there would be
  1748. something of the impulsion received at the source. _Pure mechanism,
  1749. then, would be refutable, and finality, in the special sense in which we
  1750. understand it, would be demonstrable in a certain aspect, if it could be
  1751. proved that life may manufacture the like apparatus, by unlike means, on
  1752. divergent lines of evolution; and the strength of the proof would be
  1753. proportional both to the divergency between the lines of evolution thus
  1754. chosen and to the complexity of the similar structures found in them._
  1755. It will be said that resemblance of structure is due to sameness of the
  1756. general conditions in which life has evolved, and that these permanent
  1757. outer conditions may have imposed the same direction on the forces
  1758. constructing this or that apparatus, in spite of the diversity of
  1759. transient outer influences and accidental inner changes. We are not, of
  1760. course, blind to the rôle which the concept of _adaptation_ plays in the
  1761. science of to-day. Biologists certainly do not all make the same use of
  1762. it. Some think the outer conditions capable of causing change in
  1763. organisms in a _direct_ manner, in a definite direction, through
  1764. physico-chemical alterations induced by them in the living substance;
  1765. such is the hypothesis of Eimer, for example. Others, more faithful to
  1766. the spirit of Darwinism, believe the influence of conditions works
  1767. _indirectly_ only, through favoring, in the struggle for life, those
  1768. representatives of a species which the chance of birth has best adapted
  1769. to the environment. In other words, some attribute a _positive_
  1770. influence to outer conditions, and say that they actually _give rise to_
  1771. variations, while the others say these conditions have only a _negative_
  1772. influence and merely _eliminate_ variations. But, in both cases, the
  1773. outer conditions are supposed to bring about a precise adjustment of the
  1774. organism to its circumstances. Both parties, then, will attempt to
  1775. explain mechanically, by adaptation to similar conditions, the
  1776. similarities of structure which we think are the strongest argument
  1777. against mechanism. So we must at once indicate in a general way, before
  1778. passing to the detail, why explanations from "adaptation" seem to us
  1779. insufficient.
  1780. Let us first remark that, of the two hypotheses just described, the
  1781. latter is the only one which is not equivocal. The Darwinian idea of
  1782. adaptation by automatic elimination of the unadapted is a simple and
  1783. clear idea. But, just because it attributes to the outer cause which
  1784. controls evolution a merely negative influence, it has great difficulty
  1785. in accounting for the progressive and, so to say, rectilinear
  1786. development of complex apparatus such as we are about to examine. How
  1787. much greater will this difficulty be in the case of the similar
  1788. structure of two extremely complex organs on two entirely different
  1789. lines of evolution! An accidental variation, however minute, implies the
  1790. working of a great number of small physical and chemical causes. An
  1791. accumulation of accidental variations, such as would be necessary to
  1792. produce a complex structure, requires therefore the concurrence of an
  1793. almost infinite number of infinitesimal causes. Why should these causes,
  1794. entirely accidental, recur the same, and in the same order, at different
  1795. points of space and time? No one will hold that this is the case, and
  1796. the Darwinian himself will probably merely maintain that identical
  1797. effects may arise from different causes, that more than one road leads
  1798. to the same spot. But let us not be fooled by a metaphor. The place
  1799. reached does not give the form of the road that leads there; while an
  1800. organic structure is just the accumulation of those small differences
  1801. which evolution has had to go through in order to achieve it. The
  1802. struggle for life and natural selection can be of no use to us in
  1803. solving this part of the problem, for we are not concerned here with
  1804. what has perished, we have to do only with what has survived. Now, we
  1805. see that identical structures have been formed on independent lines of
  1806. evolution by a gradual accumulation of effects. How can accidental
  1807. causes, occurring in an accidental order, be supposed to have repeatedly
  1808. come to the same result, the causes being infinitely numerous and the
  1809. effect infinitely complicated?
  1810. The principle of mechanism is that "the same causes produce the same
  1811. effects." This principle, of course, does not always imply that the same
  1812. effects must have the same causes; but it does involve this consequence
  1813. in the particular case in which the causes remain visible in the effect
  1814. that they produce and are indeed its constitutive elements. That two
  1815. walkers starting from different points and wandering at random should
  1816. finally meet, is no great wonder. But that, throughout their walk, they
  1817. should describe two identical curves exactly superposable on each other,
  1818. is altogether unlikely. The improbability will be the greater, the more
  1819. complicated the routes; and it will become impossibility, if the zigzags
  1820. are infinitely complicated. Now, what is this complexity of zigzags as
  1821. compared with that of an organ in which thousands of different cells,
  1822. each being itself a kind of organism, are arranged in a definite order?
  1823. Let us turn, then, to the other hypothesis, and see how it would solve
  1824. the problem. Adaptation, it says, is not merely elimination of the
  1825. unadapted; it is due to the positive influence of outer conditions that
  1826. have molded the organism on their own form. This time, similarity of
  1827. effects will be explained by similarity of cause. We shall remain,
  1828. apparently, in pure mechanism. But if we look closely, we shall see that
  1829. the explanation is merely verbal, that we are again the dupes of words,
  1830. and that the trick of the solution consists in taking the term
  1831. "adaptation" in two entirely different senses at the same time.
  1832. If I pour into the same glass, by turns, water and wine, the two liquids
  1833. will take the same form, and the sameness in form will be due to the
  1834. sameness in adaptation of content to container. Adaptation, here, really
  1835. means mechanical adjustment. The reason is that the form to which the
  1836. matter has adapted itself was there, ready-made, and has forced its own
  1837. shape on the matter. But, in the adaptation of an organism to the
  1838. circumstances it has to live in, where is the pre-existing form awaiting
  1839. its matter? The circumstances are not a mold into which life is inserted
  1840. and whose form life adopts: this is indeed to be fooled by a metaphor.
  1841. There is no form yet, and the life must create a form for itself, suited
  1842. to the circumstances which are made for it. It will have to make the
  1843. best of these circumstances, neutralize their inconveniences and utilize
  1844. their advantages--in short, respond to outer actions by building up a
  1845. machine which has no resemblance to them. Such adapting is not
  1846. _repeating_, but _replying_,--an entirely different thing. If there is
  1847. still adaptation, it will be in the sense in which one may say of the
  1848. solution of a problem of geometry, for example, that it is adapted to
  1849. the conditions. I grant indeed that adaptation so understood explains
  1850. why different evolutionary processes result in similar forms: the same
  1851. problem, of course, calls for the same solution. But it is necessary
  1852. then to introduce, as for the solution of a problem of geometry, an
  1853. intelligent activity, or at least a cause which behaves in the same way.
  1854. This is to bring in finality again, and a finality this time more than
  1855. ever charged with anthropomorphic elements. In a word, if the adaptation
  1856. is passive, if it is mere repetition in the relief of what the
  1857. conditions give in the mold, it will build up nothing that one tries to
  1858. make it build; and if it is active, capable of responding by a
  1859. calculated solution to the problem which is set out in the conditions,
  1860. that is going further than we do--too far, indeed, in our opinion--in
  1861. the direction we indicated in the beginning. But the truth is that there
  1862. is a surreptitious passing from one of these two meanings to the other,
  1863. a flight for refuge to the first whenever one is about to be caught _in
  1864. flagrante delicto_ of finalism by employing the second. It is really
  1865. the second which serves the usual practice of science, but it is the
  1866. first that generally provides its philosophy. In any _particular_ case
  1867. one talks as if the process of adaptation were an effort of the organism
  1868. to build up a machine capable of turning external circumstances to the
  1869. best possible account: then one speaks of adaptation _in general_ as if
  1870. it were the very impress of circumstances, passively received by an
  1871. indifferent matter.
  1872. But let us come to the examples. It would be interesting first to
  1873. institute here a general comparison between plants and animals. One
  1874. cannot fail to be struck with the parallel progress which has been
  1875. accomplished, on both sides, in the direction of sexuality. Not only is
  1876. fecundation itself the same in higher plants and in animals, since it
  1877. consists, in both, in the union of two nuclei that differ in their
  1878. properties and structure before their union and immediately after become
  1879. equivalent to each other; but the preparation of sexual elements goes on
  1880. in both under like conditions: it consists essentially in the reduction
  1881. of the number of chromosomes and the rejection of a certain quantity of
  1882. chromatic substance.[22] Yet vegetables and animals have evolved on
  1883. independent lines, favored by unlike circumstances, opposed by unlike
  1884. obstacles. Here are two great series which have gone on diverging. On
  1885. either line, thousands and thousands of causes have combined to
  1886. determine the morphological and functional evolution. Yet these
  1887. infinitely complicated causes have been consummated, in each series, in
  1888. the same effect. And this effect, could hardly be called a phenomenon of
  1889. "adaptation": where is the adaptation, where is the pressure of external
  1890. circumstances? There is no striking utility in sexual generation; it
  1891. has been interpreted in the most diverse ways; and some very acute
  1892. enquirers even regard the sexuality of the plant, at least, as a luxury
  1893. which nature might have dispensed with.[23] But we do not wish to dwell
  1894. on facts so disputed. The ambiguity of the term "adaptation," and the
  1895. necessity of transcending both the point of view of mechanical causality
  1896. and that of anthropomorphic finality, will stand out more clearly with
  1897. simpler examples. At all times the doctrine of finality has laid much
  1898. stress on the marvellous structure of the sense-organs, in order to
  1899. liken the work of nature to that of an intelligent workman. Now, since
  1900. these organs are found, in a rudimentary state, in the lower animals,
  1901. and since nature offers us many intermediaries between the pigment-spot
  1902. of the simplest organisms and the infinitely complex eye of the
  1903. vertebrates, it may just as well be alleged that the result has been
  1904. brought about by natural selection perfecting the organ automatically.
  1905. In short, if there is a case in which it seems justifiable to invoke
  1906. adaptation, it is this particular one. For there may be discussion about
  1907. the function and meaning of such a thing as sexual generation, in so far
  1908. as it is related to the conditions in which it occurs; but the relation
  1909. of the eye to light is obvious, and when we call this relation an
  1910. adaptation, we must know what we mean. If, then, we can show, in this
  1911. privileged case, the insufficiency of the principles invoked on both
  1912. sides, our demonstration will at once have reached a high degree of
  1913. generality.
  1914. Let us consider the example on which the advocates of finality have
  1915. always insisted: the structure of such an organ as the human eye. They
  1916. have had no difficulty in showing that in this extremely complicated
  1917. apparatus all the elements are marvelously co-ordinated. In order that
  1918. vision shall operate, says the author of a well-known book on _Final
  1919. Causes_, "the sclerotic membrane must become transparent in one point of
  1920. its surface, so as to enable luminous rays to pierce it;... the cornea
  1921. must correspond exactly with the opening of the socket;... behind this
  1922. transparent opening there must be refracting media;... there must be a
  1923. retina[24] at the extremity of the dark chamber;... perpendicular to the
  1924. retina there must be an innumerable quantity of transparent cones
  1925. permitting only the light directed in the line of their axes to reach
  1926. the nervous membrane,"[25] etc. etc. In reply, the advocate of final
  1927. causes has been invited to assume the evolutionist hypothesis.
  1928. Everything is marvelous, indeed, if one consider an eye like ours, in
  1929. which thousands of elements are coördinated in a single function. But
  1930. take the function at its origin, in the Infusorian, where it is reduced
  1931. to the mere impressionability (almost purely chemical) of a pigment-spot
  1932. to light: this function, possibly only an accidental fact in the
  1933. beginning, may have brought about a slight complication of the organ,
  1934. which again induced an improvement of the function. It may have done
  1935. this either directly, through some unknown mechanism, or indirectly,
  1936. merely through the effect of the advantages it brought to the living
  1937. being and the hold it thus offered to natural selection. Thus the
  1938. progressive formation of an eye as well contrived as ours would be
  1939. explained by an almost infinite number of actions and reactions between
  1940. the function and the organ, without the intervention of other than
  1941. mechanical causes.
  1942. The question is hard to decide, indeed, when put directly between the
  1943. function and the organ, as is done in the doctrine of finality, as also
  1944. mechanism itself does. For organ and function are terms of different
  1945. nature, and each conditions the other so closely that it is impossible
  1946. to say _a priori_ whether in expressing their relation we should begin
  1947. with the first, as does mechanism, or with the second, as finalism
  1948. requires. But the discussion would take an entirely different turn, we
  1949. think, if we began by comparing together two terms of the same nature,
  1950. an organ with an organ, instead of an organ with its function. In this
  1951. case, it would be possible to proceed little by little to a solution
  1952. more and more plausible, and there would be the more chance of a
  1953. successful issue the more resolutely we assumed the evolutionist
  1954. hypothesis.
  1955. Let us place side by side the eye of a vertebrate and that of a mollusc
  1956. such as the common Pecten. We find the same essential parts in each,
  1957. composed of analogous elements. The eye of the Pecten presents a retina,
  1958. a cornea, a lens of cellular structure like our own. There is even that
  1959. peculiar inversion of retinal elements which is not met with, in
  1960. general, in the retina of the invertebrates. Now, the origin of molluscs
  1961. may be a debated question, but, whatever opinion we hold, all are agreed
  1962. that molluscs and vertebrates separated from their common parent-stem
  1963. long before the appearance of an eye so complex as that of the Pecten.
  1964. Whence, then, the structural analogy?
  1965. Let us question on this point the two opposed systems of evolutionist
  1966. explanation in turn--the hypothesis of purely accidental variations, and
  1967. that of a variation directed in a definite way under the influence of
  1968. external conditions.
  1969. The first, as is well known, is presented to-day in two quite different
  1970. forms. Darwin spoke of very slight variations being accumulated by
  1971. natural selection. He was not ignorant of the facts of sudden variation;
  1972. but he thought these "sports," as he called them, were only
  1973. monstrosities incapable of perpetuating themselves; and he accounted for
  1974. the genesis of species by an accumulation of _insensible_
  1975. variations.[26] Such is still the opinion of many naturalists. It is
  1976. tending, however, to give way to the opposite idea that a new species
  1977. comes into being all at once by the simultaneous appearance of several
  1978. new characters, all somewhat different from the previous ones. This
  1979. latter hypothesis, already proposed by various authors, notably by
  1980. Bateson in a remarkable book,[27] has become deeply significant and
  1981. acquired great force since the striking experiments of Hugo de Vries.
  1982. This botanist, working on the _OEnothera Lamarckiana_, obtained at the
  1983. end of a few generations a certain number of new species. The theory he
  1984. deduces from his experiments is of the highest interest. Species pass
  1985. through alternate periods of stability and transformation. When the
  1986. period of "mutability" occurs, unexpected forms spring forth in a great
  1987. number of different directions.[28]--We will not attempt to take sides
  1988. between this hypothesis and that of insensible variations. Indeed,
  1989. perhaps both are partly true. We wish merely to point out that if the
  1990. variations invoked are accidental, they do not, whether small or great,
  1991. account for a similarity of structure such as we have cited.
  1992. Let us assume, to begin with, the Darwinian theory of insensible
  1993. variations, and suppose the occurrence of small differences due to
  1994. chance, and continually accumulating. It must not be forgotten that all
  1995. the parts of an organism are necessarily coördinated. Whether the
  1996. function be the effect of the organ or its cause, it matters little; one
  1997. point is certain--the organ will be of no use and will not give
  1998. selection a hold unless it functions. However the minute structure of
  1999. the retina may develop, and however complicated it may become, such
  2000. progress, instead of favoring vision, will probably hinder it if the
  2001. visual centres do not develop at the same time, as well as several parts
  2002. of the visual organ itself. If the variations are accidental, how can
  2003. they ever agree to arise in every part of the organ at the same time, in
  2004. such way that the organ will continue to perform its function? Darwin
  2005. quite understood this; it is one of the reasons why he regarded
  2006. variation as insensible.[29] For a difference which arises accidentally
  2007. at one point of the visual apparatus, if it be very slight, will not
  2008. hinder the functioning of the organ; and hence this first accidental
  2009. variation can, in a sense, _wait for_ complementary variations to
  2010. accumulate and raise vision to a higher degree of perfection. Granted;
  2011. but while the insensible variation does not hinder the functioning of
  2012. the eye, neither does it help it, so long as the variations that are
  2013. complementary do not occur. How, in that case, can the variation be
  2014. retained by natural selection? Unwittingly one will reason as if the
  2015. slight variation were a toothing stone set up by the organism and
  2016. reserved for a later construction. This hypothesis, so little
  2017. conformable to the Darwinian principle, is difficult enough to avoid
  2018. even in the case of an organ which has been developed along one single
  2019. main line of evolution, _e.g._ the vertebrate eye. But it is absolutely
  2020. forced upon us when we observe the likeness of structure of the
  2021. vertebrate eye and that of the molluscs. How could the same small
  2022. variations, incalculable in number, have ever occurred in the same
  2023. order on two independent lines of evolution, if they were purely
  2024. accidental? And how could they have been preserved by selection and
  2025. accumulated in both cases, the same in the same order, when each of
  2026. them, taken separately, was of no use?
  2027. Let us turn, then, to the hypothesis of sudden variations, and see
  2028. whether it will solve the problem. It certainly lessens the difficulty
  2029. on one point, but it makes it much worse on another. If the eye of the
  2030. mollusc and that of the vertebrate have both been raised to their
  2031. present form by a relatively small number of sudden leaps, I have less
  2032. difficulty in understanding the resemblance of the two organs than if
  2033. this resemblance were due to an incalculable number of infinitesimal
  2034. resemblances acquired successively: in both cases it is chance that
  2035. operates, but in the second case chance is not required to work the
  2036. miracle it would have to perform in the first. Not only is the number of
  2037. resemblances to be added somewhat reduced, but I can also understand
  2038. better how each could be preserved and added to the others; for the
  2039. elementary variation is now considerable enough to be an advantage to
  2040. the living being, and so to lend itself to the play of selection. But
  2041. here there arises another problem, no less formidable, viz., how do all
  2042. the parts of the visual apparatus, suddenly changed, remain so well
  2043. coördinated that the eye continues to exercise its function? For the
  2044. change of one part alone will make vision impossible, unless this change
  2045. is absolutely infinitesimal. The parts must then all change at once,
  2046. each consulting the others. I agree that a great number of uncoördinated
  2047. variations may indeed have arisen in less fortunate individuals, that
  2048. natural selection may have eliminated these, and that only the
  2049. combination fit to endure, capable of preserving and improving vision,
  2050. has survived. Still, this combination had to be produced. And, supposing
  2051. chance to have granted this favor once, can we admit that it repeats the
  2052. self-same favor in the course of the history of a species, so as to give
  2053. rise, every time, all at once, to new complications marvelously
  2054. regulated with reference to each other, and so related to former
  2055. complications as to go further on in the same direction? How,
  2056. especially, can we suppose that by a series of mere "accidents" these
  2057. sudden variations occur, the same, in the same order,--involving in each
  2058. case a perfect harmony of elements more and more numerous and
  2059. complex--along two independent lines of evolution?
  2060. The law of correlation will be invoked, of course; Darwin himself
  2061. appealed to it.[30] It will be alleged that a change is not localized in
  2062. a single point of the organism, but has its necessary recoil on other
  2063. points. The examples cited by Darwin remain classic: white cats with
  2064. blue eyes are generally deaf; hairless dogs have imperfect dentition,
  2065. etc.--Granted; but let us not play now on the word "correlation." A
  2066. collective whole of _solidary_ changes is one thing, a system of
  2067. _complementary_ changes--changes so coördinated as to keep up and even
  2068. improve the functioning of an organ under more complicated
  2069. conditions--is another. That an anomaly of the pilous system should be
  2070. accompanied by an anomaly of dentition is quite conceivable without our
  2071. having to call for a special principle of explanation; for hair and
  2072. teeth are similar formations,[31] and the same chemical change of the
  2073. germ that hinders the formation of hair would probably obstruct that of
  2074. teeth: it may be for the same sort of reason that white cats with blue
  2075. eyes are deaf. In these different examples the "correlative" changes are
  2076. only _solidary_ changes (not to mention the fact that they are really
  2077. _lesions_, namely, diminutions or suppressions, and not additions, which
  2078. makes a great difference). But when we speak of "correlative" changes
  2079. occurring suddenly in the different parts of the eye, we use the word in
  2080. an entirely new sense: this time there is a whole set of changes not
  2081. only simultaneous, not only bound together by community of origin, but
  2082. so coördinated that the organ keeps on performing the same simple
  2083. function, and even performs it better. That a change in the germ, which
  2084. influences the formation of the retina, may affect at the same time also
  2085. the formation of the cornea, the iris, the lens, the visual centres,
  2086. etc., I admit, if necessary, although they are formations that differ
  2087. much more from one another in their original nature than do probably
  2088. hair and teeth. But that all these simultaneous changes should occur in
  2089. such a way as to improve or even merely maintain vision, this is what,
  2090. in the hypothesis of sudden variation, I cannot admit, unless a
  2091. mysterious principle is to come in, whose duty it is to watch over the
  2092. interest of the function. But this would be to give up the idea of
  2093. "accidental" variation. In reality, these two senses of the word
  2094. "correlation" are often interchanged in the mind of the biologist, just
  2095. like the two senses of the word "adaptation." And the confusion is
  2096. almost legitimate in botany, that science in which the theory of the
  2097. formation of species by sudden variation rests on the firmest
  2098. experimental basis. In vegetables, function is far less narrowly bound
  2099. to form than in animals. Even profound morphological differences, such
  2100. as a change in the form of leaves, have no appreciable influence on the
  2101. exercise of function, and so do not require a whole system of
  2102. complementary changes for the plant to remain fit to survive. But it is
  2103. not so in the animal, especially in the case of an organ like the eye, a
  2104. very complex structure and very delicate function. Here it is impossible
  2105. to identify changes that are simply solidary with changes which are also
  2106. complementary. The two senses of the word "correlation" must be
  2107. carefully distinguished; it would be a downright paralogism to adopt one
  2108. of them in the premisses of the reasoning, and the other in the
  2109. conclusion. And this is just what is done when the principle of
  2110. correlation is invoked in explanations of _detail_ in order to account
  2111. for complementary variations, and then correlation _in general_ is
  2112. spoken of as if it were any group of variations provoked by any
  2113. variation of the germ. Thus, the notion of correlation is first used in
  2114. current science as it might be used by an advocate of finality; it is
  2115. understood that this is only a convenient way of expressing oneself,
  2116. that one will correct it and fall back on pure mechanism when explaining
  2117. the nature of the principles and turning from science to philosophy. And
  2118. one does then come back to pure mechanism, but only by giving a new
  2119. meaning to the word "correlation"--a meaning which would now make
  2120. correlation inapplicable to the detail it is called upon to explain.
  2121. To sum up, if the accidental variations that bring about evolution are
  2122. insensible variations, some good genius must be appealed to--the genius
  2123. of the future species--in order to preserve and accumulate these
  2124. variations, for selection will not look after this. If, on the other
  2125. hand, the accidental variations are sudden, then, for the previous
  2126. function to go on or for a new function to take its place, all the
  2127. changes that have happened together must be complementary. So we have to
  2128. fall back on the good genius again, this time to obtain the
  2129. _convergence_ of _simultaneous_ changes, as before to be assured of the
  2130. _continuity of direction_ of _successive_ variations. But in neither
  2131. case can parallel development of the same complex structures on
  2132. independent lines of evolution be due to a mere accumulation of
  2133. accidental variations. So we come to the second of the two great
  2134. hypotheses we have to examine. Suppose the variations are due, not to
  2135. accidental and inner causes, but to the direct influence of outer
  2136. circumstances. Let us see what line we should have to take, on this
  2137. hypothesis, to account for the resemblance of eye-structure in two
  2138. series that are independent of each other from the phylogenetic point of
  2139. view.
  2140. Though molluscs and vertebrates have evolved separately, both have
  2141. remained exposed to the influence of light. And light is a physical
  2142. cause bringing forth certain definite effects. Acting in a continuous
  2143. way, it has been able to produce a continuous variation in a constant
  2144. direction. Of course it is unlikely that the eye of the vertebrate and
  2145. that of the mollusc have been built up by a series of variations due to
  2146. simple chance. Admitting even that light enters into the case as an
  2147. instrument of selection, in order to allow only useful variations to
  2148. persist, there is no possibility that the play of chance, even thus
  2149. supervised from without, should bring about in both cases the same
  2150. juxtaposition of elements coördinated in the same way. But it would be
  2151. different supposing that light acted directly on the organized matter so
  2152. as to change its structure and somehow adapt this structure to its own
  2153. form. The resemblance of the two effects would then be explained by the
  2154. identity of the cause. The more and more complex eye would be something
  2155. like the deeper and deeper imprint of light on a matter which, being
  2156. organized, possesses a special aptitude for receiving it.
  2157. But can an organic structure be likened to an imprint? We have already
  2158. called attention to the ambiguity of the term "adaptation." The gradual
  2159. complication of a form which is being better and better adapted to the
  2160. mold of outward circumstances is one thing, the increasingly complex
  2161. structure of an instrument which derives more and more advantage from
  2162. these circumstances is another. In the former case, the matter merely
  2163. receives an imprint; in the second, it reacts positively, it solves a
  2164. problem. Obviously it is this second sense of the word "adapt" that is
  2165. used when one says that the eye has become better and better adapted to
  2166. the influence of light. But one passes more or less unconsciously from
  2167. this sense to the other, and a purely mechanistic biology will strive to
  2168. make the _passive_ adaptation of an inert matter, which submits to the
  2169. influence of its environment, mean the same as the _active_ adaptation
  2170. of an organism which derives from this influence an advantage it can
  2171. appropriate. It must be owned, indeed, that Nature herself appears to
  2172. invite our mind to confuse these two kinds of adaptation, for she
  2173. usually begins by a passive adaptation where, later on, she will build
  2174. up a mechanism for active response. Thus, in the case before us, it is
  2175. unquestionable that the first rudiment of the eye is found in the
  2176. pigment-spot of the lower organisms; this spot may indeed have been
  2177. produced physically, by the mere action of light, and there are a great
  2178. number of intermediaries between the simple spot of pigment and a
  2179. complicated eye like that of the vertebrates.--But, from the fact that
  2180. we pass from one thing to another by degrees, it does not follow that
  2181. the two things are of the same nature. From the fact that an orator
  2182. falls in, at first, with the passions of his audience in order to make
  2183. himself master of them, it will not be concluded that to _follow_ is the
  2184. same as to _lead_. Now, living matter seems to have no other means of
  2185. turning circumstances to good account than by adapting itself to them
  2186. passively at the outset. Where it has to direct a movement, it begins by
  2187. adopting it. Life proceeds by insinuation. The intermediate degrees
  2188. between a pigment-spot and an eye are nothing to the point: however
  2189. numerous the degrees, there will still be the same interval between the
  2190. pigment-spot and the eye as between a photograph and a photographic
  2191. apparatus. Certainly the photograph has been gradually turned into a
  2192. photographic apparatus; but could light alone, a physical force, ever
  2193. have provoked this change, and converted an impression left by it into a
  2194. machine capable of using it?
  2195. It may be claimed that considerations of utility are out of place here;
  2196. that the eye is not made to see, but that we see because we have eyes;
  2197. that the organ is what it is, and "utility" is a word by which we
  2198. designate the functional effects of the structure. But when I say that
  2199. the eye "makes use of" light, I do not merely mean that the eye is
  2200. capable of seeing; I allude to the very precise relations that exist
  2201. between this organ and the apparatus of locomotion. The retina of
  2202. vertebrates is prolonged in an optic nerve, which, again, is continued
  2203. by cerebral centres connected with motor mechanisms. Our eye makes use
  2204. of light in that it enables us to utilize, by movements of reaction, the
  2205. objects that we see to be advantageous, and to avoid those which we see
  2206. to be injurious. Now, of course, as light may have produced a
  2207. pigment-spot by physical means, so it can physically determine the
  2208. movements of certain organisms; ciliated Infusoria, for instance, react
  2209. to light. But no one would hold that the influence of light has
  2210. physically caused the formation of a nervous system, of a muscular
  2211. system, of an osseous system, all things which are continuous with the
  2212. apparatus of vision in vertebrate animals. The truth is, when one
  2213. speaks of the gradual formation of the eye, and, still more, when one
  2214. takes into account all that is inseparably connected with it, one brings
  2215. in something entirely different from the direct action of light. One
  2216. implicitly attributes to organized matter a certain capacity _sui
  2217. generis_, the mysterious power of building up very complicated machines
  2218. to utilize the simple excitation that it undergoes.
  2219. But this is just what is claimed to be unnecessary. Physics and
  2220. chemistry are said to give us the key to everything. Eimer's great work
  2221. is instructive in this respect. It is well known what persevering effort
  2222. this biologist has devoted to demonstrating that transformation is
  2223. brought about by the influence of the external on the internal,
  2224. continuously exerted in the same direction, and not, as Darwin held, by
  2225. accidental variations. His theory rests on observations of the highest
  2226. interest, of which the starting-point was the study of the course
  2227. followed by the color variation of the skin in certain lizards. Before
  2228. this, the already old experiments of Dorfmeister had shown that the same
  2229. chrysalis, according as it was submitted to cold or heat, gave rise to
  2230. very different butterflies, which had long been regarded as independent
  2231. species, _Vanessa levana_ and _Vanessa prorsa_: an intermediate
  2232. temperature produces an intermediate form. We might class with these
  2233. facts the important transformations observed in a little crustacean,
  2234. _Artemia salina_, when the salt of the water it lives in is increased or
  2235. diminished.[32] In these various experiments the external agent seems to
  2236. act as a cause of transformation. But what does the word "cause" mean
  2237. here? Without undertaking an exhaustive analysis of the idea of
  2238. causality, we will merely remark that three very different meanings of
  2239. this term are commonly confused. A cause may act by _impelling_,
  2240. _releasing_, or _unwinding_. The billiard-ball, that strikes another,
  2241. determines its movement by _impelling_. The spark that explodes the
  2242. powder acts by _releasing_. The gradual relaxing of the spring, that
  2243. makes the phonograph turn, _unwinds_ the melody inscribed on the
  2244. cylinder: if the melody which is played be the effect, and the relaxing
  2245. of the spring the cause, we must say that the cause acts by _unwinding_.
  2246. What distinguishes these three cases from each other is the greater or
  2247. less solidarity between the cause and the effect. In the first, the
  2248. quantity and quality of the effect vary with the quantity and quality of
  2249. the cause. In the second, neither quality nor quantity of the effect
  2250. varies with quality and quantity of the cause: the effect is invariable.
  2251. In the third, the quantity of the effect depends on the quantity of the
  2252. cause, but the cause does not influence the quality of the effect: the
  2253. longer the cylinder turns by the action of the spring, the more of the
  2254. melody I shall hear, but the nature of the melody, or of the part heard,
  2255. does not depend on the action of the spring. Only in the first case,
  2256. really, does cause _explain_ effect; in the others the effect is more or
  2257. less given in advance, and the antecedent invoked is--in different
  2258. degrees, of course--its occasion rather than its cause. Now, in saying
  2259. that the saltness of the water is the cause of the transformations of
  2260. Artemia, or that the degree of temperature determines the color and
  2261. marks of the wings which a certain chrysalis will assume on becoming a
  2262. butterfly, is the word "cause" used in the first sense? Obviously not:
  2263. causality has here an intermediary sense between those of unwinding and
  2264. releasing. Such, indeed, seems to be Eimer's own meaning when he speaks
  2265. of the "kaleidoscopic" character of the variation,[33] or when he says
  2266. that the variation of organized matter works in a definite way, just as
  2267. inorganic matter crystallizes in definite directions.[34] And it may be
  2268. granted, perhaps, that the process is a merely physical and chemical one
  2269. in the case of the color-changes of the skin. But if this sort of
  2270. explanation is extended to the case of the gradual formation of the eye
  2271. of the vertebrate, for instance, it must be supposed that the
  2272. physico-chemistry of living bodies is such that the influence of light
  2273. has caused the organism to construct a progressive series of visual
  2274. apparatus, all extremely complex, yet all capable of seeing, and of
  2275. seeing better and better.[35] What more could the most confirmed
  2276. finalist say, in order to mark out so exceptional a physico-chemistry?
  2277. And will not the position of a mechanistic philosophy become still more
  2278. difficult, when it is pointed out to it that the egg of a mollusc cannot
  2279. have the same chemical composition as that of a vertebrate, that the
  2280. organic substance which evolved toward the first of these two forms
  2281. could not have been chemically identical with that of the substance
  2282. which went in the other direction, and that, nevertheless, under the
  2283. influence of light, the same organ has been constructed in the one case
  2284. as in the other?
  2285. The more we reflect upon it, the more we shall see that this production
  2286. of the same effect by two different accumulations of an enormous number
  2287. of small causes is contrary to the principles of mechanistic philosophy.
  2288. We have concentrated the full force of our discussion upon an example
  2289. drawn from phylogenesis. But ontogenesis would have furnished us with
  2290. facts no less cogent. Every moment, right before our eyes, nature
  2291. arrives at identical results, in sometimes neighboring species, by
  2292. entirely different embryogenic processes. Observations of
  2293. "heteroblastia" have multiplied in late years,[36] and it has been
  2294. necessary to reject the almost classical theory of the specificity of
  2295. embryonic gills. Still keeping to our comparison between the eye of
  2296. vertebrates and that of molluscs, we may point out that the retina of
  2297. the vertebrate is produced by an expansion in the rudimentary brain of
  2298. the young embryo. It is a regular nervous centre which has moved toward
  2299. the periphery. In the mollusc, on the contrary, the retina is derived
  2300. from the ectoderm directly, and not indirectly by means of the embryonic
  2301. encephalon. Quite different, therefore, are the evolutionary processes
  2302. which lead, in man and in the Pecten, to the development of a like
  2303. retina. But, without going so far as to compare two organisms so distant
  2304. from each other, we might reach the same conclusion simply by looking at
  2305. certain very curious facts of regeneration in one and the same organism.
  2306. If the crystalline lens of a Triton be removed, it is regenerated by the
  2307. iris.[37] Now, the original lens was built out of the ectoderm, while
  2308. the iris is of mesodermic origin. What is more, in the _Salamandra
  2309. maculata_, if the lens be removed and the iris left, the regeneration of
  2310. the lens takes place at the upper part of the iris; but if this upper
  2311. part of the iris itself be taken away, the regeneration takes place in
  2312. the inner or retinal layer of the remaining region.[38] Thus, parts
  2313. differently situated, differently constituted, meant normally for
  2314. different functions, are capable of performing the same duties and even
  2315. of manufacturing, when necessary, the same pieces of the machine. Here
  2316. we have, indeed, the same effect obtained by different combinations of
  2317. causes.
  2318. Whether we will or no, we must appeal to some inner directing principle
  2319. in order to account for this convergence of effects. Such convergence
  2320. does not appear possible in the Darwinian, and especially the
  2321. neo-Darwinian, theory of insensible accidental variations, nor in the
  2322. hypothesis of sudden accidental variations, nor even in the theory that
  2323. assigns definite directions to the evolution of the various organs by a
  2324. kind of mechanical composition of the external with the internal forces.
  2325. So we come to the only one of the present forms of evolution which
  2326. remains for us to mention, viz., neo-Lamarckism.
  2327. * * * * *
  2328. It is well known that Lamarck attributed to the living being the power
  2329. of varying by use or disuse of its organs, and also of passing on the
  2330. variation so acquired to its descendants. A certain number of biologists
  2331. hold a doctrine of this kind to-day. The variation that results in a new
  2332. species is not, they believe, merely an accidental variation inherent in
  2333. the germ itself, nor is it governed by a determinism _sui generis_ which
  2334. develops definite characters in a definite direction, apart from every
  2335. consideration of utility. It springs from the very effort of the living
  2336. being to adapt itself to the circumstances of its existence. The effort
  2337. may indeed be only the mechanical exercise of certain organs,
  2338. mechanically elicited by the pressure of external circumstances. But it
  2339. may also imply consciousness and will, and it is in this sense that it
  2340. appears to be understood by one of the most eminent representatives of
  2341. the doctrine, the American naturalist Cope.[39] Neo-Lamarckism is
  2342. therefore, of all the later forms of evolutionism, the only one capable
  2343. of admitting an internal and psychological principle of development,
  2344. although it is not bound to do so. And it is also the only evolutionism
  2345. that seems to us to account for the building up of identical complex
  2346. organs on independent lines of development. For it is quite conceivable
  2347. that the same effort to turn the same circumstances to good account
  2348. might have the same result, especially if the problem put by the
  2349. circumstances is such as to admit of only one solution. But the question
  2350. remains, whether the term "effort" must not then be taken in a deeper
  2351. sense, a sense even more psychological than any neo-Lamarckian supposes.
  2352. For a mere variation of size is one thing, and a change of form is
  2353. another. That an organ can be strengthened and grow by exercise, nobody
  2354. will deny. But it is a long way from that to the progressive development
  2355. of an eye like that of the molluscs and of the vertebrates. If this
  2356. development be ascribed to the influence of light, long continued but
  2357. passively received, we fall back on the theory we have just criticized.
  2358. If, on the other hand, an internal activity is appealed to, then it must
  2359. be something quite different from what we usually call an effort, for
  2360. never has an effort been known to produce the slightest complication of
  2361. an organ, and yet an enormous number of complications, all admirably
  2362. coördinated, have been necessary to pass from the pigment-spot of the
  2363. Infusorian to the eye of the vertebrate. But, even if we accept this
  2364. notion of the evolutionary process in the case of animals, how can we
  2365. apply it to plants? Here, variations of form do not seem to imply, nor
  2366. always to lead to, functional changes; and even if the cause of the
  2367. variation is of a psychological nature, we can hardly call it an effort,
  2368. unless we give a very unusual extension to the meaning of the word. The
  2369. truth is, it is necessary to dig beneath the effort itself and look for
  2370. a deeper cause.
  2371. This is especially necessary, we believe, if we wish to get at a cause
  2372. of regular hereditary variations. We are not going to enter here into
  2373. the controversies over the transmissibility of acquired characters;
  2374. still less do we wish to take too definite a side on this question,
  2375. which is not within our province. But we cannot remain completely
  2376. indifferent to it. Nowhere is it clearer that philosophers can not
  2377. to-day content themselves with vague generalities, but must follow the
  2378. scientists in experimental detail and discuss the results with them. If
  2379. Spencer had begun by putting to himself the question of the
  2380. hereditability of acquired characters, his evolutionism would no doubt
  2381. have taken an altogether different form. If (as seems probable to us) a
  2382. habit contracted by the individual were transmitted to its descendants
  2383. only in very exceptional cases, all the Spencerian psychology would need
  2384. remaking, and a large part of Spencer's philosophy would fall to pieces.
  2385. Let us say, then, how the problem seems to us to present itself, and in
  2386. what direction an attempt might be made to solve it.
  2387. After having been affirmed as a dogma, the transmissibility of acquired
  2388. characters has been no less dogmatically denied, for reasons drawn _a
  2389. priori_ from the supposed nature of germinal cells. It is well known how
  2390. Weismann was led, by his hypothesis of the continuity of the germ-plasm,
  2391. to regard the germinal cells--ova and spermatozoa--as almost independent
  2392. of the somatic cells. Starting from this, it has been claimed, and is
  2393. still claimed by many, that the hereditary transmission of an acquired
  2394. character is inconceivable. But if, perchance, experiment should show
  2395. that acquired characters are transmissible, it would prove thereby that
  2396. the germ-plasm is not so independent of the somatic envelope as has been
  2397. contended, and the transmissibility of acquired characters would become
  2398. _ipso facto_ conceivable; which amounts to saying that conceivability
  2399. and inconceivability have nothing to do with the case, and that
  2400. experience alone must settle the matter. But it is just here that the
  2401. difficulty begins. The acquired characters we are speaking of are
  2402. generally habits or the effects of habit, and at the root of most habits
  2403. there is a natural disposition. So that one can always ask whether it is
  2404. really the habit acquired by the soma of the individual that is
  2405. transmitted, or whether it is not rather a natural aptitude, which
  2406. existed prior to the habit. This aptitude would have remained inherent
  2407. in the germ-plasm which the individual bears within him, as it was in
  2408. the individual himself and consequently in the germ whence he sprang.
  2409. Thus, for instance, there is no proof that the mole has become blind
  2410. because it has formed the habit of living underground; it is perhaps
  2411. because its eyes were becoming atrophied that it condemned itself to a
  2412. life underground.[40] If this is the case, the tendency to lose the
  2413. power of vision has been transmitted from germ to germ without anything
  2414. being acquired or lost by the soma of the mole itself. From the fact
  2415. that the son of a fencing-master has become a good fencer much more
  2416. quickly than his father, we cannot infer that the habit of the parent
  2417. has been transmitted to the child; for certain natural dispositions in
  2418. course of growth may have passed from the plasma engendering the father
  2419. to the plasma engendering the son, may have grown on the way by the
  2420. effect of the primitive impetus, and thus assured to the son a greater
  2421. suppleness than the father had, without troubling, so to speak, about
  2422. what the father did. So of many examples drawn from the progressive
  2423. domestication of animals: it is hard to say whether it is the acquired
  2424. habit that is transmitted or only a certain natural tendency--that,
  2425. indeed, which has caused such and such a particular species or certain
  2426. of its representatives to be specially chosen for domestication. The
  2427. truth is, when every doubtful case, every fact open to more than one
  2428. interpretation, has been eliminated, there remains hardly a single
  2429. unquestionable example of acquired and transmitted peculiarities, beyond
  2430. the famous experiments of Brown-Séquard, repeated and confirmed by other
  2431. physiologists.[41] By cutting the spinal cord or the sciatic nerve of
  2432. guinea-pigs, Brown-Séquard brought about an epileptic state which was
  2433. transmitted to the descendants. Lesions of the same sciatic nerve, of
  2434. the restiform body, etc., provoked various troubles in the guinea-pig
  2435. which its progeny inherited sometimes in a quite different form:
  2436. exophthalmia, loss of toes, etc. But it is not demonstrated that in
  2437. these different cases of hereditary transmission there had been a real
  2438. influence of the soma of the animal on its germ-plasm. Weismann at once
  2439. objected that the operations of Brown-Séquard might have introduced
  2440. certain special microbes into the body of the guinea-pig, which had
  2441. found their means of nutrition in the nervous tissues and transmitted
  2442. the malady by penetrating into the sexual elements.[42] This objection
  2443. has been answered by Brown-Séquard himself;[43] but a more plausible
  2444. one might be raised. Some experiments of Voisin and Peron have shown
  2445. that fits of epilepsy are followed by the elimination of a toxic body
  2446. which, when injected into animals,[44] is capable of producing
  2447. convulsive symptoms. Perhaps the trophic disorders following the nerve
  2448. lesions made by Brown-Séquard correspond to the formation of precisely
  2449. this convulsion-causing poison. If so, the toxin passed from the
  2450. guinea-pig to its spermatozoon or ovum, and caused in the development of
  2451. the embryo a general disturbance, which, however, had no visible effects
  2452. except at one point or another of the organism when developed. In that
  2453. case, what occurred would have been somewhat the same as in the
  2454. experiments of Charrin, Delamare, and Moussu, where guinea-pigs in
  2455. gestation, whose liver or kidney was injured, transmitted the lesion to
  2456. their progeny, simply because the injury to the mother's organ had given
  2457. rise to specific "cytotoxins" which acted on the corresponding organ of
  2458. the foetus.[45] It is true that, in these experiments, as in a former
  2459. observation of the same physiologists,[46] it was the already formed
  2460. foetus that was influenced by the toxins. But other researches of
  2461. Charrin have resulted in showing that the same effect may be produced,
  2462. by an analogous process, on the spermatozoa and the ova.[47] To
  2463. conclude, then: the inheritance of an acquired peculiarity in the
  2464. experiments of Brown-Séquard can be explained by the effect of a toxin
  2465. on the germ. The lesion, however well localized it seems, is transmitted
  2466. by the same process as, for instance, the taint of alcoholism. But may
  2467. it not be the same in the case of every acquired peculiarity that has
  2468. become hereditary?
  2469. There is, indeed, one point on which both those who affirm and those who
  2470. deny the transmissibility of acquired characters are agreed, namely,
  2471. that certain influences, such as that of alcohol, can affect at the same
  2472. time both the living being and the germ-plasm it contains. In such case,
  2473. there is inheritance of a defect, and the result is _as if_ the soma of
  2474. the parent had acted on the germ-plasm, although in reality soma and
  2475. plasma have simply both suffered the action of the same cause. Now,
  2476. suppose that the soma can influence the germ-plasm, as those believe who
  2477. hold that acquired characters are transmissible. Is not the most natural
  2478. hypothesis to suppose that things happen in this second case as in the
  2479. first, and that the direct effect of the influence of the soma is a
  2480. _general_ alteration of the germ-plasm? If this is the case, it is by
  2481. exception, and in some sort by accident, that the modification of the
  2482. descendant is the same as that of the parent. It is like the
  2483. hereditability of the alcoholic taint: it passes from father to
  2484. children, but it may take a different form in each child, and in none of
  2485. them be like what it was in the father. Let the letter C represent the
  2486. change in the plasm, C being either positive or negative, that is to
  2487. say, showing either the gain or loss of certain substances. The effect
  2488. will not be an exact reproduction of the cause, nor will the change in
  2489. the germ-plasm, provoked by a certain modification of a certain part of
  2490. the soma, determine a similar modification of the corresponding part of
  2491. the new organism in process of formation, unless all the other nascent
  2492. parts of this organism enjoy a kind of immunity as regards C: the same
  2493. part will then undergo alteration in the new organism, because it
  2494. happens that the development of this part is alone subject to the new
  2495. influence. And, even then, the part might be altered in an entirely
  2496. different way from that in which the corresponding part was altered in
  2497. the generating organism.
  2498. We should propose, then, to introduce a distinction between the
  2499. hereditability of _deviation_ and that of _character_. An individual
  2500. which acquires a new character thereby _deviates_ from the form it
  2501. previously had, which form the germs, or oftener the half-germs, it
  2502. contains would have reproduced in their development. If this
  2503. modification does not involve the production of substances capable of
  2504. changing the germ-plasm, or does not so affect nutrition as to deprive
  2505. the germ-plasm of certain of its elements, it will have no effect on the
  2506. offspring of the individual. This is probably the case as a rule. If, on
  2507. the contrary, it has some effect, this is likely to be due to a chemical
  2508. change which it has induced in the germ-plasm. This chemical change
  2509. might, by exception, bring about the original modification again in the
  2510. organism which the germ is about to develop, but there are as many and
  2511. more chances that it will do something else. In this latter case, the
  2512. generated organism will perhaps deviate from the normal type _as much
  2513. as_ the generating organism, but it will do so _differently_. It will
  2514. have inherited deviation and not character. In general, therefore, the
  2515. habits formed by an individual have probably no echo in its offspring;
  2516. and when they have, the modification in the descendants may have no
  2517. visible likeness to the original one. Such, at least, is the hypothesis
  2518. which seems to us most likely. In any case, in default of proof to the
  2519. contrary, and so long as the decisive experiments called for by an
  2520. eminent biologist[48] have not been made, we must keep to the actual
  2521. results of observation. Now, even if we take the most favorable view of
  2522. the theory of the transmissibility of acquired characters, and assume
  2523. that the ostensible acquired character is not, in most cases, the more
  2524. or less tardy development of an innate character, facts show us that
  2525. hereditary transmission is the exception and not the rule. How, then,
  2526. shall we expect it to develop an organ such as the eye? When we think of
  2527. the enormous number of variations, all in the same direction, that we
  2528. must suppose to be accumulated before the passage from the pigment-spot
  2529. of the Infusorian to the eye of the mollusc and of the vertebrate is
  2530. possible, we do not see how heredity, as we observe it, could ever have
  2531. determined this piling-up of differences, even supposing that individual
  2532. efforts could have produced each of them singly. That is to say that
  2533. neo-Lamarckism is no more able than any other form of evolutionism to
  2534. solve the problem.
  2535. * * * * *
  2536. In thus submitting the various present forms of evolutionism to a common
  2537. test, in showing that they all strike against the same insurmountable
  2538. difficulty, we have in no wise the intention of rejecting them
  2539. altogether. On the contrary, each of them, being supported by a
  2540. considerable number of facts, must be true in its way. Each of them must
  2541. correspond to a certain aspect of the process of evolution. Perhaps even
  2542. it is necessary that a theory should restrict itself exclusively to a
  2543. particular point of view, in order to remain scientific, _i.e._ to give
  2544. a precise direction to researches into detail. But the reality of which
  2545. each of these theories takes a partial view must transcend them all. And
  2546. this reality is the special object of philosophy, which is not
  2547. constrained to scientific precision because it contemplates no
  2548. practical application. Let us therefore indicate in a word or two the
  2549. positive contribution that each of the three present forms of
  2550. evolutionism seems to us to make toward the solution of the problem,
  2551. what each of them leaves out, and on what point this threefold effort
  2552. should, in our opinion, converge in order to obtain a more
  2553. comprehensive, although thereby of necessity a less definite, idea of
  2554. the evolutionary process.
  2555. The neo-Darwinians are probably right, we believe, when they teach that
  2556. the essential causes of variation are the differences inherent in the
  2557. germ borne by the individual, and not the experiences or behavior of the
  2558. individual in the course of his career. Where we fail to follow these
  2559. biologists, is in regarding the differences inherent in the germ as
  2560. purely accidental and individual. We cannot help believing that these
  2561. differences are the development of an impulsion which passes from germ
  2562. to germ across the individuals, that they are therefore not pure
  2563. accidents, and that they might well appear at the same time, in the same
  2564. form, in all the representatives of the same species, or at least in a
  2565. certain number of them. Already, in fact, the theory of _mutations_ is
  2566. modifying Darwinism profoundly on this point. It asserts that at a given
  2567. moment, after a long period, the entire species is beset with a tendency
  2568. to change. The _tendency to change_, therefore, is not accidental. True,
  2569. the change itself would be accidental, since the mutation works,
  2570. according to De Vries, in different directions in the different
  2571. representatives of the species. But, first we must see if the theory is
  2572. confirmed by many other vegetable species (De Vries has verified it only
  2573. by the _OEnothera Lamarckiana_),[49] and then there is the
  2574. possibility, as we shall explain further on, that the part played by
  2575. chance is much greater in the variation of plants than in that of
  2576. animals, because, in the vegetable world, function does not depend so
  2577. strictly on form. Be that as it may, the neo-Darwinians are inclined to
  2578. admit that the periods of mutation are determinate. The direction of the
  2579. mutation may therefore be so as well, at least in animals, and to the
  2580. extent we shall have to indicate.
  2581. We thus arrive at a hypothesis like Eimer's, according to which the
  2582. variations of different characters continue from generation to
  2583. generation in definite directions. This hypothesis seems plausible to
  2584. us, within the limits in which Eimer himself retains it. Of course, the
  2585. evolution of the organic world cannot be predetermined as a whole. We
  2586. claim, on the contrary, that the spontaneity of life is manifested by a
  2587. continual creation of new forms succeeding others. But this
  2588. indetermination cannot be complete; it must leave a certain part to
  2589. determination. An organ like the eye, for example, must have been formed
  2590. by just a continual changing in a definite direction. Indeed, we do not
  2591. see how otherwise to explain the likeness of structure of the eye in
  2592. species that have not the same history. Where we differ from Eimer is in
  2593. his claim that combinations of physical and chemical causes are enough
  2594. to secure the result. We have tried to prove, on the contrary, by the
  2595. example of the eye, that if there is "orthogenesis" here, a
  2596. psychological cause intervenes.
  2597. Certain neo-Lamarckians do indeed resort to a cause of a psychological
  2598. nature. There, to our thinking, is one of the most solid positions of
  2599. neo-Lamarckism. But if this cause is nothing but the conscious effort of
  2600. the individual, it cannot operate in more than a restricted number of
  2601. cases--at most in the animal world, and not at all in the vegetable
  2602. kingdom. Even in animals, it will act only on points which are under the
  2603. direct or indirect control of the will. And even where it does act, it
  2604. is not clear how it could compass a change so profound as an increase of
  2605. complexity: at most this would be conceivable if the acquired characters
  2606. were regularly transmitted so as to be added together; but this
  2607. transmission seems to be the exception rather than the rule. A
  2608. hereditary change in a definite direction, which continues to accumulate
  2609. and add to itself so as to build up a more and more complex machine,
  2610. must certainly be related to some sort of effort, but to an effort of
  2611. far greater depth than the individual effort, far more independent of
  2612. circumstances, an effort common to most representatives of the same
  2613. species, inherent in the germs they bear rather than in their substance
  2614. alone, an effort thereby assured of being passed on to their
  2615. descendants.
  2616. * * * * *
  2617. So we come back, by a somewhat roundabout way, to the idea we started
  2618. from, that of an _original impetus_ of life, passing from one generation
  2619. of germs to the following generation of germs through the developed
  2620. organisms which bridge the interval between the generations. This
  2621. impetus, sustained right along the lines of evolution among which it
  2622. gets divided, is the fundamental cause of variations, at least of those
  2623. that are regularly passed on, that accumulate and create new species. In
  2624. general, when species have begun to diverge from a common stock, they
  2625. accentuate their divergence as they progress in their evolution. Yet, in
  2626. certain definite points, they may evolve identically; in fact, they must
  2627. do so if the hypothesis of a common impetus be accepted. This is just
  2628. what we shall have to show now in a more precise way, by the same
  2629. example we have chosen, the formation of the eye in molluscs and
  2630. vertebrates. The idea of an "original impetus," moreover, will thus be
  2631. made clearer.
  2632. Two points are equally striking in an organ like the eye: the complexity
  2633. of its structure and the simplicity of its function. The eye is composed
  2634. of distinct parts, such as the sclerotic, the cornea, the retina, the
  2635. crystalline lens, etc. In each of these parts the detail is infinite.
  2636. The retina alone comprises three layers of nervous elements--multipolar
  2637. cells, bipolar cells, visual cells--each of which has its individuality
  2638. and is undoubtedly a very complicated organism: so complicated, indeed,
  2639. is the retinal membrane in its intimate structure, that no simple
  2640. description can give an adequate idea of it. The mechanism of the eye
  2641. is, in short, composed of an infinity of mechanisms, all of extreme
  2642. complexity. Yet vision is one simple fact. As soon as the eye opens, the
  2643. visual act is effected. Just because the act is simple, the slightest
  2644. negligence on the part of nature in the building of the infinitely
  2645. complex machine would have made vision impossible. This contrast between
  2646. the complexity of the organ and the unity of the function is what gives
  2647. us pause.
  2648. A mechanistic theory is one which means to show us the gradual
  2649. building-up of the machine under the influence of external circumstances
  2650. intervening either directly by action on the tissues or indirectly by
  2651. the selection of better-adapted ones. But, whatever form this theory may
  2652. take, supposing it avails at all to explain the detail of the parts, it
  2653. throws no light on their correlation.
  2654. Then comes the doctrine of finality, which says that the parts have been
  2655. brought together on a preconceived plan with a view to a certain end. In
  2656. this it likens the labor of nature to that of the workman, who also
  2657. proceeds by the assemblage of parts with a view to the realization of an
  2658. idea or the imitation of a model. Mechanism, here, reproaches finalism
  2659. with its anthropomorphic character, and rightly. But it fails to see
  2660. that itself proceeds according to this method--somewhat mutilated! True,
  2661. it has got rid of the end pursued or the ideal model. But it also holds
  2662. that nature has worked like a human being by bringing parts together,
  2663. while a mere glance at the development of an embryo shows that life goes
  2664. to work in a very different way. _Life does not proceed by the
  2665. association and addition of elements, but by dissociation and division._
  2666. We must get beyond both points of view, both mechanism and finalism
  2667. being, at bottom, only standpoints to which the human mind has been led
  2668. by considering the work of man. But in what direction can we go beyond
  2669. them? We have said that in analyzing the structure of an organ, we can
  2670. go on decomposing for ever, although the function of the whole is a
  2671. simple thing. This contrast between the infinite complexity of the organ
  2672. and the extreme simplicity of the function is what should open our eyes.
  2673. In general, when the same object appears in one aspect and in another as
  2674. infinitely complex, the two aspects have by no means the same
  2675. importance, or rather the same degree of reality. In such cases, the
  2676. simplicity belongs to the object itself, and the infinite complexity to
  2677. the views we take in turning around it, to the symbols by which our
  2678. senses or intellect represent it to us, or, more generally, to elements
  2679. _of a different order_, with which we try to imitate it artificially,
  2680. but with which it remains incommensurable, being of a different nature.
  2681. An artist of genius has painted a figure on his canvas. We can imitate
  2682. his picture with many-colored squares of mosaic. And we shall reproduce
  2683. the curves and shades of the model so much the better as our squares are
  2684. smaller, more numerous and more varied in tone. But an infinity of
  2685. elements infinitely small, presenting an infinity of shades, would be
  2686. necessary to obtain the exact equivalent of the figure that the artist
  2687. has conceived as a simple thing, which he has wished to transport as a
  2688. whole to the canvas, and which is the more complete the more it strikes
  2689. us as the projection of an indivisible intuition. Now, suppose our eyes
  2690. so made that they cannot help seeing in the work of the master a mosaic
  2691. effect. Or suppose our intellect so made that it cannot explain the
  2692. appearance of the figure on the canvas except as a work of mosaic. We
  2693. should then be able to speak simply of a collection of little squares,
  2694. and we should be under the mechanistic hypothesis. We might add that,
  2695. beside the materiality of the collection, there must be a plan on which
  2696. the artist worked; and then we should be expressing ourselves as
  2697. finalists. But in neither case should we have got at the real process,
  2698. for there are no squares brought together. It is the picture, _i.e._ the
  2699. simple act, projected on the canvas, which, by the mere fact of entering
  2700. into our perception, is _de_composed before our eyes into thousands and
  2701. thousands of little squares which present, as _re_composed, a wonderful
  2702. arrangement. So the eye, with its marvelous complexity of structure, may
  2703. be only the simple act of vision, divided _for us_ into a mosaic of
  2704. cells, whose order seems marvelous to us because we have conceived the
  2705. whole as an assemblage.
  2706. If I raise my hand from A to B, this movement appears to me under two
  2707. aspects at once. Felt from within, it is a simple, indivisible act.
  2708. Perceived from without, it is the course of a certain curve, AB. In this
  2709. curve I can distinguish as many positions as I please, and the line
  2710. itself might be defined as a certain mutual coördination of these
  2711. positions. But the positions, infinite in number, and the order in which
  2712. they are connected, have sprung automatically from the indivisible act
  2713. by which my hand has gone from A to B. Mechanism, here, would consist
  2714. in seeing only the positions. Finalism would take their order into
  2715. account. But both mechanism and finalism would leave on one side the
  2716. movement, which is reality itself. In one sense, the movement is _more_
  2717. than the positions and than their order; for it is sufficient to make it
  2718. in its indivisible simplicity to secure that the infinity of the
  2719. successive positions as also their order be given at once--with
  2720. something else which is neither order nor position but which is
  2721. essential, the mobility. But, in another sense, the movement is _less_
  2722. than the series of positions and their connecting order; for, to arrange
  2723. points in a certain order, it is necessary first to conceive the order
  2724. and then to realize it with points, there must be the work of assemblage
  2725. and there must be intelligence, whereas the simple movement of the hand
  2726. contains nothing of either. It is not intelligent, in the human sense of
  2727. the word, and it is not an assemblage, for it is not made up of
  2728. elements. Just so with the relation of the eye to vision. There is in
  2729. vision _more_ than the component cells of the eye and their mutual
  2730. coördination: in this sense, neither mechanism nor finalism go far
  2731. enough. But, in another sense, mechanism and finalism both go too far,
  2732. for they attribute to Nature the most formidable of the labors of
  2733. Hercules in holding that she has exalted to the simple act of vision an
  2734. infinity of infinitely complex elements, whereas Nature has had no more
  2735. trouble in making an eye than I have in lifting my hand. Nature's simple
  2736. act has divided itself automatically into an infinity of elements which
  2737. are then found to be coördinated to one idea, just as the movement of my
  2738. hand has dropped an infinity of points which are then found to satisfy
  2739. one equation.
  2740. We find it very hard to see things in that light, because we cannot
  2741. help conceiving organization as manufacturing. But it is one thing to
  2742. manufacture, and quite another to organize. Manufacturing is peculiar to
  2743. man. It consists in assembling parts of matter which we have cut out in
  2744. such manner that we can fit them together and obtain from them a common
  2745. action. The parts are arranged, so to speak, around the action as an
  2746. ideal centre. To manufacture, therefore, is to work from the periphery
  2747. to the centre, or, as the philosophers say, from the many to the one.
  2748. Organization, on the contrary, works from the centre to the periphery.
  2749. It begins in a point that is almost a mathematical point, and spreads
  2750. around this point by concentric waves which go on enlarging. The work of
  2751. manufacturing is the more effective, the greater the quantity of matter
  2752. dealt with. It proceeds by concentration and compression. The organizing
  2753. act, on the contrary, has something explosive about it: it needs at the
  2754. beginning the smallest possible place, a minimum of matter, as if the
  2755. organizing forces only entered space reluctantly. The spermatozoon,
  2756. which sets in motion the evolutionary process of the embryonic life, is
  2757. one of the smallest cells of the organism; and it is only a small part
  2758. of the spermatozoon which really takes part in the operation.
  2759. But these are only superficial differences. Digging beneath them, we
  2760. think, a deeper difference would be found.
  2761. A manufactured thing delineates exactly the form of the work of
  2762. manufacturing it. I mean that the manufacturer finds in his product
  2763. exactly what he has put into it. If he is going to make a machine, he
  2764. cuts out its pieces one by one and then puts them together: the machine,
  2765. when made, will show both the pieces and their assemblage. The whole of
  2766. the result represents the whole of the work; and to each part of the
  2767. work corresponds a part of the result.
  2768. Now I recognize that positive science can and should proceed as if
  2769. organization was like making a machine. Only so will it have any hold on
  2770. organized bodies. For its object is not to show us the essence of
  2771. things, but to furnish us with the best means of acting on them. Physics
  2772. and chemistry are well advanced sciences, and living matter lends itself
  2773. to our action only so far as we can treat it by the processes of our
  2774. physics and chemistry. Organization can therefore only be studied
  2775. scientifically if the organized body has first been likened to a
  2776. machine. The cells will be the pieces of the machine, the organism their
  2777. assemblage, and the elementary labors which have organized the parts
  2778. will be regarded as the real elements of the labor which has organized
  2779. the whole. This is the standpoint of science. Quite different, in our
  2780. opinion, is that of philosophy.
  2781. For us, the whole of an organized machine may, strictly speaking,
  2782. represent the whole of the organizing work (this is, however, only
  2783. approximately true), yet the parts of the machine do not correspond to
  2784. parts of the work, because _the materiality of this machine does not
  2785. represent a sum of means employed, but a sum of obstacles avoided_: it
  2786. is a negation rather than a positive reality. So, as we have shown in a
  2787. former study, vision is a power which should attain _by right_ an
  2788. infinity of things inaccessible to our eyes. But such a vision would not
  2789. be continued into action; it might suit a phantom, but not a living
  2790. being. The vision of a living being is an _effective_ vision, limited to
  2791. objects on which the being can act: it is a vision that is _canalized_,
  2792. and the visual apparatus simply symbolizes the work of canalizing.
  2793. Therefore the creation of the visual apparatus is no more explained by
  2794. the assembling of its anatomic elements than the digging of a canal
  2795. could be explained by the heaping up of the earth which might have
  2796. formed its banks. A mechanistic theory would maintain that the earth
  2797. had been brought cart-load by cart-load; finalism would add that it had
  2798. not been dumped down at random, that the carters had followed a plan.
  2799. But both theories would be mistaken, for the canal has been made in
  2800. another way.
  2801. With greater precision, we may compare the process by which nature
  2802. constructs an eye to the simple act by which we raise the hand. But we
  2803. supposed at first that the hand met with no resistance. Let us now
  2804. imagine that, instead of moving in air, the hand has to pass through
  2805. iron filings which are compressed and offer resistance to it in
  2806. proportion as it goes forward. At a certain moment the hand will have
  2807. exhausted its effort, and, at this very moment, the filings will be
  2808. massed and coördinated in a certain definite form, to wit, that of the
  2809. hand that is stopped and of a part of the arm. Now, suppose that the
  2810. hand and arm are invisible. Lookers-on will seek the reason of the
  2811. arrangement in the filings themselves and in forces within the mass.
  2812. Some will account for the position of each filing by the action exerted
  2813. upon it by the neighboring filings: these are the mechanists. Others
  2814. will prefer to think that a plan of the whole has presided over the
  2815. detail of these elementary actions: they are the finalists. But the
  2816. truth is that there has been merely one indivisible act, that of the
  2817. hand passing through the filings: the inexhaustible detail of the
  2818. movement of the grains, as well as the order of their final arrangement,
  2819. expresses negatively, in a way, this undivided movement, being the
  2820. unitary form of a resistance, and not a synthesis of positive elementary
  2821. actions. For this reason, if the arrangement of the grains is termed an
  2822. "effect" and the movement of the hand a "cause," it may indeed be said
  2823. that the whole of the effect is explained by the whole of the cause, but
  2824. to parts of the cause parts of the effect will in no wise correspond.
  2825. In other words, neither mechanism nor finalism will here be in place,
  2826. and we must resort to an explanation of a different kind. Now, in the
  2827. hypothesis we propose, the relation of vision to the visual apparatus
  2828. would be very nearly that of the hand to the iron filings that follow,
  2829. canalize and limit its motion.
  2830. The greater the effort of the hand, the farther it will go into the
  2831. filings. But at whatever point it stops, instantaneously and
  2832. automatically the filings coördinate and find their equilibrium. So with
  2833. vision and its organ. According as the undivided act constituting vision
  2834. advances more or less, the materiality of the organ is made of a more or
  2835. less considerable number of mutually coördinated elements, but the order
  2836. is necessarily complete and perfect. It could not be partial, because,
  2837. once again, the real process which gives rise to it has no parts. That
  2838. is what neither mechanism nor finalism takes into account, and it is
  2839. what we also fail to consider when we wonder at the marvelous structure
  2840. of an instrument such as the eye. At the bottom of our wondering is
  2841. always this idea, that it would have been possible for _a part only_ of
  2842. this coördination to have been realized, that the complete realization
  2843. is a kind of special favor. This favor the finalists consider as
  2844. dispensed to them all at once, by the final cause; the mechanists claim
  2845. to obtain it little by little, by the effect of natural selection; but
  2846. both see something positive in this coördination, and consequently
  2847. something fractionable in its cause,--something which admits of every
  2848. possible degree of achievement. In reality, the cause, though more or
  2849. less intense, cannot produce its effect except in one piece, and
  2850. completely finished. According as it goes further and further in the
  2851. direction of vision, it gives the simple pigmentary masses of a lower
  2852. organism, or the rudimentary eye of a Serpula, or the slightly
  2853. differentiated eye of the Alciope, or the marvelously perfected eye of
  2854. the bird; but all these organs, unequal as is their complexity,
  2855. necessarily present an equal coördination. For this reason, no matter
  2856. how distant two animal species may be from each other, if the progress
  2857. toward vision has gone equally far in both, there is the same visual
  2858. organ in each case, for the form of the organ only expresses the degree
  2859. in which the exercise of the function has been obtained.
  2860. But, in speaking of a progress toward vision, are we not coming back to
  2861. the old notion of finality? It would be so, undoubtedly, if this
  2862. progress required the conscious or unconscious idea of an end to be
  2863. attained. But it is really effected in virtue of the original impetus of
  2864. life; it is implied in this movement itself, and that is just why it is
  2865. found in independent lines of evolution. If now we are asked why and how
  2866. it is implied therein, we reply that life is, more than anything else, a
  2867. tendency to act on inert matter. The direction of this action is not
  2868. predetermined; hence the unforeseeable variety of forms which life, in
  2869. evolving, sows along its path. But this action always presents, to some
  2870. extent, the character of contingency; it implies at least a rudiment of
  2871. choice. Now a choice involves the anticipatory idea of several possible
  2872. actions. Possibilities of action must therefore be marked out for the
  2873. living being before the action itself. Visual perception is nothing
  2874. else:[50] the visible outlines of bodies are the design of our eventual
  2875. action on them. Vision will be found, therefore, in different degrees in
  2876. the most diverse animals, and it will appear in the same complexity of
  2877. structure wherever it has reached the same degree of intensity.
  2878. We have dwelt on these resemblances of structure in general, and on the
  2879. example of the eye in particular, because we had to define our attitude
  2880. toward mechanism on the one hand and finalism on the other. It remains
  2881. for us to describe it more precisely in itself. This we shall now do by
  2882. showing the divergent results of evolution not as presenting analogies,
  2883. but as themselves mutually complementary.
  2884. FOOTNOTES:
  2885. [Footnote 3: _Matière et mémoire_, Paris, 1896, chaps. ii. and iii.]
  2886. [Footnote 4: Calkins, _Studies on the Life History of Protozoa (Archiv
  2887. f. Entwicklungsmechanik_, vol. xv., 1903, pp. 139-186).]
  2888. [Footnote 5: Sedgwick Minot, _On Certain Phenomena of Growing Old_
  2889. (_Proc. Amer. Assoc. for the Advancement of Science_, 39th Meeting,
  2890. Salem, 1891, pp. 271-288).]
  2891. [Footnote 6: Le Dantec, _L'Individualité et l'erreur individualiste_,
  2892. Paris, 1905, pp. 84 ff.]
  2893. [Footnote 7: Metchnikoff, _La Dégénérescence sénile_ (_Année
  2894. biologique_, iii., 1897, pp. 249 ff.). Cf. by the same author, _La
  2895. Nature humaine_, Paris, 1903, pp. 312 ff.]
  2896. [Footnote 8: Roule, _L'Embryologie générale_, Paris, 1893, p. 319.]
  2897. [Footnote 9: The irreversibility of the series of living beings has been
  2898. well set forth by Baldwin (_Development and Evolution_, New York, 1902;
  2899. in particular p. 327).]
  2900. [Footnote 10: We have dwelt on this point and tried to make it clear in
  2901. the _Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience_, pp. 140-151.]
  2902. [Footnote 11: In his fine work on _Genius in Art_ (_Le Génie dans
  2903. l'art_), M. Séailles develops this twofold thesis, that art is a
  2904. continuation of nature and that life is creation. We should willingly
  2905. accept the second formula; but by creation must we understand, as the
  2906. author does, a _synthesis_ of elements? Where the elements pre-exist,
  2907. the synthesis that will be made is virtually given, being only one of
  2908. the possible arrangements. This arrangement a superhuman intellect could
  2909. have perceived in advance among all the possible ones that surround it.
  2910. We hold, on the contrary, that in the domain of life the elements have
  2911. no real and separate existence. They are manifold mental views of an
  2912. indivisible process. And for that reason there is radical contingency in
  2913. progress, incommensurability between what goes before and what
  2914. follows--in short, duration.]
  2915. [Footnote 12: Bütschli, _Untersuchungen über mikroskopische Schäume und
  2916. das Protoplasma_, Leipzig, 1892, First Part.]
  2917. [Footnote 13: Rhumbler, _Versuch einer mechanischen Erklärung der
  2918. indirekten Zell-und Kernteilung_ (_Roux's Archiv_, 1896).]
  2919. [Footnote 14: Berthold, _Studien über Protoplasmamechanik_, Leipzig,
  2920. 1886, p. 102. Cf. the explanation proposed by Le Dantec, _Théorie
  2921. nouvelle de la vie_, Paris, 1896, p. 60.]
  2922. [Footnote 15: Cope, _The Primary Factors of Organic Evolution_, Chicago,
  2923. 1896, pp. 475-484.]
  2924. [Footnote 16: Maupas, "Etude des infusoires ciliés" (_Arch. de zoologie
  2925. expérimentale_, 1883, pp. 47, 491, 518, 549, in particular). P. Vignon,
  2926. _Recherches de cytologie générale sur les épithéliums_, Paris, 1902, p.
  2927. 655. A profound study of the motions of the Infusoria and a very
  2928. penetrating criticism of the idea of tropism have been made recently by
  2929. Jennings (_Contributions to the Study of the Behavior of Lower
  2930. Organisms_, Washington, 1904). The "type of behavior" of these lower
  2931. organisms, as Jennings defines it (pp. 237-252), is unquestionably of
  2932. the psychological order.]
  2933. [Footnote 17: E.B. Wilson, _The Cell in Development and Inheritance_,
  2934. New York, 1897, p. 330.]
  2935. [Footnote 18: Dastre, _La Vie et la mort_, p. 43.]
  2936. [Footnote 19: Laplace, _Introduction à la théorie analytique des
  2937. probabilités_ (_OEuvres complètes_, vol. vii., Paris, 1886, p. vi.).]
  2938. [Footnote 20: Du Bois-Reymond, _Über die Grenzen des Naturerkennens_,
  2939. Leipzig, 1892.]
  2940. [Footnote 21: There are really two lines to follow in contemporary
  2941. neo-vitalism: on the one hand, the assertion that pure mechanism is
  2942. insufficient, which assumes great authority when made by such scientists
  2943. as Driesch or Reinke, for example; and, on the other hand, the
  2944. hypotheses which this vitalism superposes on mechanism (the
  2945. "entelechies" of Driesch, and the "dominants" of Reinke, etc.). Of these
  2946. two parts, the former is perhaps the more interesting. See the admirable
  2947. studies of Driesch--_Die Lokalisation morphogenetischer Vorgänge_,
  2948. Leipzig, 1899; _Die organischen Regulationen_, Leipzig, 1901;
  2949. _Naturbegriffe und Natururteile_, Leipzig, 1904; _Der Vitalismus als
  2950. Geschichte und als Lehre_, Leipzig, 1905; and of Reinke--_Die Welt als
  2951. Tat_, Berlin, 1899; _Einleitung in die theoretische Biologie_, Berlin,
  2952. 1901; _Philosophie der Botanik_, Leipzig, 1905.]
  2953. [Footnote 22: P. Guérin, _Les Connaissances actuelles sur la fécondation
  2954. chez les phanérogames_, Paris, 1904, pp. 144-148. Cf. Delage,
  2955. _L'Hérédité_, 2nd edition, 1903, pp. 140 ff.]
  2956. [Footnote 23: Möbius, _Beiträge zur Lehre von der Fortpflanzung der
  2957. Gewächse_, Jena, 1897, pp. 203-206 in particular. Cf. Hartog, "Sur les
  2958. phénomènes de reproduction" (_Année biologique_, 1895, pp. 707-709).]
  2959. [Footnote 24: Paul Janet, _Les Causes finales_, Paris, 1876, p. 83.]
  2960. [Footnote 25: _Ibid._ p. 80.]
  2961. [Footnote 26: Darwin, _Origin of Species_, chap. ii.]
  2962. [Footnote 27: Bateson, _Materials for the Study of Variation_, London,
  2963. 1894, especially pp. 567 ff. Cf. Scott, "Variations and Mutations"
  2964. (_American Journal of Science_, Nov. 1894).]
  2965. [Footnote 28: De Vries, _Die Mutationstheorie_, Leipzig, 1901-1903. Cf.,
  2966. by the same author, _Species and Varieties_, Chicago, 1905.]
  2967. [Footnote 29: Darwin, _Origin of Species_, chap. vi.]
  2968. [Footnote 30: Darwin, _Origin of Species_, chap. i.]
  2969. [Footnote 31: On this homology of hair and teeth, see Brandt, "Über ...
  2970. eine mutmassliche Homologie der Haare und Zahne" (_Biol. Centralblatt_,
  2971. vol. xviii., 1898, especially pp. 262 ff.).]
  2972. [Footnote 32: It seems, from later observations, that the transformation
  2973. of Artemia is a more complex phenomenon than was first supposed. See on
  2974. this subject Samter and Heymons, "Die Variation bei Artemia Salina"
  2975. (_Anhang zu den Abhandlungen der k. preussischen Akad. der
  2976. Wissenschaften_, 1902).]
  2977. [Footnote 33: Eimer, _Orthogenesis der Schmetterlinge_, Leipzig, 1897,
  2978. p. 24. Cf. _Die Entstehung der Arten_, p. 53.]
  2979. [Footnote 34: Eimer, _Die Entstehung der Arten_, Jena, 1888, p. 25.]
  2980. [Footnote 35: _Ibid._ pp. 165 ff.]
  2981. [Footnote 36: Salensky, "Heteroblastie" (_Proc. of the Fourth
  2982. International Congress of Zoology_, London, 1899, pp. 111-118). Salensky
  2983. has coined this word to designate the cases in which organs that are
  2984. equivalent, but of different embryological origin, are formed at the
  2985. same points in animals related to each other.]
  2986. [Footnote 37: Wolff, "Die Regeneration der Urodelenlinse" (_Arch. f.
  2987. Entwicklungsmechanik_, i., 1895, pp. 380 ff.).]
  2988. [Footnote 38: Fischel, "Über die Regeneration der Linse" (_Anat.
  2989. Anzeiger_, xiv., 1898, pp. 373-380).]
  2990. [Footnote 39: Cope, _The Origin of the Fittest_, 1887; _The Primary
  2991. Factors of Organic Evolution_, 1896.]
  2992. [Footnote 40: Cuénot, "La Nouvelle Théorie transformiste" (_Revue
  2993. générale des sciences_, 1894). Cf. Morgan, _Evolution and Adaptation_,
  2994. London, 1903, p. 357.]
  2995. [Footnote 41: Brown-Séquard, "Nouvelles recherches sur l'épilepsie due à
  2996. certaines lésions de la moelle épiniéere et des nerfs rachidiens"
  2997. (_Arch. de physiologie_, vol. ii., 1866, pp. 211, 422, and 497).]
  2998. [Footnote 42: Weismann, _Aufsätze über Vererbung_, Jena, 1892, pp.
  2999. 376-378, and also _Vorträge über Descendenztheorie_, Jena, 1902, vol.
  3000. ii., p. 76.]
  3001. [Footnote 43: Brown-Séquard, "Hérédité d'une affection due à une cause
  3002. accidentelle" (_Arch. de physiologie_, 1892, pp. 686 ff.).]
  3003. [Footnote 44: Voisin and Peron, "Recherches sur la toxicité urinaire
  3004. chez les épileptiques" (_Arch. de neurologie_, vol. xxiv., 1892, and
  3005. xxv., 1893. Cf. the work of Voisin, _L'Épilepsie_, Paris, 1897, pp.
  3006. 125-133).]
  3007. [Footnote 45: Charrin, Delamare and Moussu, "Transmission expérimentale
  3008. aux descendants de lésions développées chez les ascendants" (_C.R. de
  3009. l'Acad. des sciences_, vol. cxxxv., 1902, p. 191). Cf. Morgan,
  3010. _Evolution and Adaptation_, p. 257, and Delage, _L'Hérédité_, 2nd
  3011. edition, p. 388.]
  3012. [Footnote 46: Charrin and Delamare, "Hérédité cellulaire" (_C.R. de
  3013. l'Acad. des sciences_, vol. cxxxiii., 1901, pp. 69-71).]
  3014. [Footnote 47: Charrin, "L'Hérédité pathologique" (_Revue générale des
  3015. sciences_, 15 janvier 1896).]
  3016. [Footnote 48: Giard, _Controverses transformistes_, Paris, 1904, p.
  3017. 147.]
  3018. [Footnote 49: Some analogous facts, however, have been noted, all in the
  3019. vegetable world. See Blaringhem, "La Notion d'espèce et la théorie de la
  3020. mutation" (_Année psychologique_, vol. xii., 1906, pp. 95 ff.), and De
  3021. Vries, _Species and Varieties_, p. 655.]
  3022. [Footnote 50: See, on this subject, _Matière et mémoire_, chap. i.]
  3023. CHAPTER II
  3024. THE DIVERGENT DIRECTIONS OF THE EVOLUTION OF LIFE. TORPOR, INTELLIGENCE,
  3025. INSTINCT
  3026. The evolution movement would be a simple one, and we should soon have
  3027. been able to determine its direction, if life had described a single
  3028. course, like that of a solid ball shot from a cannon. But it proceeds
  3029. rather like a shell, which suddenly bursts into fragments, which
  3030. fragments, being themselves shells, burst in their turn into fragments
  3031. destined to burst again, and so on for a time incommensurably long. We
  3032. perceive only what is nearest to us, namely, the scattered movements of
  3033. the pulverized explosions. From them we have to go back, stage by stage,
  3034. to the original movement.
  3035. When a shell bursts, the particular way it breaks is explained both by
  3036. the explosive force of the powder it contains and by the resistance of
  3037. the metal. So of the way life breaks into individuals and species. It
  3038. depends, we think, on two series of causes: the resistance life meets
  3039. from inert matter, and the explosive force--due to an unstable balance
  3040. of tendencies--which life bears within itself.
  3041. The resistance of inert matter was the obstacle that had first to be
  3042. overcome. Life seems to have succeeded in this by dint of humility, by
  3043. making itself very small and very insinuating, bending to physical and
  3044. chemical forces, consenting even to go a part of the way with them, like
  3045. the switch that adopts for a while the direction of the rail it is
  3046. endeavoring to leave. Of phenomena in the simplest forms of life, it is
  3047. hard to say whether they are still physical and chemical or whether they
  3048. are already vital. Life had to enter thus into the habits of inert
  3049. matter, in order to draw it little by little, magnetized, as it were, to
  3050. another track. The animate forms that first appeared were therefore of
  3051. extreme simplicity. They were probably tiny masses of scarcely
  3052. differentiated protoplasm, outwardly resembling the amoeba observable
  3053. to-day, but possessed of the tremendous internal push that was to raise
  3054. them even to the highest forms of life. That in virtue of this push the
  3055. first organisms sought to grow as much as possible, seems likely. But
  3056. organized matter has a limit of expansion that is very quickly reached;
  3057. beyond a certain point it divides instead of growing. Ages of effort and
  3058. prodigies of subtlety were probably necessary for life to get past this
  3059. new obstacle. It succeeded in inducing an increasing number of elements,
  3060. ready to divide, to remain united. By the division of labor it knotted
  3061. between them an indissoluble bond. The complex and quasi-discontinuous
  3062. organism is thus made to function as would a continuous living mass
  3063. which had simply grown bigger.
  3064. But the real and profound causes of division were those which life bore
  3065. within its bosom. For life is tendency, and the essence of a tendency is
  3066. to develop in the form of a sheaf, creating, by its very growth,
  3067. divergent directions among which its impetus is divided. This we observe
  3068. in ourselves, in the evolution of that special tendency which we call
  3069. our character. Each of us, glancing back over his history, will find
  3070. that his child-personality, though indivisible, united in itself divers
  3071. persons, which could remain blended just because they were in their
  3072. nascent state: this indecision, so charged with promise, is one of the
  3073. greatest charms of childhood. But these interwoven personalities become
  3074. incompatible in course of growth, and, as each of us can live but one
  3075. life, a choice must perforce be made. We choose in reality without
  3076. ceasing; without ceasing, also, we abandon many things. The route we
  3077. pursue in time is strewn with the remains of all that we began to be, of
  3078. all that we might have become. But nature, which has at command an
  3079. incalculable number of lives, is in no wise bound to make such
  3080. sacrifices. She preserves the different tendencies that have bifurcated
  3081. with their growth. She creates with them diverging series of species
  3082. that will evolve separately.
  3083. These series may, moreover, be of unequal importance. The author who
  3084. begins a novel puts into his hero many things which he is obliged to
  3085. discard as he goes on. Perhaps he will take them up later in other
  3086. books, and make new characters with them, who will seem like extracts
  3087. from, or rather like complements of, the first; but they will almost
  3088. always appear somewhat poor and limited in comparison with the original
  3089. character. So with regard to the evolution of life. The bifurcations on
  3090. the way have been numerous, but there have been many blind alleys beside
  3091. the two or three highways; and of these highways themselves, only one,
  3092. that which leads through the vertebrates up to man, has been wide enough
  3093. to allow free passage to the full breath of life. We get this impression
  3094. when we compare the societies of bees and ants, for instance, with human
  3095. societies. The former are admirably ordered and united, but stereotyped;
  3096. the latter are open to every sort of progress, but divided, and
  3097. incessantly at strife with themselves. The ideal would be a society
  3098. always in progress and always in equilibrium, but this ideal is perhaps
  3099. unrealizable: the two characteristics that would fain complete each
  3100. other, which do complete each other in their embryonic state, can no
  3101. longer abide together when they grow stronger. If one could speak,
  3102. otherwise than metaphorically, of an impulse toward social life, it
  3103. might be said that the brunt of the impulse was borne along the line of
  3104. evolution ending at man, and that the rest of it was collected on the
  3105. road leading to the hymenoptera: the societies of ants and bees would
  3106. thus present the aspect complementary to ours. But this would be only a
  3107. manner of expression. There has been no particular impulse towards
  3108. social life; there is simply the general movement of life, which on
  3109. divergent lines is creating forms ever new. If societies should appear
  3110. on two of these lines, they ought to show divergence of paths at the
  3111. same time as community of impetus. They will thus develop two classes of
  3112. characteristics which we shall find vaguely complementary of each other.
  3113. So our study of the evolution movement will have to unravel a certain
  3114. number of divergent directions, and to appreciate the importance of what
  3115. has happened along each of them--in a word, to determine the nature of
  3116. the dissociated tendencies and estimate their relative proportion.
  3117. Combining these tendencies, then, we shall get an approximation, or
  3118. rather an imitation, of the indivisible motor principle whence their
  3119. impetus proceeds. Evolution will thus prove to be something entirely
  3120. different from a series of adaptations to circumstances, as mechanism
  3121. claims; entirely different also from the realization of a plan of the
  3122. whole, as maintained by the doctrine of finality.
  3123. * * * * *
  3124. That adaptation to environment is the necessary condition of evolution
  3125. we do not question for a moment. It is quite evident that a species
  3126. would disappear, should it fail to bend to the conditions of existence
  3127. which are imposed on it. But it is one thing to recognize that outer
  3128. circumstances are forces evolution must reckon with, another to claim
  3129. that they are the directing causes of evolution. This latter theory is
  3130. that of mechanism. It excludes absolutely the hypothesis of an original
  3131. impetus, I mean an internal push that has carried life, by more and more
  3132. complex forms, to higher and higher destinies. Yet this impetus is
  3133. evident, and a mere glance at fossil species shows us that life need not
  3134. have evolved at all, or might have evolved only in very restricted
  3135. limits, if it had chosen the alternative, much more convenient to
  3136. itself, of becoming anchylosed in its primitive forms. Certain
  3137. Foraminifera have not varied since the Silurian epoch. Unmoved witnesses
  3138. of the innumerable revolutions that have upheaved our planet, the
  3139. Lingulae are to-day what they were at the remotest times of the
  3140. paleozoic era.
  3141. The truth is that adaptation explains the sinuosities of the movement of
  3142. evolution, but not its general directions, still less the movement
  3143. itself.[51] The road that leads to the town is obliged to follow the ups
  3144. and downs of the hills; it _adapts itself_ to the accidents of the
  3145. ground; but the accidents of the ground are not the cause of the road,
  3146. nor have they given it its direction. At every moment they furnish it
  3147. with what is indispensable, namely, the soil on which it lies; but if we
  3148. consider the whole of the road, instead of each of its parts, the
  3149. accidents of the ground appear only as impediments or causes of delay,
  3150. for the road aims simply at the town and would fain be a straight line.
  3151. Just so as regards the evolution of life and the circumstances through
  3152. which it passes--with this difference, that evolution does not mark out
  3153. a solitary route, that it takes directions without aiming at ends, and
  3154. that it remains inventive even in its adaptations.
  3155. But, if the evolution of life is something other than a series of
  3156. adaptations to accidental circumstances, so also it is not the
  3157. realization of a plan. A plan is given in advance. It is represented, or
  3158. at least representable, before its realization. The complete execution
  3159. of it may be put off to a distant future, or even indefinitely; but the
  3160. idea is none the less formulable at the present time, in terms actually
  3161. given. If, on the contrary, evolution is a creation unceasingly renewed,
  3162. it creates, as it goes on, not only the forms of life, but the ideas
  3163. that will enable the intellect to understand it, the terms which will
  3164. serve to express it. That is to say that its future overflows its
  3165. present, and can not be sketched out therein in an idea.
  3166. There is the first error of finalism. It involves another, yet more
  3167. serious.
  3168. If life realizes a plan, it ought to manifest a greater harmony the
  3169. further it advances, just as the house shows better and better the idea
  3170. of the architect as stone is set upon stone. If, on the contrary, the
  3171. unity of life is to be found solely in the impetus that pushes it along
  3172. the road of time, the harmony is not in front, but behind. The unity is
  3173. derived from a _vis a tergo_: it is given at the start as an impulsion,
  3174. not placed at the end as an attraction. In communicating itself, the
  3175. impetus splits up more and more. Life, in proportion to its progress, is
  3176. scattered in manifestations which undoubtedly owe to their common origin
  3177. the fact that they are complementary to each other in certain aspects,
  3178. but which are none the less mutually incompatible and antagonistic. So
  3179. the discord between species will go on increasing. Indeed, we have as
  3180. yet only indicated the essential cause of it. We have supposed, for the
  3181. sake of simplicity, that each species received the impulsion in order to
  3182. pass it on to others, and that, in every direction in which life
  3183. evolves, the propagation is in a straight line. But, as a matter of
  3184. fact, there are species which are arrested; there are some that
  3185. retrogress. Evolution is not only a movement forward; in many cases we
  3186. observe a marking-time, and still more often a deviation or turning
  3187. back. It must be so, as we shall show further on, and the same causes
  3188. that divide the evolution movement often cause life to be diverted from
  3189. itself, hypnotized by the form it has just brought forth. Thence results
  3190. an increasing disorder. No doubt there is progress, if progress mean a
  3191. continual advance in the general direction determined by a first
  3192. impulsion; but this progress is accomplished only on the two or three
  3193. great lines of evolution on which forms ever more and more complex, ever
  3194. more and more high, appear; between these lines run a crowd of minor
  3195. paths in which, on the contrary, deviations, arrests, and set-backs, are
  3196. multiplied. The philosopher, who begins by laying down as a principle
  3197. that each detail is connected with some general plan of the whole, goes
  3198. from one disappointment to another as soon as he comes to examine the
  3199. facts; and, as he had put everything in the same rank, he finds that, as
  3200. the result of not allowing for accident, he must regard everything as
  3201. accidental. For accident, then, an allowance must first be made, and a
  3202. very liberal allowance. We must recognize that all is not coherent in
  3203. nature. By so doing, we shall be led to ascertain the centres around
  3204. which the incoherence crystallizes. This crystallization itself will
  3205. clarify the rest; the main directions will appear, in which life is
  3206. moving whilst developing the original impulse. True, we shall not
  3207. witness the detailed accomplishment of a plan. Nature is more and better
  3208. than a plan in course of realization. A plan is a term assigned to a
  3209. labor: it closes the future whose form it indicates. Before the
  3210. evolution of life, on the contrary, the portals of the future remain
  3211. wide open. It is a creation that goes on for ever in virtue of an
  3212. initial movement. This movement constitutes the unity of the organized
  3213. world--a prolific unity, of an infinite richness, superior to any that
  3214. the intellect could dream of, for the intellect is only one of its
  3215. aspects or products.
  3216. But it is easier to define the method than to apply it. The complete
  3217. interpretation of the evolution movement in the past, as we conceive it,
  3218. would be possible only if the history of the development of the
  3219. organized world were entirely known. Such is far from being the case.
  3220. The genealogies proposed for the different species are generally
  3221. questionable. They vary with their authors, with the theoretic views
  3222. inspiring them, and raise discussions to which the present state of
  3223. science does not admit of a final settlement. But a comparison of the
  3224. different solutions shows that the controversy bears less on the main
  3225. lines of the movement than on matters of detail; and so, by following
  3226. the main lines as closely as possible, we shall be sure of not going
  3227. astray. Moreover, they alone are important to us; for we do not aim,
  3228. like the naturalist, at finding the order of succession of different
  3229. species, but only at defining the principal directions of their
  3230. evolution. And not all of these directions have the same interest for
  3231. us: what concerns us particularly is the path that leads to man. We
  3232. shall therefore not lose sight of the fact, in following one direction
  3233. and another, that our main business is to determine the relation of man
  3234. to the animal kingdom, and the place of the animal kingdom itself in the
  3235. organized world as a whole.
  3236. * * * * *
  3237. To begin with the second point, let us say that no definite
  3238. characteristic distinguishes the plant from the animal. Attempts to
  3239. define the two kingdoms strictly have always come to naught. There is
  3240. not a single property of vegetable life that is not found, in some
  3241. degree, in certain animals; not a single characteristic feature of the
  3242. animal that has not been seen in certain species or at certain moments
  3243. in the vegetable world. Naturally, therefore, biologists enamored of
  3244. clean-cut concepts have regarded the distinction between the two
  3245. kingdoms as artificial. They would be right, if definition in this case
  3246. must be made, as in the mathematical and physical sciences, according to
  3247. certain statical attributes which belong to the object defined and are
  3248. not found in any other. Very different, in our opinion, is the kind of
  3249. definition which befits the sciences of life. There is no manifestation
  3250. of life which does not contain, in a rudimentary state--either latent or
  3251. potential,--the essential characters of most other manifestations. The
  3252. difference is in the proportions. But this very difference of proportion
  3253. will suffice to define the group, if we can establish that it is not
  3254. accidental, and that the group as it evolves, tends more and more to
  3255. emphasize these particular characters. In a word, _the group must not be
  3256. defined by the possession of certain characters, but by its tendency to
  3257. emphasize them_. From this point of view, taking tendencies rather than
  3258. states into account, we find that vegetables and animals may be
  3259. precisely defined and distinguished, and that they correspond to two
  3260. divergent developments of life.
  3261. This divergence is shown, first, in the method of alimentation. We know
  3262. that the vegetable derives directly from the air and water and soil the
  3263. elements necessary to maintain life, especially carbon and nitrogen,
  3264. which it takes in mineral form. The animal, on the contrary, cannot
  3265. assimilate these elements unless they have already been fixed for it in
  3266. organic substances by plants, or by animals which directly or indirectly
  3267. owe them to plants; so that ultimately the vegetable nourishes the
  3268. animal. True, this law allows of many exceptions among vegetables. We do
  3269. not hesitate to class amongst vegetables the Drosera, the Dionaea, the
  3270. Pinguicula, which are insectivorous plants. On the other hand, the
  3271. fungi, which occupy so considerable a place in the vegetable world, feed
  3272. like animals: whether they are ferments, saprophytes or parasites, it is
  3273. to already formed organic substances that they owe their nourishment. It
  3274. is therefore impossible to draw from this difference any _static_
  3275. definition such as would automatically settle in any particular case the
  3276. question whether we are dealing with a plant or an animal. But the
  3277. difference may provide the beginning of a _dynamic_ definition of the
  3278. two kingdoms, in that it marks the two divergent directions in which
  3279. vegetables and animals have taken their course. It is a remarkable fact
  3280. that the fungi, which nature has spread all over the earth in such
  3281. extraordinary profusion, have not been able to evolve. Organically they
  3282. do not rise above tissues which, in the higher vegetables, are formed in
  3283. the embryonic sac of the ovary, and precede the germinative development
  3284. of the new individual.[52] They might be called the abortive children of
  3285. the vegetable world. Their different species are like so many blind
  3286. alleys, as if, by renouncing the mode of alimentation customary amongst
  3287. vegetables, they had been brought to a standstill on the highway of
  3288. vegetable evolution. As to the Drosera, the Dionaea, and insectivorous
  3289. plants in general, they are fed by their roots, like other plants; they
  3290. too fix, by their green parts, the carbon of the carbonic acid in the
  3291. atmosphere. Their faculty of capturing, absorbing and digesting insects
  3292. must have arisen late, in quite exceptional cases where the soil was too
  3293. poor to furnish sufficient nourishment. In a general way, then, if we
  3294. attach less importance to the presence of special characters than to
  3295. their tendency to develop, and if we regard as essential that tendency
  3296. along which evolution has been able to continue indefinitely, we may say
  3297. that vegetables are distinguished from animals by their power of
  3298. creating organic matter out of mineral elements which they draw directly
  3299. from the air and earth and water. But now we come to another difference,
  3300. deeper than this, though not unconnected with it.
  3301. The animal, being unable to fix directly the carbon and nitrogen which
  3302. are everywhere to be found, has to seek for its nourishment vegetables
  3303. which have already fixed these elements, or animals which have taken
  3304. them from the vegetable kingdom. So the animal must be able to move.
  3305. From the amoeba, which thrusts out its pseudopodia at random to seize
  3306. the organic matter scattered in a drop of water, up to the higher
  3307. animals which have sense-organs with which to recognize their prey,
  3308. locomotor organs to go and seize it, and a nervous system to coördinate
  3309. their movements with their sensations, animal life is characterized, in
  3310. its general direction, by mobility in space. In its most rudimentary
  3311. form, the animal is a tiny mass of protoplasm enveloped at most in a
  3312. thin albuminous pellicle which allows full freedom for change of shape
  3313. and movement. The vegetable cell, on the contrary, is surrounded by a
  3314. membrane of cellulose, which condemns it to immobility. And, from the
  3315. bottom to the top of the vegetable kingdom, there are the same habits
  3316. growing more and more sedentary, the plant having no need to move, and
  3317. finding around it, in the air and water and soil in which it is placed,
  3318. the mineral elements it can appropriate directly. It is true that
  3319. phenomena of movement are seen in plants. Darwin has written a
  3320. well-known work on the movements of climbing plants. He studied also the
  3321. contrivances of certain insectivorous plants, such as the Drosera and
  3322. the Dionaea, to seize their prey. The leaf-movements of the acacia, the
  3323. sensitive plant, etc., are well known. Moreover, the circulation of the
  3324. vegetable protoplasm within its sheath bears witness to its relationship
  3325. to the protoplasm of animals, whilst in a large number of animal species
  3326. (generally parasites) phenomena of fixation, analogous to those of
  3327. vegetables, can be observed.[53] Here, again, it would be a mistake to
  3328. claim that fixity and mobility are the two characters which enable us to
  3329. decide, by simple inspection alone, whether we have before us a plant or
  3330. an animal. But fixity, in the animal, generally seems like a torpor into
  3331. which the species has fallen, a refusal to evolve further in a certain
  3332. direction; it is closely akin to parasitism and is accompanied by
  3333. features that recall those of vegetable life. On the other hand, the
  3334. movements of vegetables have neither the frequency nor the variety of
  3335. those of animals. Generally, they involve only part of the organism and
  3336. scarcely ever extend to the whole. In the exceptional cases in which a
  3337. vague spontaneity appears in vegetables, it is as if we beheld the
  3338. accidental awakening of an activity normally asleep. In short, although
  3339. both mobility and fixity exist in the vegetable as in the animal world,
  3340. the balance is clearly in favor of fixity in the one case and of
  3341. mobility in the other. These two opposite tendencies are so plainly
  3342. directive of the two evolutions that the two kingdoms might almost be
  3343. defined by them. But fixity and mobility, again, are only superficial
  3344. signs of tendencies that are still deeper.
  3345. Between mobility and consciousness there is an obvious relationship. No
  3346. doubt, the consciousness of the higher organisms seems bound up with
  3347. certain cerebral arrangements. The more the nervous system develops,
  3348. the more numerous and more precise become the movements among which it
  3349. can choose; the clearer, also, is the consciousness that accompanies
  3350. them. But neither this mobility nor this choice nor consequently this
  3351. consciousness involves as a necessary condition the presence of a
  3352. nervous system; the latter has only canalized in definite directions,
  3353. and brought up to a higher degree of intensity, a rudimentary and vague
  3354. activity, diffused throughout the mass of the organized substance. The
  3355. lower we descend in the animal series, the more the nervous centres are
  3356. simplified, and the more, too, they separate from each other, till
  3357. finally the nervous elements disappear, merged in the mass of a less
  3358. differentiated organism. But it is the same with all the other
  3359. apparatus, with all the other anatomical elements; and it would be as
  3360. absurd to refuse consciousness to an animal because it has no brain as
  3361. to declare it incapable of nourishing itself because it has no stomach.
  3362. The truth is that the nervous system arises, like the other systems,
  3363. from a division of labor. It does not create the function, it only
  3364. brings it to a higher degree of intensity and precision by giving it the
  3365. double form of reflex and voluntary activity. To accomplish a true
  3366. reflex movement, a whole mechanism is necessary, set up in the spinal
  3367. cord or the medulla. To choose voluntarily between several definite
  3368. courses of action, cerebral centres are necessary, that is, crossways
  3369. from which paths start, leading to motor mechanisms of diverse form but
  3370. equal precision. But where nervous elements are not yet canalized, still
  3371. less concentrated into a system, there is something from which, by a
  3372. kind of splitting, both the reflex and the voluntary will arise,
  3373. something which has neither the mechanical precision of the former nor
  3374. the intelligent hesitations of the latter, but which, partaking of both
  3375. it may be infinitesimally, is a reaction simply undecided, and therefore
  3376. vaguely conscious. This amounts to saying that the humblest organism is
  3377. conscious in proportion to its power to move _freely_. Is consciousness
  3378. here, in relation to movement, the effect or the cause? In one sense it
  3379. is the cause, since it has to direct locomotion. But in another sense it
  3380. is the effect; for it is the motor activity that maintains it, and, once
  3381. this activity disappears, consciousness dies away or rather falls
  3382. asleep. In crustaceans such as the rhizocephala, which must formerly
  3383. have shown a more differentiated structure, fixity and parasitism
  3384. accompany the degeneration and almost complete disappearance of the
  3385. nervous system. Since, in such a case, the progress of organization must
  3386. have localized all the conscious activity in nervous centres, we may
  3387. conjecture that consciousness is even weaker in animals of this kind
  3388. than in organisms much less differentiated, which have never had nervous
  3389. centres but have remained mobile.
  3390. How then could the plant, which is fixed in the earth and finds its food
  3391. on the spot, have developed in the direction of conscious activity? The
  3392. membrane of cellulose, in which the protoplasm wraps itself up, not only
  3393. prevents the simplest vegetable organism from moving, but screens it
  3394. also, in some measure, from those outer stimuli which act on the
  3395. sensibility of the animal as irritants and prevent it from going to
  3396. sleep.[54] The plant is therefore unconscious. Here again, however, we
  3397. must beware of radical distinctions. "Unconscious" and "conscious" are
  3398. not two labels which can be mechanically fastened, the one on every
  3399. vegetable cell, the other on all animals. While consciousness sleeps in
  3400. the animal which has degenerated into a motionless parasite, it probably
  3401. awakens in the vegetable that has regained liberty of movement, and
  3402. awakens in just the degree to which the vegetable has reconquered this
  3403. liberty. Nevertheless, consciousness and unconsciousness mark the
  3404. directions in which the two kingdoms have developed, in this sense, that
  3405. to find the best specimens of consciousness in the animal we must
  3406. _ascend_ to the highest representatives of the series, whereas, to find
  3407. probable cases of vegetable consciousness, we must _descend_ as low as
  3408. possible in the scale of plants--down to the zoospores of the algae, for
  3409. instance, and, more generally, to those unicellular organisms which may
  3410. be said to hesitate between the vegetable form and animality. From this
  3411. standpoint, and in this measure, we should define the animal by
  3412. sensibility and awakened consciousness, the vegetable by consciousness
  3413. asleep and by insensibility.
  3414. To sum up, the vegetable manufactures organic substances directly with
  3415. mineral substances; as a rule, this aptitude enables it to dispense with
  3416. movement and so with feeling. Animals, which are obliged to go in search
  3417. of their food, have evolved in the direction of locomotor activity, and
  3418. consequently of a consciousness more and more distinct, more and more
  3419. ample.
  3420. * * * * *
  3421. Now, it seems to us most probable that the animal cell and the vegetable
  3422. cell are derived from a common stock, and that the first living
  3423. organisms oscillated between the vegetable and animal form,
  3424. participating in both at once. Indeed, we have just seen that the
  3425. characteristic tendencies of the evolution of the two kingdoms, although
  3426. divergent, coexist even now, both in the plant and in the animal. The
  3427. proportion alone differs. Ordinarily, one of the two tendencies covers
  3428. or crushes down the other, but in exceptional circumstances the
  3429. suppressed one starts up and regains the place it had lost. The
  3430. mobility and consciousness of the vegetable cell are not so sound asleep
  3431. that they cannot rouse themselves when circumstances permit or demand
  3432. it; and, on the other hand, the evolution of the animal kingdom has
  3433. always been retarded, or stopped, or dragged back, by the tendency it
  3434. has kept toward the vegetative life. However full, however overflowing
  3435. the activity of an animal species may appear, torpor and unconsciousness
  3436. are always lying in wait for it. It keeps up its rôle only by effort, at
  3437. the price of fatigue. Along the route on which the animal has evolved,
  3438. there have been numberless shortcomings and cases of decay, generally
  3439. associated with parasitic habits; they are so many shuntings on to the
  3440. vegetative life. Thus, everything bears out the belief that vegetable
  3441. and animal are descended from a common ancestor which united the
  3442. tendencies of both in a rudimentary state.
  3443. But the two tendencies mutually implied in this rudimentary form became
  3444. dissociated as they grew. Hence the world of plants with its fixity and
  3445. insensibility, hence the animals with their mobility and consciousness.
  3446. There is no need, in order to explain this dividing into two, to bring
  3447. in any mysterious force. It is enough to point out that the living being
  3448. leans naturally toward what is most convenient to it, and that
  3449. vegetables and animals have chosen two different kinds of convenience in
  3450. the way of procuring the carbon and nitrogen they need. Vegetables
  3451. continually and mechanically draw these elements from an environment
  3452. that continually provides it. Animals, by action that is discontinuous,
  3453. concentrated in certain moments, and conscious, go to find these bodies
  3454. in organisms that have already fixed them. They are two different ways
  3455. of being industrious, or perhaps we may prefer to say, of being idle.
  3456. For this very reason we doubt whether nervous elements, however
  3457. rudimentary, will ever be found in the plant. What corresponds in it to
  3458. the directing will of the animal is, we believe, the direction in which
  3459. it bends the energy of the solar radiation when it uses it to break the
  3460. connection of the carbon with the oxygen in carbonic acid. What
  3461. corresponds in it to the sensibility of the animal is the
  3462. impressionability, quite of its kind, of its chlorophyl light. Now, a
  3463. nervous system being pre-eminently a mechanism which serves as
  3464. intermediary between sensations and volitions, the true "nervous system"
  3465. of the plant seems to be the mechanism or rather chemicism _sui generis_
  3466. which serves as intermediary between the impressionability of its
  3467. chlorophyl to light and the producing of starch: which amounts to saying
  3468. that the plant can have no nervous elements, and that _the same impetus
  3469. that has led the animal to give itself nerves and nerve centres must
  3470. have ended, in the plant, in the chlorophyllian function_.[55]
  3471. * * * * *
  3472. This first glance over the organized world will enable us to ascertain
  3473. more precisely what unites the two kingdoms, and also what separates
  3474. them.
  3475. Suppose, as we suggested in the preceding chapter, that at the root of
  3476. life there is an effort to engraft on to the necessity of physical
  3477. forces the largest possible amount of _indetermination_. This effort
  3478. cannot result in the creation of energy, or, if it does, the quantity
  3479. created does not belong to the order of magnitude apprehended by our
  3480. senses and instruments of measurement, our experience and science. All
  3481. that the effort can do, then, is to make the best of a pre-existing
  3482. energy which it finds at its disposal. Now, it finds only one way of
  3483. succeeding in this, namely, to secure such an accumulation of potential
  3484. energy from matter, that it can get, at any moment, the amount of work
  3485. it needs for its action, simply by pulling a trigger. The effort itself
  3486. possesses only that power of releasing. But the work of releasing,
  3487. although always the same and always smaller than any given quantity,
  3488. will be the more effective the heavier the weight it makes fall and the
  3489. greater the height--or, in other words, the greater the sum of potential
  3490. energy accumulated and disposable. As a matter of fact, the principal
  3491. source of energy usable on the surface of our planet is the sun. So the
  3492. problem was this: to obtain from the sun that it should partially and
  3493. provisionally suspend, here and there, on the surface of the earth, its
  3494. continual outpour of usable energy, and store a certain quantity of it,
  3495. in the form of unused energy, in appropriate reservoirs, whence it could
  3496. be drawn at the desired moment, at the desired spot, in the desired
  3497. direction. The substances forming the food of animals are just such
  3498. reservoirs. Made of very complex molecules holding a considerable amount
  3499. of chemical energy in the potential state, they are like explosives
  3500. which only need a spark to set free the energy stored within them. Now,
  3501. it is probable that life tended at the beginning to compass at one and
  3502. the same time both the manufacture of the explosive and the explosion by
  3503. which it is utilized. In this case, the same organism that had directly
  3504. stored the energy of the solar radiation would have expended it in free
  3505. movements in space. And for that reason we must presume that the first
  3506. living beings sought on the one hand to accumulate, without ceasing,
  3507. energy borrowed from the sun, and on the other hand to expend it, in a
  3508. discontinuous and explosive way, in movements of locomotion. Even
  3509. to-day, perhaps, a chlorophyl-bearing Infusorian such as the Euglena may
  3510. symbolize this primordial tendency of life, though in a mean form,
  3511. incapable of evolving. Is the divergent development of the two kingdoms
  3512. related to what one may call the oblivion of each kingdom as regards one
  3513. of the two halves of the programme? Or rather, which is more likely, was
  3514. the very nature of the matter, that life found confronting it on our
  3515. planet, opposed to the possibility of the two tendencies evolving very
  3516. far together in the same organism? What is certain is that the vegetable
  3517. has trended principally in the first direction and the animal in the
  3518. second. But if, from the very first, in making the explosive, nature had
  3519. for object the explosion, then it is the evolution of the animal, rather
  3520. than that of the vegetable, that indicates, on the whole, the
  3521. fundamental direction of life.
  3522. The "harmony" of the two kingdoms, the complementary characters they
  3523. display, might then be due to the fact that they develop two tendencies
  3524. which at first were fused in one. The more the single original tendency
  3525. grows, the harder it finds it to keep united in the same living being
  3526. those two elements which in the rudimentary state implied each other.
  3527. Hence a parting in two, hence two divergent evolutions; hence also two
  3528. series of characters opposed in certain points, complementary in others,
  3529. but, whether opposed or complementary, always preserving an appearance
  3530. of kinship. While the animal evolved, not without accidents along the
  3531. way, toward a freer and freer expenditure of discontinuous energy, the
  3532. plant perfected rather its system of accumulation without moving. We
  3533. shall not dwell on this second point. Suffice it to say that the plant
  3534. must have been greatly benefited, in its turn, by a new division,
  3535. analogous to that between plants and animals. While the primitive
  3536. vegetable cell had to fix by itself both its carbon and its nitrogen, it
  3537. became able almost to give up the second of these two functions as soon
  3538. as microscopic vegetables came forward which leaned in this direction
  3539. exclusively, and even specialized diversely in this still complicated
  3540. business. The microbes that fix the nitrogen of the air and those which
  3541. convert the ammoniacal compounds into nitrous ones, and these again into
  3542. nitrates, have, by the same splitting up of a tendency primitively one,
  3543. rendered to the whole vegetable world the same kind of service as the
  3544. vegetables in general have rendered to animals. If a special kingdom
  3545. were to be made for these microscopic vegetables, it might be said that
  3546. in the microbes of the soil, the vegetables and the animals, we have
  3547. before us the _analysis_, carried out by the matter that life found at
  3548. its disposal on our planet, of all that life contained, at the outset,
  3549. in a state of reciprocal implication. Is this, properly speaking, a
  3550. "division of labor"? These words do not give the exact idea of
  3551. evolution, such as we conceive it. Wherever there is division of labor,
  3552. there is _association_ and also _convergence_ of effort. Now, the
  3553. evolution we are speaking of is never achieved by means of association,
  3554. but by _dissociation_; it never tends toward convergence, but toward
  3555. _divergence_ of efforts. The harmony between terms that are mutually
  3556. complementary in certain points is not, in our opinion, produced, in
  3557. course of progress, by a reciprocal adaptation; on the contrary, it is
  3558. complete only at the start. It arises from an original identity, from
  3559. the fact that the evolutionary process, splaying out like a sheaf,
  3560. sunders, in proportion to their simultaneous growth, terms which at
  3561. first completed each other so well that they coalesced.
  3562. Now, the elements into which a tendency splits up are far from
  3563. possessing the same importance, or, above all, the same power to evolve.
  3564. We have just distinguished three different kingdoms, if one may so
  3565. express it, in the organized world. While the first comprises only
  3566. microorganisms which have remained in the rudimentary state, animals and
  3567. vegetables have taken their flight toward very lofty fortunes. Such,
  3568. indeed, is generally the case when a tendency divides. Among the
  3569. divergent developments to which it gives rise, some go on indefinitely,
  3570. others come more or less quickly to the end of their tether. These
  3571. latter do not issue directly from the primitive tendency, but from one
  3572. of the elements into which it has divided; they are residual
  3573. developments made and left behind on the way by some truly elementary
  3574. tendency which continues to evolve. Now, these truly elementary
  3575. tendencies, we think, bear a mark by which they may be recognized.
  3576. This mark is like a trace, still visible in each, of what was in the
  3577. original tendency of which they represent the elementary directions. The
  3578. elements of a tendency are not like objects set beside each other in
  3579. space and mutually exclusive, but rather like psychic states, each of
  3580. which, although it be itself to begin with, yet partakes of others, and
  3581. so virtually includes in itself the whole personality to which it
  3582. belongs. There is no real manifestation of life, we said, that does not
  3583. show us, in a rudimentary or latent state, the characters of other
  3584. manifestations. Conversely, when we meet, on one line of evolution, a
  3585. recollection, so to speak, of what is developed along other lines, we
  3586. must conclude that we have before us dissociated elements of one and the
  3587. same original tendency. In this sense, vegetables and animals represent
  3588. the two great divergent developments of life. Though the plant is
  3589. distinguished from the animal by fixity and insensibility, movement and
  3590. consciousness sleep in it as recollections which may waken. But, beside
  3591. these normally sleeping recollections, there are others awake and
  3592. active, just those, namely, whose activity does not obstruct the
  3593. development of the elementary tendency itself. We may then formulate
  3594. this law: _When a tendency splits up in the course of its development,
  3595. each of the special tendencies which thus arise tries to preserve and
  3596. develop everything in the primitive tendency that is not incompatible
  3597. with the work for which it is specialized._ This explains precisely the
  3598. fact we dwelt on in the preceding chapter, viz., the formation of
  3599. identical complex mechanisms on independent lines of evolution. Certain
  3600. deep-seated analogies between the animal and the vegetable have probably
  3601. no other cause: sexual generation is perhaps only a luxury for the
  3602. plant, but to the animal it was a necessity, and the plant must have
  3603. been driven to it by the same impetus which impelled the animal thereto,
  3604. a primitive, original impetus, anterior to the separation of the two
  3605. kingdoms. The same may be said of the tendency of the vegetable towards
  3606. a growing complexity. This tendency is essential to the animal kingdom,
  3607. ever tormented by the need of more and more extended and effective
  3608. action. But the vegetable, condemned to fixity and insensibility,
  3609. exhibits the same tendency only because it received at the outset the
  3610. same impulsion. Recent experiments show that it varies at random when
  3611. the period of "mutation" arrives; whereas the animal must have evolved,
  3612. we believe, in much more definite directions. But we will not dwell
  3613. further on this original doubling of the modes of life. Let us come to
  3614. the evolution of animals, in which we are more particularly interested.
  3615. What constitutes animality, we said, is the faculty of utilizing a
  3616. releasing mechanism for the conversion of as much stored-up potential
  3617. energy as possible into "explosive" actions. In the beginning the
  3618. explosion is haphazard, and does not choose its direction. Thus the
  3619. amoeba thrusts out its pseudopodic prolongations in all directions at
  3620. once. But, as we rise in the animal scale, the form of the body itself
  3621. is observed to indicate a certain number of very definite directions
  3622. along which the energy travels. These directions are marked by so many
  3623. chains of nervous elements. Now, the nervous element has gradually
  3624. emerged from the barely differentiated mass of organized tissue. It may,
  3625. therefore, be surmised that in the nervous element, as soon as it
  3626. appears, and also in its appendages, the faculty of suddenly freeing the
  3627. gradually stored-up energy is concentrated. No doubt, every living cell
  3628. expends energy without ceasing, in order to maintain its equilibrium.
  3629. The vegetable cell, torpid from the start, is entirely absorbed in this
  3630. work of maintenance alone, as if it took for end what must at first have
  3631. been only a means. But, in the animal, all points to action, that is, to
  3632. the utilization of energy for movements from place to place. True, every
  3633. animal cell expends a good deal--often the whole--of the energy at its
  3634. disposal in keeping itself alive; but the organism as a whole tries to
  3635. attract as much energy as possible to those points where the locomotive
  3636. movements are effected. So that where a nervous system exists, with its
  3637. complementary sense-organs and motor apparatus, everything should happen
  3638. as if the rest of the body had, as its essential function, to prepare
  3639. for these and pass on to them, at the moment required, that force which
  3640. they are to liberate by a sort of explosion.
  3641. The part played by food amongst the higher animals is, indeed,
  3642. extremely complex. In the first place it serves to repair tissues, then
  3643. it provides the animal with the heat necessary to render it as
  3644. independent as possible of changes in external temperature. Thus it
  3645. preserves, supports, and maintains the organism in which the nervous
  3646. system is set and on which the nervous elements have to live. But these
  3647. nervous elements would have no reason for existence if the organism did
  3648. not pass to them, and especially to the muscles they control, a certain
  3649. energy to expend; and it may even be conjectured that there, in the
  3650. main, is the essential and ultimate destination of food. This does not
  3651. mean that the greater part of the food is used in this work. A state may
  3652. have to make enormous expenditure to secure the return of taxes, and the
  3653. sum which it will have to dispose of, after deducting the cost of
  3654. collection, will perhaps be very small: that sum is, none the less, the
  3655. reason for the tax and for all that has been spent to obtain its return.
  3656. So it is with the energy which the animal demands of its food.
  3657. Many facts seem to indicate that the nervous and muscular elements stand
  3658. in this relation towards the rest of the organism. Glance first at the
  3659. distribution of alimentary substances among the different elements of
  3660. the living body. These substances fall into two classes, one the
  3661. quaternary or albuminoid, the other the ternary, including the
  3662. carbohydrates and the fats. The albuminoids are properly plastic,
  3663. destined to repair the tissues--although, owing to the carbon they
  3664. contain, they are capable of providing energy on occasion. But the
  3665. function of supplying energy has devolved more particularly on the
  3666. second class of substances: these, being deposited in the cell rather
  3667. than forming part of its substance, convey to it, in the form of
  3668. chemical potential, an expansive energy that may be directly converted
  3669. into either movement or heat. In short, the chief function of the
  3670. albuminoids is to repair the machine, while the function of the other
  3671. class of substances is to supply power. It is natural that the
  3672. albuminoids should have no specially allotted destination, since every
  3673. part of the machine has to be maintained. But not so with the other
  3674. substances. The carbohydrates are distributed very unequally, and this
  3675. inequality of distribution seems to us in the highest degree
  3676. instructive.
  3677. Conveyed by the arterial blood in the form of glucose, these substances
  3678. are deposited, in the form of glycogen, in the different cells forming
  3679. the tissues. We know that one of the principal functions of the liver is
  3680. to maintain at a constant level the quantity of glucose held by the
  3681. blood, by means of the reserves of glycogen secreted by the hepatic
  3682. cells. Now, in this circulation of glucose and accumulation of glycogen,
  3683. it is easy to see that the effect is as if the whole effort of the
  3684. organism were directed towards providing with potential energy the
  3685. elements of both the muscular and the nervous tissues. The organism
  3686. proceeds differently in the two cases, but it arrives at the same
  3687. result. In the first case, it provides the muscle-cell with a large
  3688. reserve deposited in advance: the quantity of glycogen contained in the
  3689. muscles is, indeed, enormous in comparison with what is found in the
  3690. other tissues. In the nervous tissue, on the contrary, the reserve is
  3691. small (the nervous elements, whose function is merely to liberate the
  3692. potential energy stored in the muscle, never have to furnish much work
  3693. at one time); but the remarkable thing is that this reserve is restored
  3694. by the blood at the very moment that it is expended, so that the nerve
  3695. is instantly recharged with potential energy. Muscular tissue and
  3696. nervous tissue are, therefore, both privileged, the one in that it is
  3697. stocked with a large reserve of energy, the other in that it is always
  3698. served at the instant it is in need and to the exact extent of its
  3699. requirements.
  3700. More particularly, it is from the sensori-motor system that the call for
  3701. glycogen, the potential energy, comes, as if the rest of the organism
  3702. were simply there in order to transmit force to the nervous system and
  3703. to the muscles which the nerves control. True, when we think of the part
  3704. played by the nervous system (even the sensori-motor system) as
  3705. regulator of the organic life, it may well be asked whether, in this
  3706. exchange of good offices between it and the rest of the body, the
  3707. nervous system is indeed a master that the body serves. But we shall
  3708. already incline to this hypothesis when we consider, even in the static
  3709. state only, the distribution of potential energy among the tissues; and
  3710. we shall be entirely convinced of it when we reflect upon the conditions
  3711. in which the energy is expended and restored. For suppose the
  3712. sensori-motor system is a system like the others, of the same rank as
  3713. the others. Borne by the whole of the organism, it will wait until an
  3714. excess of chemical potential is supplied to it before it performs any
  3715. work. In other words, it is the production of glycogen which will
  3716. regulate the consumption by the nerves and muscles. On the contrary, if
  3717. the sensori-motor system is the actual master, the duration and extent
  3718. of its action will be independent, to a certain extent at least, of the
  3719. reserve of glycogen that it holds, and even of that contained in the
  3720. whole of the organism. It will perform work, and the other tissues will
  3721. have to arrange as they can to supply it with potential energy. Now,
  3722. this is precisely what does take place, as is shown in particular by the
  3723. experiments of Morat and Dufourt.[56] While the glycogenic function of
  3724. the liver depends on the action of the excitory nerves which control it,
  3725. the action of these nerves is subordinated to the action of those which
  3726. stimulate the locomotor muscles--in this sense, that the muscles begin
  3727. by expending without calculation, thus consuming glycogen, impoverishing
  3728. the blood of its glucose, and finally causing the liver, which has had
  3729. to pour into the impoverished blood some of its reserve of glycogen, to
  3730. manufacture a fresh supply. From the sensori-motor system, then,
  3731. everything starts; on that system everything converges; and we may say,
  3732. without metaphor, that the rest of the organism is at its service.
  3733. Consider again what happens in a prolonged fast. It is a remarkable fact
  3734. that in animals that have died of hunger the brain is found to be almost
  3735. unimpaired, while the other organs have lost more or less of their
  3736. weight and their cells have undergone profound changes.[57] It seems as
  3737. though the rest of the body had sustained the nervous system to the last
  3738. extremity, treating itself simply as the means of which the nervous
  3739. system is the end.
  3740. To sum up: if we agree, in short, to understand by "the sensori-motor
  3741. system" the cerebro-spinal nervous system together with the sensorial
  3742. apparatus in which it is prolonged and the locomotor muscles it
  3743. controls, we may say that a higher organism is essentially a
  3744. sensori-motor system installed on systems of digestion, respiration,
  3745. circulation, secretion, etc., whose function it is to repair, cleanse
  3746. and protect it, to create an unvarying internal environment for it, and
  3747. above all to pass it potential energy to convert into locomotive
  3748. movement.[58] It is true that the more the nervous function is
  3749. perfected, the more must the functions required to maintain it develop,
  3750. and the more exacting, consequently, they become for themselves. As the
  3751. nervous activity has emerged from the protoplasmic mass in which it was
  3752. almost drowned, it has had to summon around itself activities of all
  3753. kinds for its support. These could only be developed on other
  3754. activities, which again implied others, and so on indefinitely. Thus it
  3755. is that the complexity of functioning of the higher organisms goes on to
  3756. infinity. The study of one of these organisms therefore takes us round
  3757. in a circle, as if everything was a means to everything else. But the
  3758. circle has a centre, none the less, and that is the system of nervous
  3759. elements stretching between the sensory organs and the motor apparatus.
  3760. We will not dwell here on a point we have treated at length in a former
  3761. work. Let us merely recall that the progress of the nervous system has
  3762. been effected both in the direction of a more precise adaptation of
  3763. movements and in that of a greater latitude left to the living being to
  3764. choose between them. These two tendencies may appear antagonistic, and
  3765. indeed they are so; but a nervous chain, even in its most rudimentary
  3766. form, successfully reconciles them. On the one hand, it marks a
  3767. well-defined track between one point of the periphery and another, the
  3768. one sensory, the other motor. It has therefore canalized an activity
  3769. which was originally diffused in the protoplasmic mass. But, on the
  3770. other hand, the elements that compose it are probably discontinuous; at
  3771. any rate, even supposing they anastomose, they exhibit a _functional_
  3772. discontinuity, for each of them ends in a kind of cross-road where
  3773. probably the nervous current may choose its course. From the humblest
  3774. Monera to the best endowed insects, and up to the most intelligent
  3775. vertebrates, the progress realized has been above all a progress of the
  3776. nervous system, coupled at every stage with all the new constructions
  3777. and complications of mechanism that this progress required. As we
  3778. foreshadowed in the beginning of this work, the rôle of life is to
  3779. insert some _indetermination_ into matter. Indeterminate, _i.e._
  3780. unforeseeable, are the forms it creates in the course of its evolution.
  3781. More and more indeterminate also, more and more free, is the activity to
  3782. which these forms serve as the vehicle. A nervous system, with neurones
  3783. placed end to end in such wise that, at the extremity of each, manifold
  3784. ways open in which manifold questions present themselves, is a veritable
  3785. _reservoir of indetermination_. That the main energy of the vital
  3786. impulse has been spent in creating apparatus of this kind is, we
  3787. believe, what a glance over the organized world as a whole easily shows.
  3788. But concerning the vital impulse itself a few explanations are
  3789. necessary.
  3790. * * * * *
  3791. It must not be forgotten that the force which is evolving throughout the
  3792. organized world is a limited force, which is always seeking to transcend
  3793. itself and always remains inadequate to the work it would fain produce.
  3794. The errors and puerilities of radical finalism are due to the
  3795. misapprehension of this point. It has represented the whole of the
  3796. living world as a construction, and a construction analogous to a human
  3797. work. All the pieces have been arranged with a view to the best possible
  3798. functioning of the machine. Each species has its reason for existence,
  3799. its part to play, its allotted place; and all join together, as it were,
  3800. in a musical concert, wherein the seeming discords are really meant to
  3801. bring out a fundamental harmony. In short, all goes on in nature as in
  3802. the works of human genius, where, though the result may be trifling,
  3803. there is at least perfect adequacy between the object made and the work
  3804. of making it.
  3805. Nothing of the kind in the evolution of life. There, the disproportion
  3806. is striking between the work and the result. From the bottom to the top
  3807. of the organized world we do indeed find one great effort; but most
  3808. often this effort turns short, sometimes paralyzed by contrary forces,
  3809. sometimes diverted from what it should do by what it does, absorbed by
  3810. the form it is engaged in taking, hypnotized by it as by a mirror. Even
  3811. in its most perfect works, though it seems to have triumphed over
  3812. external resistances and also over its own, it is at the mercy of the
  3813. materiality which it has had to assume. It is what each of us may
  3814. experience in himself. Our freedom, in the very movements by which it is
  3815. affirmed, creates the growing habits that will stifle it if it fails to
  3816. renew itself by a constant effort: it is dogged by automatism. The most
  3817. living thought becomes frigid in the formula that expresses it. The word
  3818. turns against the idea.
  3819. The letter kills the spirit. And our most ardent enthusiasm, as soon as
  3820. it is externalized into action, is so naturally congealed into the cold
  3821. calculation of interest or vanity, the one takes so easily the shape of
  3822. the other, that we might confuse them together, doubt our own
  3823. sincerity, deny goodness and love, if we did not know that the dead
  3824. retain for a time the features of the living.
  3825. The profound cause of this discordance lies in an irremediable
  3826. difference of rhythm. Life in general is mobility itself; particular
  3827. manifestations of life accept this mobility reluctantly, and constantly
  3828. lag behind. It is always going ahead; they want to mark time. Evolution
  3829. in general would fain go on in a straight line; each special evolution
  3830. is a kind of circle. Like eddies of dust raised by the wind as it
  3831. passes, the living turn upon themselves, borne up by the great blast of
  3832. life. They are therefore relatively stable, and counterfeit immobility
  3833. so well that we treat each of them as a _thing_ rather than as a
  3834. _progress_, forgetting that the very permanence of their form is only
  3835. the outline of a movement. At times, however, in a fleeting vision, the
  3836. invisible breath that bears them is materialized before our eyes. We
  3837. have this sudden illumination before certain forms of maternal love, so
  3838. striking, and in most animals so touching, observable even in the
  3839. solicitude of the plant for its seed. This love, in which some have seen
  3840. the great mystery of life, may possibly deliver us life's secret. It
  3841. shows us each generation leaning over the generation that shall follow.
  3842. It allows us a glimpse of the fact that the living being is above all a
  3843. thoroughfare, and that the essence of life is in the movement by which
  3844. life is transmitted.
  3845. This contrast between life in general, and the forms in which it is
  3846. manifested, has everywhere the same character. It might be said that
  3847. life tends toward the utmost possible action, but that each species
  3848. prefers to contribute the slightest possible effort. Regarded in what
  3849. constitutes its true essence, namely, as a transition from species to
  3850. species, life is a continually growing action. But each of the species,
  3851. through which life passes, aims only at its own convenience. It goes
  3852. for that which demands the least labor. Absorbed in the form it is about
  3853. to take, it falls into a partial sleep, in which it ignores almost all
  3854. the rest of life; it fashions itself so as to take the greatest possible
  3855. advantage of its immediate environment with the least possible trouble.
  3856. Accordingly, the act by which life goes forward to the creation of a new
  3857. form, and the act by which this form is shaped, are two different and
  3858. often antagonistic movements. The first is continuous with the second,
  3859. but cannot continue in it without being drawn aside from its direction,
  3860. as would happen to a man leaping, if, in order to clear the obstacle, he
  3861. had to turn his eyes from it and look at himself all the while.
  3862. Living forms are, by their very definition, forms that are able to live.
  3863. In whatever way the adaptation of the organism to its circumstances is
  3864. explained, it has necessarily been sufficient, since the species has
  3865. subsisted. In this sense, each of the successive species that
  3866. paleontology and zoology describes was a _success_ carried off by life.
  3867. But we get a very different impression when we refer each species to the
  3868. movement that has left it behind on its way, instead of to the
  3869. conditions into which it has been set. Often this movement has turned
  3870. aside; very often, too, it has stopped short; what was to have been a
  3871. thoroughfare has become a terminus. From this new point of view, failure
  3872. seems the rule, success exceptional and always imperfect. We shall see
  3873. that, of the four main directions along which animal life bent its
  3874. course, two have led to blind alleys, and, in the other two, the effort
  3875. has generally been out of proportion to the result.
  3876. Documents are lacking to reconstruct this history in detail, but we can
  3877. make out its main lines. We have already said that animals and
  3878. vegetables must have separated soon from their common stock, the
  3879. vegetable falling asleep in immobility, the animal, on the contrary,
  3880. becoming more and more awake and marching on to the conquest of a
  3881. nervous system. Probably the effort of the animal kingdom resulted in
  3882. creating organisms still very simple, but endowed with a certain freedom
  3883. of action, and, above all, with a shape so undecided that it could lend
  3884. itself to any future determination. These animals may have resembled
  3885. some of our worms, but with this difference, however, that the worms
  3886. living to-day, to which they could be compared, are but the empty and
  3887. fixed examples of infinitely plastic forms, pregnant with an unlimited
  3888. future, the common stock of the echinoderms, molluscs, arthropods, and
  3889. vertebrates.
  3890. One danger lay in wait for them, one obstacle which might have stopped
  3891. the soaring course of animal life. There is one peculiarity with which
  3892. we cannot help being struck when glancing over the fauna of primitive
  3893. times, namely, the imprisonment of the animal in a more or less solid
  3894. sheath, which must have obstructed and often even paralyzed its
  3895. movements. The molluscs of that time had a shell more universally than
  3896. those of to-day. The arthropods in general were provided with a
  3897. carapace; most of them were crustaceans. The more ancient fishes had a
  3898. bony sheath of extreme hardness.[59] The explanation of this general
  3899. fact should be sought, we believe, in a tendency of soft organisms to
  3900. defend themselves against one another by making themselves, as far as
  3901. possible, undevourable. Each species, in the act by which it comes into
  3902. being, trends towards that which is most expedient. Just as among
  3903. primitive organisms there were some that turned towards animal life by
  3904. refusing to manufacture organic out of inorganic material and taking
  3905. organic substances ready made from organisms that had turned toward the
  3906. vegetative life, so, among the animal species themselves, many contrived
  3907. to live at the expense of other animals. For an organism that is animal,
  3908. that is to say mobile, can avail itself of its mobility to go in search
  3909. of defenseless animals, and feed on them quite as well as on vegetables.
  3910. So, the more species became mobile, the more they became voracious and
  3911. dangerous to one another. Hence a sudden arrest of the entire animal
  3912. world in its progress towards higher and higher mobility; for the hard
  3913. and calcareous skin of the echinoderm, the shell of the mollusc, the
  3914. carapace of the crustacean and the ganoid breast-plate of the ancient
  3915. fishes probably all originated in a common effort of the animal species
  3916. to protect themselves against hostile species. But this breast-plate,
  3917. behind which the animal took shelter, constrained it in its movements
  3918. and sometimes fixed it in one place. If the vegetable renounced
  3919. consciousness in wrapping itself in a cellulose membrane, the animal
  3920. that shut itself up in a citadel or in armor condemned itself to a
  3921. partial slumber. In this torpor the echinoderms and even the molluscs
  3922. live to-day. Probably arthropods and vertebrates were threatened with it
  3923. too. They escaped, however, and to this fortunate circumstance is due
  3924. the expansion of the highest forms of life.
  3925. In two directions, in fact, we see the impulse of life to movement
  3926. getting the upper hand again. The fishes exchanged their ganoid
  3927. breast-plate for scales. Long before that, the insects had appeared,
  3928. also disencumbered of the breast-plate that had protected their
  3929. ancestors. Both supplemented the insufficiency of their protective
  3930. covering by an agility that enabled them to escape their enemies, and
  3931. also to assume the offensive, to choose the place and the moment of
  3932. encounter. We see a progress of the same kind in the evolution of human
  3933. armaments. The first impulse is to seek shelter; the second, which is
  3934. the better, is to become as supple as possible for flight and above all
  3935. for attack--attack being the most effective means of defense. So the
  3936. heavy hoplite was supplanted by the legionary; the knight, clad in
  3937. armor, had to give place to the light free-moving infantryman; and in a
  3938. general way, in the evolution of life, just as in the evolution of human
  3939. societies and of individual destinies, the greatest successes have been
  3940. for those who have accepted the heaviest risks.
  3941. Evidently, then, it was to the animal's interest to make itself more
  3942. mobile. As we said when speaking of adaptation in general, any
  3943. transformation of a species can be explained by its own particular
  3944. interest. This will give the immediate cause of the variation, but often
  3945. only the most superficial cause. The profound cause is the impulse which
  3946. thrust life into the world, which made it divide into vegetables and
  3947. animals, which shunted the animal on to suppleness of form, and which,
  3948. at a certain moment, in the animal kingdom threatened with torpor,
  3949. secured that, on some points at least, it should rouse itself up and
  3950. move forward.
  3951. On the two paths along which the vertebrates and arthropods have
  3952. separately evolved, development (apart from retrogressions connected
  3953. with parasitism or any other cause) has consisted above all in the
  3954. progress of the sensori-motor nervous system. Mobility and suppleness
  3955. were sought for, and also--through many experimental attempts, and not
  3956. without a tendency to excess of substance and brute force at the
  3957. start--variety of movements. But this quest itself took place in
  3958. divergent directions. A glance at the nervous system of the arthropods
  3959. and that of the vertebrates shows us the difference. In the arthropods,
  3960. the body is formed of a series more or less long of rings set together;
  3961. motor activity is thus distributed amongst a varying--sometimes a
  3962. considerable--number of appendages, each of which has its special
  3963. function. In the vertebrates, activity is concentrated in two pairs of
  3964. members only, and these organs perform functions which depend much less
  3965. strictly on their form.[60] The independence becomes complete in man,
  3966. whose hand is capable of any kind of work.
  3967. That, at least, is what we see. But behind what is seen there is what
  3968. may be surmised--two powers, immanent in life and originally
  3969. intermingled, which were bound to part company in course of growth.
  3970. To define these powers, we must consider, in the evolution both of the
  3971. arthropods and the vertebrates, the species which mark the culminating
  3972. point of each. How is this point to be determined? Here again, to aim at
  3973. geometrical precision will lead us astray. There is no single simple
  3974. sign by which we can recognize that one species is more advanced than
  3975. another on the same line of evolution. There are manifold characters,
  3976. that must be compared and weighed in each particular case, in order to
  3977. ascertain to what extent they are essential or accidental and how far
  3978. they must be taken into account.
  3979. It is unquestionable, for example, that _success_ is the most general
  3980. criterion of superiority, the two terms being, up to a certain point,
  3981. synonymous. By success must be understood, so far as the living being is
  3982. concerned, an aptitude to develop in the most diverse environments,
  3983. through the greatest possible variety of obstacles, so as to cover the
  3984. widest possible extent of ground. A species which claims the entire
  3985. earth for its domain is truly a dominating and consequently superior
  3986. species. Such is the human species, which represents the culminating
  3987. point of the evolution of the vertebrates. But such also are, in the
  3988. series of the articulate, the insects and in particular certain
  3989. hymenoptera. It has been said of the ants that, as man is lord of the
  3990. soil, they are lords of the sub-soil.
  3991. On the other hand, a group of species that has appeared late may be a
  3992. group of degenerates; but, for that, some special cause of retrogression
  3993. must have intervened. By right, this group should be superior to the
  3994. group from which it is derived, since it would correspond to a more
  3995. advanced stage of evolution. Now man is probably the latest comer of the
  3996. vertebrates;[61] and in the insect series no species is later than the
  3997. hymenoptera, unless it be the lepidoptera, which are probably
  3998. degenerates, living parasitically on flowering plants.
  3999. So, by different ways, we are led to the same conclusion. The evolution
  4000. of the arthropods reaches its culminating point in the insect, and in
  4001. particular in the hymenoptera, as that of the vertebrates in man. Now,
  4002. since instinct is nowhere so developed as in the insect world, and in no
  4003. group of insects so marvelously as in the hymenoptera, it may be said
  4004. that the whole evolution of the animal kingdom, apart from
  4005. retrogressions towards vegetative life, has taken place on two divergent
  4006. paths, one of which led to instinct and the other to intelligence.
  4007. Vegetative torpor, instinct, and intelligence--these, then, are the
  4008. elements that coincided in the vital impulsion common to plants and
  4009. animals, and which, in the course of a development in which they were
  4010. made manifest in the most unforeseen forms, have been dissociated by the
  4011. very fact of their growth. _The cardinal error which, from Aristotle
  4012. onwards, has vitiated most of the philosophies of nature, is to see in
  4013. vegetative, instinctive and rational life, three successive degrees of
  4014. the development of one and the same tendency, whereas they are three
  4015. divergent directions of an activity that has split up as it grew._ The
  4016. difference between them is not a difference of intensity, nor, more
  4017. generally, of degree, but of kind.
  4018. * * * * *
  4019. It is important to investigate this point. We have seen in the case of
  4020. vegetable and animal life how they are at once mutually complementary
  4021. and mutually antagonistic. Now we must show that intelligence and
  4022. instinct also are opposite and complementary. But let us first explain
  4023. why we are generally led to regard them as activities of which one is
  4024. superior to the other and based upon it, whereas in reality they are not
  4025. things of the same order: they have not succeeded one another, nor can
  4026. we assign to them different grades.
  4027. It is because intelligence and instinct, having originally been
  4028. interpenetrating, retain something of their common origin. Neither is
  4029. ever found in a pure state. We said that in the plant the consciousness
  4030. and mobility of the animal, which lie dormant, can be awakened; and that
  4031. the animal lives under the constant menace of being drawn aside to the
  4032. vegetative life. The two tendencies--that of the plant and that of the
  4033. animal--were so thoroughly interpenetrating, to begin with, that there
  4034. has never been a complete severance between them: they haunt each other
  4035. continually; everywhere we find them mingled; it is the proportion that
  4036. differs. So with intelligence and instinct. There is no intelligence in
  4037. which some traces of instinct are not to be discovered, more especially
  4038. no instinct that is not surrounded with a fringe of intelligence. It is
  4039. this fringe of intelligence that has been the cause of so many
  4040. misunderstandings. From the fact that instinct is always more or less
  4041. intelligent, it has been concluded that instinct and intelligence are
  4042. things of the same kind, that there is only a difference of complexity
  4043. or perfection between them, and, above all, that one of the two is
  4044. expressible in terms of the other. In reality, they accompany each other
  4045. only because they are complementary, and they are complementary only
  4046. because they are different, what is instinctive in instinct being
  4047. opposite to what is intelligent in intelligence.
  4048. We are bound to dwell on this point. It is one of the utmost importance.
  4049. Let us say at the outset that the distinctions we are going to make will
  4050. be too sharply drawn, just because we wish to define in instinct what is
  4051. instinctive, and in intelligence what is intelligent, whereas all
  4052. concrete instinct is mingled with intelligence, as all real intelligence
  4053. is penetrated by instinct. Moreover, neither intelligence nor instinct
  4054. lends itself to rigid definition: they are tendencies, and not things.
  4055. Also, it must not be forgotten that in the present chapter we are
  4056. considering intelligence and instinct as going out of life which
  4057. deposits them along its course. Now the life manifested by an organism
  4058. is, in our view, a certain effort to obtain certain things from the
  4059. material world. No wonder, therefore, if it is the diversity of this
  4060. effort that strikes us in instinct and intelligence, and if we see in
  4061. these two modes of psychical activity, above all else, two different
  4062. methods of action on inert matter. This rather narrow view of them has
  4063. the advantage of giving us an objective means of distinguishing them. In
  4064. return, however, it gives us, of intelligence in general and of instinct
  4065. in general, only the mean position above and below which both constantly
  4066. oscillate. For that reason the reader must expect to see in what follows
  4067. only a diagrammatic drawing, in which the respective outlines of
  4068. intelligence and instinct are sharper than they should be, and in which
  4069. the shading-off which comes from the indecision of each and from their
  4070. reciprocal encroachment on one another is neglected. In a matter so
  4071. obscure, we cannot strive too hard for clearness. It will always be easy
  4072. afterwards to soften the outlines and to correct what is too geometrical
  4073. in the drawing--in short, to replace the rigidity of a diagram by the
  4074. suppleness of life.
  4075. * * * * *
  4076. To what date is it agreed to ascribe the appearance of man on the earth?
  4077. To the period when the first weapons, the first tools, were made. The
  4078. memorable quarrel over the discovery of Boucher de Perthes in the quarry
  4079. of Moulin-Quignon is not forgotten. The question was whether real
  4080. hatchets had been found or merely bits of flint accidentally broken. But
  4081. that, supposing they were hatchets, we were indeed in the presence of
  4082. intelligence, and more particularly of _human_ intelligence, no one
  4083. doubted for an instant. Now let us open a collection of anecdotes on the
  4084. intelligence of animals: we shall see that besides many acts explicable
  4085. by imitation or by the automatic association of images, there are some
  4086. that we do not hesitate to call intelligent: foremost among them are
  4087. those that bear witness to some idea of manufacture, whether the animal
  4088. life succeeds in fashioning a crude instrument or uses for its profit an
  4089. object made by man. The animals that rank immediately after man in the
  4090. matter of intelligence, the apes and elephants, are those that can use
  4091. an artificial instrument occasionally. Below, but not very far from
  4092. them, come those that _recognize_ a constructed object: for example, the
  4093. fox, which knows quite well that a trap is a trap. No doubt, there is
  4094. intelligence wherever there is inference; but inference, which consists
  4095. in an inflection of past experience in the direction of present
  4096. experience, is already a beginning of invention. Invention becomes
  4097. complete when it is materialized in a manufactured instrument. Towards
  4098. that achievement the intelligence of animals tends as towards an ideal.
  4099. And though, ordinarily, it does not yet succeed in fashioning artificial
  4100. objects and in making use of them, it is preparing for this by the very
  4101. variations which it performs on the instincts furnished by nature. As
  4102. regards human intelligence, it has not been sufficiently noted that
  4103. mechanical invention has been from the first its essential feature, that
  4104. even to-day our social life gravitates around the manufacture and use of
  4105. artificial instruments, that the inventions which strew the road of
  4106. progress have also traced its direction. This we hardly realize, because
  4107. it takes us longer to change ourselves than to change our tools. Our
  4108. individual and even social habits survive a good while the circumstances
  4109. for which they were made, so that the ultimate effects of an invention
  4110. are not observed until its novelty is already out of sight. A century
  4111. has elapsed since the invention of the steam-engine, and we are only
  4112. just beginning to feel the depths of the shock it gave us. But the
  4113. revolution it has effected in industry has nevertheless upset human
  4114. relations altogether. New ideas are arising, new feelings are on the way
  4115. to flower. In thousands of years, when, seen from the distance, only the
  4116. broad lines of the present age will still be visible, our wars and our
  4117. revolutions will count for little, even supposing they are remembered
  4118. at all; but the steam-engine, and the procession of inventions of every
  4119. kind that accompanied it, will perhaps be spoken of as we speak of the
  4120. bronze or of the chipped stone of prehistoric times: it will serve to
  4121. define an age.[62] If we could rid ourselves of all pride, if, to define
  4122. our species, we kept strictly to what the historic and the prehistoric
  4123. periods show us to be the constant characteristic of man and of
  4124. intelligence, we should say not _Homo sapiens_, but _Homo faber_. In
  4125. short, _intelligence, considered in what seems to be its original
  4126. feature, is the faculty of manufacturing artificial objects, especially
  4127. tools to make tools, and of indefinitely varying the manufacture_.
  4128. Now, does an unintelligent animal also possess tools or machines? Yes,
  4129. certainly, but here the instrument forms a part of the body that uses
  4130. it; and, corresponding to this instrument, there is an _instinct_ that
  4131. knows how to use it. True, it cannot be maintained that _all_ instincts
  4132. consist in a natural ability to use an inborn mechanism. Such a
  4133. definition would not apply to the instincts which Romanes called
  4134. "secondary"; and more than one "primary" instinct would not come under
  4135. it. But this definition, like that which we have provisionally given of
  4136. intelligence, determines at least the ideal limit toward which the very
  4137. numerous forms of instinct are traveling. Indeed, it has often been
  4138. pointed out that most instincts are only the continuance, or rather the
  4139. consummation, of the work of organization itself. Where does the
  4140. activity of instinct begin? and where does that of nature end? We cannot
  4141. tell. In the metamorphoses of the larva into the nymph and into the
  4142. perfect insect, metamorphoses that often require appropriate action and
  4143. a kind of initiative on the part of the larva, there is no sharp line of
  4144. demarcation between the instinct of the animal and the organizing work
  4145. of living matter. We may say, as we will, either that instinct organizes
  4146. the instruments it is about to use, or that the process of organization
  4147. is continued in the instinct that has to use the organ. The most
  4148. marvelous instincts of the insect do nothing but develop its special
  4149. structure into movements: indeed, where social life divides the labor
  4150. among different individuals, and thus allots them different instincts, a
  4151. corresponding difference of structure is observed: the polymorphism of
  4152. ants, bees, wasps and certain pseudoneuroptera is well known. Thus, if
  4153. we consider only those typical cases in which the complete triumph of
  4154. intelligence and of instinct is seen, we find this essential difference
  4155. between them: _instinct perfected is a faculty of using and even of
  4156. constructing organized instruments; intelligence perfected is the
  4157. faculty of making and using unorganized instruments_.
  4158. The advantages and drawbacks of these two modes of activity are obvious.
  4159. Instinct finds the appropriate instrument at hand: this instrument,
  4160. which makes and repairs itself, which presents, like all the works of
  4161. nature, an infinite complexity of detail combined with a marvelous
  4162. simplicity of function, does at once, when required, what it is called
  4163. upon to do, without difficulty and with a perfection that is often
  4164. wonderful. In return, it retains an almost invariable structure, since a
  4165. modification of it involves a modification of the species. Instinct is
  4166. therefore necessarily specialized, being nothing but the utilization of
  4167. a specific instrument for a specific object. The instrument constructed
  4168. intelligently, on the contrary, is an imperfect instrument. It costs an
  4169. effort. It is generally troublesome to handle. But, as it is made of
  4170. unorganized matter, it can take any form whatsoever, serve any purpose,
  4171. free the living being from every new difficulty that arises and bestow
  4172. on it an unlimited number of powers. Whilst it is inferior to the
  4173. natural instrument for the satisfaction of immediate wants, its
  4174. advantage over it is the greater, the less urgent the need. Above all,
  4175. it reacts on the nature of the being that constructs it; for in calling
  4176. on him to exercise a new function, it confers on him, so to speak, a
  4177. richer organization, being an artificial organ by which the natural
  4178. organism is extended. For every need that it satisfies, it creates a new
  4179. need; and so, instead of closing, like instinct, the round of action
  4180. within which the animal tends to move automatically, it lays open to
  4181. activity an unlimited field into which it is driven further and further,
  4182. and made more and more free. But this advantage of intelligence over
  4183. instinct only appears at a late stage, when intelligence, having raised
  4184. construction to a higher degree, proceeds to construct constructive
  4185. machinery. At the outset, the advantages and drawbacks of the artificial
  4186. instrument and of the natural instrument balance so well that it is hard
  4187. to foretell which of the two will secure to the living being the greater
  4188. empire over nature.
  4189. We may surmise that they began by being implied in each other, that the
  4190. original psychical activity included both at once, and that, if we went
  4191. far enough back into the past, we should find instincts more nearly
  4192. approaching intelligence than those of our insects, intelligence nearer
  4193. to instinct than that of our vertebrates, intelligence and instinct
  4194. being, in this elementary condition, prisoners of a matter which they
  4195. are not yet able to control. If the force immanent in life were an
  4196. unlimited force, it might perhaps have developed instinct and
  4197. intelligence together, and to any extent, in the same organisms. But
  4198. everything seems to indicate that this force is limited, and that it
  4199. soon exhausts itself in its very manifestation. It is hard for it to go
  4200. far in several directions at once: it must choose. Now, it has the
  4201. choice between two modes of acting on the material world: it can either
  4202. effect this action _directly_ by creating an _organized_ instrument to
  4203. work with; or else it can effect it _indirectly_ through an organism
  4204. which, instead of possessing the required instrument naturally, will
  4205. itself construct it by fashioning inorganic matter. Hence intelligence
  4206. and instinct, which diverge more and more as they develop, but which
  4207. never entirely separate from each other. On the one hand, the most
  4208. perfect instinct of the insect is accompanied by gleams of intelligence,
  4209. if only in the choice of place, time and materials of construction: the
  4210. bees, for example, when by exception they build in the open air, invent
  4211. new and really intelligent arrangements to adapt themselves to such new
  4212. conditions.[63] But, on the other hand, intelligence has even more need
  4213. of instinct than instinct has of intelligence; for the power to give
  4214. shape to crude matter involves already a superior degree of
  4215. organization, a degree to which the animal could not have risen, save on
  4216. the wings of instinct. So, while nature has frankly evolved in the
  4217. direction of instinct in the arthropods, we observe in almost all the
  4218. vertebrates the striving after rather than the expansion of
  4219. intelligence. It is instinct still which forms the basis of their
  4220. psychical activity; but intelligence is there, and would fain supersede
  4221. it. Intelligence does not yet succeed in inventing instruments; but at
  4222. least it tries to, by performing as many variations as possible on the
  4223. instinct which it would like to dispense with. It gains complete
  4224. self-possession only in man, and this triumph is attested by the very
  4225. insufficiency of the natural means at man's disposal for defense against
  4226. his enemies, against cold and hunger. This insufficiency, when we strive
  4227. to fathom its significance, acquires the value of a prehistoric
  4228. document; it is the final leave-taking between intelligence and
  4229. instinct. But it is no less true that nature must have hesitated between
  4230. two modes of psychical activity--one assured of immediate success, but
  4231. limited in its effects; the other hazardous, but whose conquests, if it
  4232. should reach independence, might be extended indefinitely. Here again,
  4233. then, the greatest success was achieved on the side of the greatest
  4234. risk. _Instinct and intelligence therefore represent two divergent
  4235. solutions, equally fitting, of one and the same problem._
  4236. There ensue, it is true, profound differences of internal structure
  4237. between instinct and intelligence. We shall dwell only on those that
  4238. concern our present study. Let us say, then, that instinct and
  4239. intelligence imply two radically different kinds of knowledge. But some
  4240. explanations are first of all necessary on the subject of consciousness
  4241. in general.
  4242. It has been asked how far instinct is conscious. Our reply is that there
  4243. are a vast number of differences and degrees, that instinct is more or
  4244. less conscious in certain cases, unconscious in others. The plant, as we
  4245. shall see, has instincts; it is not likely that these are accompanied by
  4246. feeling. Even in the animal there is hardly any complex instinct that is
  4247. not unconscious in some part at least of its exercise. But here we must
  4248. point out a difference, not often noticed, between two kinds of
  4249. unconsciousness, viz., that in which consciousness is _absent_, and that
  4250. in which consciousness is _nullified_. Both are equal to zero, but in
  4251. one case the zero expresses the fact that there is nothing, in the other
  4252. that we have two equal quantities of opposite sign which compensate and
  4253. neutralize each other. The unconsciousness of a falling stone is of the
  4254. former kind: the stone has no feeling of its fall. Is it the same with
  4255. the unconsciousness of instinct, in the extreme cases in which instinct
  4256. is unconscious? When we mechanically perform an habitual action, when
  4257. the somnambulist automatically acts his dream, unconsciousness may be
  4258. absolute; but this is merely due to the fact that the representation of
  4259. the act is held in check by the performance of the act itself, which
  4260. resembles the idea so perfectly, and fits it so exactly, that
  4261. consciousness is unable to find room between them. _Representation is
  4262. stopped up by action._ The proof of this is, that if the accomplishment
  4263. of the act is arrested or thwarted by an obstacle, consciousness may
  4264. reappear. It was there, but neutralized by the action which fulfilled
  4265. and thereby filled the representation. The obstacle creates nothing
  4266. positive; it simply makes a void, removes a stopper. This inadequacy of
  4267. act to representation is precisely what we here call consciousness.
  4268. If we examine this point more closely, we shall find that consciousness
  4269. is the light that plays around the zone of possible actions or potential
  4270. activity which surrounds the action really performed by the living
  4271. being. It signifies hesitation or choice. Where many equally possible
  4272. actions are indicated without there being any real action (as in a
  4273. deliberation that has not come to an end), consciousness is intense.
  4274. Where the action performed is the only action possible (as in activity
  4275. of the somnambulistic or more generally automatic kind), consciousness
  4276. is reduced to nothing. Representation and knowledge exist none the less
  4277. in the case if we find a whole series of systematized movements the last
  4278. of which is already pre-figured in the first, and if, besides,
  4279. consciousness can flash out of them at the shock of an obstacle. From
  4280. this point of view, _the consciousness of a living being may be defined
  4281. as an arithmetical difference between potential and real activity_. _It
  4282. measures the interval between representation and action._
  4283. It may be inferred from this that intelligence is likely to point
  4284. towards consciousness, and instinct towards unconsciousness. For, where
  4285. the implement to be used is organized by nature, the material furnished
  4286. by nature, and the result to be obtained willed by nature, there is
  4287. little left to choice; the consciousness inherent in the representation
  4288. is therefore counterbalanced, whenever it tends to disengage itself, by
  4289. the performance of the act, identical with the representation, which
  4290. forms its counterweight. Where consciousness appears, it does not so
  4291. much light up the instinct itself as the thwartings to which instinct is
  4292. subject; it is the _deficit_ of instinct, the distance, between the act
  4293. and the idea, that becomes consciousness so that consciousness, here, is
  4294. only an accident. Essentially, consciousness only emphasizes the
  4295. starting-point of instinct, the point at which the whole series of
  4296. automatic movements is released. Deficit, on the contrary, is the normal
  4297. state of intelligence. Laboring under difficulties is its very essence.
  4298. Its original function being to construct unorganized instruments, it
  4299. must, in spite of numberless difficulties, choose for this work the
  4300. place and the time, the form and the matter. And it can never satisfy
  4301. itself entirely, because every new satisfaction creates new needs. In
  4302. short, while instinct and intelligence both involve knowledge, this
  4303. knowledge is rather _acted_ and unconscious in the case of instinct,
  4304. _thought_ and conscious in the case of intelligence. But it is a
  4305. difference rather of degree than of kind. So long as consciousness is
  4306. all we are concerned with, we close our eyes to what is, from the
  4307. psychological point of view, the cardinal difference between instinct
  4308. and intelligence.
  4309. In order to get at this essential difference we must, without stopping
  4310. at the more or less brilliant light which illumines these two modes of
  4311. internal activity, go straight to the two _objects_, profoundly
  4312. different from each other, upon which instinct and intelligence are
  4313. directed.
  4314. When the horse-fly lays its eggs on the legs or shoulders of the horse,
  4315. it acts as if it knew that its larva has to develop in the horse's
  4316. stomach and that the horse, in licking itself, will convey the larva
  4317. into its digestive tract. When a paralyzing wasp stings its victim on
  4318. just those points where the nervous centres lie, so as to render it
  4319. motionless without killing it, it acts like a learned entomologist and a
  4320. skilful surgeon rolled into one. But what shall we say of the little
  4321. beetle, the Sitaris, whose story is so often quoted? This insect lays
  4322. its eggs at the entrance of the underground passages dug by a kind of
  4323. bee, the Anthophora. Its larva, after long waiting, springs upon the
  4324. male Anthophora as it goes out of the passage, clings to it, and remains
  4325. attached until the "nuptial flight," when it seizes the opportunity to
  4326. pass from the male to the female, and quietly waits until it lays its
  4327. eggs. It then leaps on the egg, which serves as a support for it in the
  4328. honey, devours the egg in a few days, and, resting on the shell,
  4329. undergoes its first metamorphosis. Organized now to float on the honey,
  4330. it consumes this provision of nourishment, and becomes a nymph, then a
  4331. perfect insect. Everything happens _as if_ the larva of the Sitaris,
  4332. from the moment it was hatched, knew that the male Anthophora would
  4333. first emerge from the passage; that the nuptial flight would give it the
  4334. means of conveying itself to the female, who would take it to a store of
  4335. honey sufficient to feed it after its transformation; that, until this
  4336. transformation, it could gradually eat the egg of the Anthophora, in
  4337. such a way that it could at the same time feed itself, maintain itself
  4338. at the surface of the honey, and also suppress the rival that otherwise
  4339. would have come out of the egg. And equally all this happens _as if_ the
  4340. Sitaris itself knew that its larva would know all these things. The
  4341. knowledge, if knowledge there be, is only implicit. It is reflected
  4342. outwardly in exact movements instead of being reflected inwardly in
  4343. consciousness. It is none the less true that the behavior of the insect
  4344. involves, or rather evolves, the idea of definite things existing or
  4345. being produced in definite points of space and time, which the insect
  4346. knows without having learned them.
  4347. Now, if we look at intelligence from the same point of view, we find
  4348. that it also knows certain things without having learned them. But the
  4349. knowledge in the two cases is of a very different order. We must be
  4350. careful here not to revive again the old philosophical dispute on the
  4351. subject of innate ideas. So we will confine ourselves to the point on
  4352. which every one is agreed, to wit, that the young child understands
  4353. immediately things that the animal will never understand, and that in
  4354. this sense intelligence, like instinct, is an inherited function,
  4355. therefore an innate one. But this innate intelligence, although it is a
  4356. faculty of knowing, knows no object in particular. When the new-born
  4357. babe seeks for the first time its mother's breast, so showing that it
  4358. has knowledge (unconscious, no doubt) of a thing it has never seen, we
  4359. say, just because the innate knowledge is in this case of a definite
  4360. object, that it belongs to _instinct_ and not to _intelligence_.
  4361. Intelligence does not then imply the innate knowledge of any object. And
  4362. yet, if intelligence knows nothing by nature, it has nothing innate.
  4363. What, then, if it be ignorant of all things, can it know? Besides
  4364. _things_, there are _relations_. The new-born child, so far as
  4365. intelligent, knows neither definite objects nor a definite property of
  4366. any object; but when, a little later on, he will hear an epithet being
  4367. applied to a substantive, he will immediately understand what it means.
  4368. The relation of attribute to subject is therefore seized by him
  4369. naturally, and the same might be said of the general relation expressed
  4370. by the verb, a relation so immediately conceived by the mind that
  4371. language can leave it to be understood, as is instanced in rudimentary
  4372. languages which have no verb. Intelligence, therefore, naturally makes
  4373. use of relations of like with like, of content to container, of cause to
  4374. effect, etc., which are implied in every phrase in which there is a
  4375. subject, an attribute and a verb, expressed or understood. May one say
  4376. that it has _innate_ knowledge of each of these relations in particular?
  4377. It is for logicians to discover whether they are so many irreducible
  4378. relations, or whether they can be resolved into relations still more
  4379. general. But, in whatever way we make the analysis of thought, we always
  4380. end with one or several general categories, of which the mind possesses
  4381. innate knowledge since it makes a natural use of them. Let us say,
  4382. therefore, that _whatever, in instinct and intelligence, is innate
  4383. knowledge, bears in the first case on_ things _and in the second on_
  4384. relations.
  4385. Philosophers distinguish between the matter of our knowledge and its
  4386. form. The matter is what is given by the perceptive faculties taken in
  4387. the elementary state. The form is the totality of the relations set up
  4388. between these materials in order to constitute a systematic knowledge.
  4389. Can the form, without matter, be an object of knowledge? Yes, without
  4390. doubt, provided that this knowledge is not like a thing we possess so
  4391. much as like a habit we have contracted,--a direction rather than a
  4392. state: it is, if we will, a certain natural bent of attention. The
  4393. schoolboy, who knows that the master is going to dictate a fraction to
  4394. him, draws a line before he knows what numerator and what denominator
  4395. are to come; he therefore has present to his mind the general relation
  4396. between the two terms although he does not know either of them; he knows
  4397. the form without the matter. So is it, prior to experience, with the
  4398. categories into which our experience comes to be inserted. Let us adopt
  4399. then words sanctioned by usage, and give the distinction between
  4400. intelligence and instinct this more precise formula: _Intelligence, in
  4401. so far as it is innate, is the knowledge of a_ form; _instinct implies
  4402. the knowledge of a_ matter.
  4403. From this second point of view, which is that of knowledge instead of
  4404. action, the force immanent in life in general appears to us again as a
  4405. limited principle, in which originally two different and even divergent
  4406. modes of knowing coexisted and intermingled. The first gets at definite
  4407. objects immediately, in their materiality itself. It says, "This is what
  4408. is." The second gets at no object in particular; it is only a natural
  4409. power of relating an object to an object, or a part to a part, or an
  4410. aspect to an aspect--in short, of drawing conclusions when in possession
  4411. of the premisses, of proceeding from what has been learnt to what is
  4412. still unknown. It does not say, "This _is_;" it says only that "_if_ the
  4413. conditions are such, such will be the conditioned." In short, the first
  4414. kind of knowledge, the instinctive, would be formulated in what
  4415. philosophers call _categorical_ propositions, while the second kind, the
  4416. intellectual, would always be expressed _hypothetically_. Of these two
  4417. faculties, the former seems, at first, much preferable to the other. And
  4418. it would be so, in truth, if it extended to an endless number of
  4419. objects. But, in fact, it applies only to one special object, and indeed
  4420. only to a restricted part of that object. Of this, at least, its
  4421. knowledge is intimate and full; not explicit, but implied in the
  4422. accomplished action. The intellectual faculty, on the contrary,
  4423. possesses naturally only an external and empty knowledge; but it has
  4424. thereby the advantage of supplying a frame in which an infinity of
  4425. objects may find room in turn. It is as if the force evolving in living
  4426. forms, being a limited force, had had to choose between two kinds of
  4427. limitation in the field of natural or innate knowledge, one applying to
  4428. the _extension_ of knowledge, the other to its _intension_. In the first
  4429. case, the knowledge may be packed and full, but it will then be confined
  4430. to one specific object; in the second, it is no longer limited by its
  4431. object, but that is because it contains nothing, being only a form
  4432. without matter. The two tendencies, at first implied in each other, had
  4433. to separate in order to grow. They both went to seek their fortune in
  4434. the world, and turned out to be instinct and intelligence.
  4435. Such, then, are the two divergent modes of knowledge by which
  4436. intelligence and instinct must be defined, from the standpoint of
  4437. knowledge rather than that of action. But knowledge and action are here
  4438. only two aspects of one and the same faculty. It is easy to see, indeed,
  4439. that the second definition is only a new form of the first.
  4440. If instinct is, above all, the faculty of using an organized natural
  4441. instrument, it must involve innate knowledge (potential or unconscious,
  4442. it is true), both of this instrument and of the object to which it is
  4443. applied. Instinct is therefore innate knowledge of a _thing_. But
  4444. intelligence is the faculty of constructing unorganized--that is to say
  4445. artificial--instruments. If, on its account, nature gives up endowing
  4446. the living being with the instruments that may serve him, it is in order
  4447. that the living being may be able to vary his construction according to
  4448. circumstances. The essential function of intelligence is therefore to
  4449. see the way out of a difficulty in any circumstances whatever, to find
  4450. what is most suitable, what answers best the question asked. Hence it
  4451. bears essentially on the relations between a given situation and the
  4452. means of utilizing it. What is innate in intellect, therefore, is the
  4453. tendency to establish relations, and this tendency implies the natural
  4454. knowledge of certain very general relations, a kind of stuff that the
  4455. activity of each particular intellect will cut up into more special
  4456. relations. Where activity is directed toward manufacture, therefore,
  4457. knowledge necessarily bears on relations. But this entirely _formal_
  4458. knowledge of intelligence has an immense advantage over the _material_
  4459. knowledge of instinct. A form, just because it is empty, may be filled
  4460. at will with any number of things in turn, even with those that are of
  4461. no use. So that a formal knowledge is not limited to what is practically
  4462. useful, although it is in view of practical utility that it has made its
  4463. appearance in the world. An intelligent being bears within himself the
  4464. means to transcend his own nature.
  4465. He transcends himself, however, less than he wishes, less also than he
  4466. imagines himself to do. The purely formal character of intelligence
  4467. deprives it of the ballast necessary to enable it to settle itself on
  4468. the objects that are of the most powerful interest to speculation.
  4469. Instinct, on the contrary, has the desired materiality, but it is
  4470. incapable of going so far in quest of its object; it does not speculate.
  4471. Here we reach the point that most concerns our present inquiry. The
  4472. difference that we shall now proceed to denote between instinct and
  4473. intelligence is what the whole of this analysis was meant to bring out.
  4474. We formulate it thus: _There are things that intelligence alone is able
  4475. to seek, but which, by itself, it will never find. These things instinct
  4476. alone could find; but it will never seek them._
  4477. It is necessary here to consider some preliminary details that concern
  4478. the mechanism of intelligence. We have said that the function of
  4479. intelligence is to establish relations. Let us determine more precisely
  4480. the nature of these relations. On this point we are bound to be either
  4481. vague or arbitrary so long as we see in the intellect a faculty intended
  4482. for pure speculation. We are then reduced to taking the general frames
  4483. of the understanding for something absolute, irreducible and
  4484. inexplicable. The understanding must have fallen from heaven with its
  4485. form, as each of us is born with his face. This form may be defined, of
  4486. course, but that is all; there is no asking why it is what it is rather
  4487. than anything else. Thus, it will be said that the function of the
  4488. intellect is essentially unification, that the common object of all its
  4489. operations is to introduce a certain unity into the diversity of
  4490. phenomena, and so forth. But, in the first place, "unification" is a
  4491. vague term, less clear than "relation" or even "thought," and says
  4492. nothing more. And, moreover, it might be asked if the function of
  4493. intelligence is not to divide even more than to unite. Finally, if the
  4494. intellect proceeds as it does because it wishes to unite, and if it
  4495. seeks unification simply because it has need of unifying, the whole of
  4496. our knowledge becomes relative to certain requirements of the mind that
  4497. probably might have been entirely different from what they are: for an
  4498. intellect differently shaped, knowledge would have been different.
  4499. Intellect being no longer dependent on anything, everything becomes
  4500. dependent on it; and so, having placed the understanding too high, we
  4501. end by putting too low the knowledge it gives us. Knowledge becomes
  4502. relative, as soon as the intellect is made a kind of absolute.--We
  4503. regard the human intellect, on the contrary, as relative to the needs of
  4504. action. Postulate action, and the very form of the intellect can be
  4505. deduced from it. This form is therefore neither irreducible nor
  4506. inexplicable. And, precisely because it is not independent, knowledge
  4507. cannot be said to depend on it: knowledge ceases to be a product of the
  4508. intellect and becomes, in a certain sense, part and parcel of reality.
  4509. Philosophers will reply that action takes place in an _ordered_ world,
  4510. that this order is itself thought, and that we beg the question when we
  4511. explain the intellect by action, which presupposes it. They would be
  4512. right if our point of view in the present chapter was to be our final
  4513. one. We should then be dupes of an illusion like that of Spencer, who
  4514. believed that the intellect is sufficiently explained as the impression
  4515. left on us by the general characters of matter: as if the order inherent
  4516. in matter were not intelligence itself! But we reserve for the next
  4517. chapter the question up to what point and with what method philosophy
  4518. can attempt a real genesis of the intellect at the same time as of
  4519. matter. For the moment, the problem that engages our attention is of a
  4520. psychological order. We are asking what is the portion of the material
  4521. world to which our intellect is specially adapted. To reply to this
  4522. question, there is no need to choose a system of philosophy: it is
  4523. enough to take up the point of view of common sense.
  4524. Let us start, then, from action, and lay down that the intellect aims,
  4525. first of all, at constructing. This fabrication is exercised exclusively
  4526. on inert matter, in this sense, that even if it makes use of organized
  4527. material, it treats it as inert, without troubling about the life which
  4528. animated it. And of inert matter itself, fabrication deals only with the
  4529. solid; the rest escapes by its very fluidity. If, therefore, the
  4530. tendency of the intellect is to fabricate, we may expect to find that
  4531. whatever is fluid in the real will escape it in part, and whatever is
  4532. life in the living will escape it altogether. _Our intelligence, as it
  4533. leaves the hands of nature, has for its chief object the unorganized
  4534. solid._
  4535. When we pass in review the intellectual functions, we see that the
  4536. intellect is never quite at its ease, never entirely at home, except
  4537. when it is working upon inert matter, more particularly upon solids.
  4538. What is the most general property of the material world? It is extended:
  4539. it presents to us objects external to other objects, and, in these
  4540. objects, parts external to parts. No doubt, it is useful to us, in view
  4541. of our ulterior manipulation, to regard each object as divisible into
  4542. parts arbitrarily cut up, each part being again divisible as we like,
  4543. and so on _ad infinitum_. But it is above all necessary, for our present
  4544. manipulation, to regard the real object in hand, or the real elements
  4545. into which we have resolved it, as _provisionally final_, and to treat
  4546. them as so many _units_. To this possibility of decomposing matter as
  4547. much as we please, and in any way we please, we allude when we speak of
  4548. the _continuity_ of material extension; but this continuity, as we see
  4549. it, is nothing else but our ability, an ability that matter allows to us
  4550. to choose the mode of discontinuity we shall find in it. It is always,
  4551. in fact, the mode of discontinuity once chosen that appears to us as the
  4552. actually real one and that which fixes our attention, just because it
  4553. rules our action. Thus discontinuity is thought for itself; it is
  4554. thinkable in itself; we form an idea of it by a positive act of our
  4555. mind; while the intellectual representation of continuity is negative,
  4556. being, at bottom, only the refusal of our mind, before any actually
  4557. given system of decomposition, to regard it as the only possible one.
  4558. _Of the discontinuous alone does the intellect form a clear idea._
  4559. On the other hand, the objects we act on are certainly mobile objects,
  4560. but the important thing for us to know is _whither_ the mobile object is
  4561. going and _where_ it is at any moment of its passage. In other words,
  4562. our interest is directed, before all, to its actual or future positions,
  4563. and not to the _progress_ by which it passes from one position to
  4564. another, progress which is the movement itself. In our actions, which
  4565. are systematized movements, what we fix our mind on is the end or
  4566. meaning of the movement, its design as a whole--in a word, the immobile
  4567. plan of its execution. That which really moves in action interests us
  4568. only so far as the whole can be advanced, retarded, or stopped by any
  4569. incident that may happen on the way. From mobility itself our intellect
  4570. turns aside, because it has nothing to gain in dealing with it. If the
  4571. intellect were meant for pure theorizing, it would take its place within
  4572. movement, for movement is reality itself, and immobility is always only
  4573. apparent or relative. But the intellect is meant for something
  4574. altogether different. Unless it does violence to itself, it takes the
  4575. opposite course; it always starts from immobility, as if this were the
  4576. ultimate reality: when it tries to form an idea of movement, it does so
  4577. by constructing movement out of immobilities put together. This
  4578. operation, whose illegitimacy and danger in the field of speculation we
  4579. shall show later on (it leads to dead-locks, and creates artificially
  4580. insoluble philosophical problems), is easily justified when we refer it
  4581. to its proper goal. Intelligence, in its natural state, aims at a
  4582. practically useful end. When it substitutes for movement immobilities
  4583. put together, it does not pretend to reconstitute the movement such as
  4584. it actually is; it merely replaces it with a practical equivalent. It is
  4585. the philosophers who are mistaken when they import into the domain of
  4586. speculation a method of thinking which is made for action. But of this
  4587. more anon. Suffice it now to say that to the stable and unchangeable our
  4588. intellect is attached by virtue of its natural disposition. _Of
  4589. immobility alone does the intellect form a clear idea._
  4590. Now, fabricating consists in carving out the form of an object in
  4591. matter. What is the most important is the form to be obtained. As to
  4592. the matter, we choose that which is most convenient; but, in order to
  4593. choose it, that is to say, in order to go and seek it among many others,
  4594. we must have tried, in imagination at least, to endow every kind of
  4595. matter with the form of the object conceived. In other words, an
  4596. intelligence which aims at fabricating is an intelligence which never
  4597. stops at the actual form of things nor regards it as final, but, on the
  4598. contrary, looks upon all matter as if it were carvable at will. Plato
  4599. compares the good dialectician to the skilful cook who carves the animal
  4600. without breaking its bones, by following the articulations marked out by
  4601. nature.[64] An intelligence which always proceeded thus would really be
  4602. an intelligence turned toward speculation. But action, and in particular
  4603. fabrication, requires the opposite mental tendency: it makes us consider
  4604. every actual form of things, even the form of natural things, as
  4605. artificial and provisional; it makes our thought efface from the object
  4606. perceived, even though organized and living, the lines that outwardly
  4607. mark its inward structure; in short, it makes us regard its matter as
  4608. indifferent to its form. The whole of matter is made to appear to our
  4609. thought as an immense piece of cloth in which we can cut out what we
  4610. will and sew it together again as we please. Let us note, in passing,
  4611. that it is this power that we affirm when we say that there is a
  4612. _space_, that is to say, a homogeneous and empty medium, infinite and
  4613. infinitely divisible, lending itself indifferently to any mode of
  4614. decomposition whatsoever. A medium of this kind is never perceived; it
  4615. is only conceived. What is perceived is extension colored, resistant,
  4616. divided according to the lines which mark out the boundaries of real
  4617. bodies or of their real elements. But when we think of our power over
  4618. this matter, that is to say, of our faculty of decomposing and
  4619. recomposing it as we please, we project the whole of these possible
  4620. decompositions and recompositions behind real extension in the form of a
  4621. homogeneous space, empty and indifferent, which is supposed to underlie
  4622. it. This space is therefore, pre-eminently, the plan of our possible
  4623. action on things, although, indeed, things have a natural tendency, as
  4624. we shall explain further on, to enter into a frame of this kind. It is a
  4625. view taken by mind. The animal has probably no idea of it, even when,
  4626. like us, it perceives extended things. It is an idea that symbolizes the
  4627. tendency of the human intellect to fabrication. But this point must not
  4628. detain us now. Suffice it to say that _the intellect is characterized by
  4629. the unlimited power of decomposing according to any law and of
  4630. recomposing into any system_.
  4631. We have now enumerated a few of the essential features of human
  4632. intelligence. But we have hitherto considered the individual in
  4633. isolation, without taking account of social life. In reality, man is a
  4634. being who lives in society. If it be true that the human intellect aims
  4635. at fabrication, we must add that, for that as well as for other
  4636. purposes, it is associated with other intellects. Now, it is difficult
  4637. to imagine a society whose members do not communicate by signs. Insect
  4638. societies probably have a language, and this language must be adapted,
  4639. like that of man, to the necessities of life in common. By language
  4640. community of action is made possible. But the requirements of joint
  4641. action are not at all the same in a colony of ants and in a human
  4642. society. In insect societies there is generally polymorphism, the
  4643. subdivision of labor is natural, and each individual is riveted by its
  4644. structure to the function it performs. In any case, these societies are
  4645. based on instinct, and consequently on certain actions or fabrications
  4646. that are more or less dependent on the form of the organs. So if the
  4647. ants, for instance, have a language, the signs which compose it must be
  4648. very limited in number, and each of them, once the species is formed,
  4649. must remain invariably attached to a certain object or a certain
  4650. operation: the sign is adherent to the thing signified. In human
  4651. society, on the contrary, fabrication and action are of variable form,
  4652. and, moreover, each individual must learn his part, because he is not
  4653. preordained to it by his structure. So a language is required which
  4654. makes it possible to be always passing from what is known to what is yet
  4655. to be known. There must be a language whose signs--which cannot be
  4656. infinite in number--are extensible to an infinity of things. This
  4657. tendency of the sign to transfer itself from one object to another is
  4658. characteristic of human language. It is observable in the little child
  4659. as soon as he begins to speak. Immediately and naturally he extends the
  4660. meaning of the words he learns, availing himself of the most accidental
  4661. connection or the most distant analogy to detach and transfer elsewhere
  4662. the sign that had been associated in his hearing with a particular
  4663. object. "Anything can designate anything;" such is the latent principle
  4664. of infantine language. This tendency has been wrongly confused with the
  4665. faculty of generalizing. The animals themselves generalize; and,
  4666. moreover, a sign--even an instinctive sign--always to some degree
  4667. represents a genus. But what characterizes the signs of human language
  4668. is not so much their generality as their mobility. _The instinctive sign
  4669. is_ adherent, _the intelligent sign is_ mobile.
  4670. Now, this mobility of words, that makes them able to pass from one thing
  4671. to another, has enabled them to be extended from things to ideas.
  4672. Certainly, language would not have given the faculty of reflecting to an
  4673. intelligence entirely externalized and incapable of turning homeward.
  4674. An intelligence which reflects is one that originally had a surplus of
  4675. energy to spend, over and above practically useful efforts. It is a
  4676. consciousness that has virtually reconquered itself. But still the
  4677. virtual has to become actual. Without language, intelligence would
  4678. probably have remained riveted to the material objects which it was
  4679. interested in considering. It would have lived in a state of
  4680. somnambulism, outside itself, hypnotized on its own work. Language has
  4681. greatly contributed to its liberation. The word, made to pass from one
  4682. thing to another, is, in fact, by nature transferable and free. It can
  4683. therefore be extended, not only from one perceived thing to another, but
  4684. even from a perceived thing to a recollection of that thing, from the
  4685. precise recollection to a more fleeting image, and finally from an image
  4686. fleeting, though still pictured, to the picturing of the act by which
  4687. the image is pictured, that is to say, to the idea. Thus is revealed to
  4688. the intelligence, hitherto always turned outwards, a whole internal
  4689. world--the spectacle of its own workings. It required only this
  4690. opportunity, at length offered by language. It profits by the fact that
  4691. the word is an external thing, which the intelligence can catch hold of
  4692. and cling to, and at the same time an immaterial thing, by means of
  4693. which the intelligence can penetrate even to the inwardness of its own
  4694. work. Its first business was indeed to make instruments, but this
  4695. fabrication is possible only by the employment of certain means which
  4696. are not cut to the exact measure of their object, but go beyond it and
  4697. thus allow intelligence a supplementary--that is to say disinterested
  4698. work. From the moment that the intellect, reflecting upon its own
  4699. doings, perceives itself as a creator of ideas, as a faculty of
  4700. representation in general, there is no object of which it may not wish
  4701. to have the idea, even though that object be without direct relation to
  4702. practical action. That is why we said there are things that intellect
  4703. alone can seek. Intellect alone, indeed, troubles itself about theory;
  4704. and its theory would fain embrace everything--not only inanimate matter,
  4705. over which it has a natural hold, but even life and thought.
  4706. By what means, what instruments, in short by what method it will
  4707. approach these problems, we can easily guess. Originally, it was
  4708. fashioned to the form of matter. Language itself, which has enabled it
  4709. to extend its field of operations, is made to designate things, and
  4710. nought but things: it is only because the word is mobile, because it
  4711. flies from one thing to another, that the intellect was sure to take it,
  4712. sooner or later, on the wing, while it was not settled on anything, and
  4713. apply it to an object which is not a thing and which, concealed till
  4714. then, awaited the coming of the word to pass from darkness to light. But
  4715. the word, by covering up this object, again converts it into a thing. So
  4716. intelligence, even when it no longer operates upon its own object,
  4717. follows habits it has contracted in that operation: it applies forms
  4718. that are indeed those of unorganized matter. It is made for this kind of
  4719. work. With this kind of work alone is it fully satisfied. And that is
  4720. what intelligence expresses by saying that thus only it arrives at
  4721. _distinctness_ and _clearness_.
  4722. It must, therefore, in order to think itself clearly and distinctly,
  4723. perceive itself under the form of discontinuity. Concepts, in fact, are
  4724. outside each other, like objects in space; and they have the same
  4725. stability as such objects, on which they have been modeled. Taken
  4726. together, they constitute an "intelligible world," that resembles the
  4727. world of solids in its essential characters, but whose elements are
  4728. lighter, more diaphanous, easier for the intellect to deal with than the
  4729. image of concrete things: they are not, indeed, the perception itself
  4730. of things, but the representation of the act by which the intellect is
  4731. fixed on them. They are, therefore, not images, but symbols. Our logic
  4732. is the complete set of rules that must be followed in using symbols. As
  4733. these symbols are derived from the consideration of solids, as the rules
  4734. for combining these symbols hardly do more than express the most general
  4735. relations among solids, our logic triumphs in that science which takes
  4736. the solidity of bodies for its object, that is, in geometry. Logic and
  4737. geometry engender each other, as we shall see a little further on. It is
  4738. from the extension of a certain natural geometry, suggested by the most
  4739. general and immediately perceived properties of solids, that natural
  4740. logic has arisen; then from this natural logic, in its turn, has sprung
  4741. scientific geometry, which extends further and further the knowledge of
  4742. the external properties of solids.[65] Geometry and logic are strictly
  4743. applicable to matter; in it they are at home, and in it they can proceed
  4744. quite alone. But, outside this domain, pure reasoning needs to be
  4745. supervised by common sense, which is an altogether different thing.
  4746. Thus, all the elementary forces of the intellect tend to transform
  4747. matter into an instrument of action, that is, in the etymological sense
  4748. of the word, into an _organ_. Life, not content with producing
  4749. organisms, would fain give them as an appendage inorganic matter itself,
  4750. converted into an immense organ by the industry of the living being.
  4751. Such is the initial task it assigns to intelligence. That is why the
  4752. intellect always behaves as if it were fascinated by the contemplation
  4753. of inert matter. It is life looking outward, putting itself outside
  4754. itself, adopting the ways of unorganized nature in principle, in order
  4755. to direct them in fact. Hence its bewilderment when it turns to the
  4756. living and is confronted with organization. It does what it can, it
  4757. resolves the organized into the unorganized, for it cannot, without
  4758. reversing its natural direction and twisting about on itself, think true
  4759. continuity, real mobility, reciprocal penetration--in a word, that
  4760. creative evolution which is life.
  4761. Consider continuity. The aspect of life that is accessible to our
  4762. intellect--as indeed to our senses, of which our intellect is the
  4763. extension--is that which offers a hold to our action. Now, to modify an
  4764. object, we have to perceive it as divisible and discontinuous. From the
  4765. point of view of positive science, an incomparable progress was realized
  4766. when the organized tissues were resolved into cells. The study of the
  4767. cell, in its turn, has shown it to be an organism whose complexity seems
  4768. to grow, the more thoroughly it is examined. The more science advances,
  4769. the more it sees the number grow of heterogeneous elements which are
  4770. placed together, outside each other, to make up a living being. Does
  4771. science thus get any nearer to life? Does it not, on the contrary, find
  4772. that what is really life in the living seems to recede with every step
  4773. by which it pushes further the detail of the parts combined? There is
  4774. indeed already among scientists a tendency to regard the substance of
  4775. the organism as continuous, and the cell as an artificial entity.[66]
  4776. But, supposing this view were finally to prevail, it could only lead, on
  4777. deeper study, to some other mode of analyzing of the living being, and
  4778. so to a new discontinuity--although less removed, perhaps, from the real
  4779. continuity of life. The truth is that this continuity cannot be thought
  4780. by the intellect while it follows its natural movement. It implies at
  4781. once the multiplicity of elements and the interpenetration of all by
  4782. all, two conditions that can hardly be reconciled in the field in which
  4783. our industry, and consequently our intellect, is engaged.
  4784. Just as we separate in space, we fix in time. The intellect is not made
  4785. to think _evolution_, in the proper sense of the word--that is to say,
  4786. the continuity of a change that is pure mobility. We shall not dwell
  4787. here on this point, which we propose to study in a special chapter.
  4788. Suffice it to say that the intellect represents _becoming_ as a series
  4789. of _states_, each of which is homogeneous with itself and consequently
  4790. does not change. Is our attention called to the internal change of one
  4791. of these states? At once we decompose it into another series of states
  4792. which, reunited, will be supposed to make up this internal modification.
  4793. Each of these new states must be invariable, or else their internal
  4794. change, if we are forced to notice it, must be resolved again into a
  4795. fresh series of invariable states, and so on to infinity. Here again,
  4796. thinking consists in reconstituting, and, naturally, it is with _given_
  4797. elements, and consequently with _stable_ elements, that we reconstitute.
  4798. So that, though we may do our best to imitate the mobility of becoming
  4799. by an addition that is ever going on, becoming itself slips through our
  4800. fingers just when we think we are holding it tight.
  4801. Precisely because it is always trying to reconstitute, and to
  4802. reconstitute with what is given, the intellect lets what is _new_ in
  4803. each moment of a history escape. It does not admit the unforeseeable. It
  4804. rejects all creation. That definite antecedents bring forth a definite
  4805. consequent, calculable as a function of them, is what satisfies our
  4806. intellect. That a definite end calls forth definite means to attain it,
  4807. is what we also understand. In both cases we have to do with the known
  4808. which is combined with the known, in short, with the old which is
  4809. repeated. Our intellect is there at its ease; and, whatever be the
  4810. object, it will abstract, separate, eliminate, so as to substitute for
  4811. the object itself, if necessary, an approximate equivalent in which
  4812. things will happen in this way. But that each instant is a fresh
  4813. endowment, that the new is ever upspringing, that the form just come
  4814. into existence (although, _when once produced_, it may be regarded as an
  4815. effect determined by its causes) could never have been foreseen--because
  4816. the causes here, unique in their kind, are part of the effect, have come
  4817. into existence with it, and are determined by it as much as they
  4818. determine it--all this we can feel within ourselves and also divine, by
  4819. sympathy, outside ourselves, but we cannot think it, in the strict sense
  4820. of the word, nor express it in terms of pure understanding. No wonder at
  4821. that: we must remember what our intellect is meant for. The causality it
  4822. seeks and finds everywhere expresses the very mechanism of our industry,
  4823. in which we go on recomposing the same whole with the same parts,
  4824. repeating the same movements to obtain the same result. The finality it
  4825. understands best is the finality of our industry, in which we work on a
  4826. model given in advance, that is to say, old or composed of elements
  4827. already known. As to invention properly so called, which is, however,
  4828. the point of departure of industry itself, our intellect does not
  4829. succeed in grasping it in its _upspringing_, that is to say, in its
  4830. indivisibility, nor in its _fervor_, that is to say, in its
  4831. creativeness. Explaining it always consists in resolving it, it the
  4832. unforeseeable and new, into elements old or known, arranged in a
  4833. different order. The intellect can no more admit complete novelty than
  4834. real becoming; that is to say, here again it lets an essential aspect of
  4835. life escape, as if it were not intended to think such an object.
  4836. All our analyses bring us to this conclusion. But it is hardly necessary
  4837. to go into such long details concerning the mechanism of intellectual
  4838. working; it is enough to consider the results. We see that the
  4839. intellect, so skilful in dealing with the inert, is awkward the moment
  4840. it touches the living. Whether it wants to treat the life of the body or
  4841. the life of the mind, it proceeds with the rigor, the stiffness and the
  4842. brutality of an instrument not designed for such use. The history of
  4843. hygiene or of pedagogy teaches us much in this matter. When we think of
  4844. the cardinal, urgent and constant need we have to preserve our bodies
  4845. and to raise our souls, of the special facilities given to each of us,
  4846. in this field, to experiment continually on ourselves and on others, of
  4847. the palpable injury by which the wrongness of a medical or pedagogical
  4848. practise is both made manifest and punished at once, we are amazed at
  4849. the stupidity and especially at the persistence of errors. We may easily
  4850. find their origin in the natural obstinacy with which we treat the
  4851. living like the lifeless and think all reality, however fluid, under the
  4852. form of the sharply defined solid. We are at ease only in the
  4853. discontinuous, in the immobile, in the dead. _The intellect is
  4854. characterized by a natural inability to comprehend life._
  4855. * * * * *
  4856. Instinct, on the contrary, is molded on the very form of life. While
  4857. intelligence treats everything mechanically, instinct proceeds, so to
  4858. speak, organically. If the consciousness that slumbers in it should
  4859. awake, if it were wound up into knowledge instead of being wound off
  4860. into action, if we could ask and it could reply, it would give up to us
  4861. the most intimate secrets of life. For it only carries out further the
  4862. work by which life organizes matter--so that we cannot say, as has often
  4863. been shown, where organization ends and where instinct begins. When the
  4864. little chick is breaking its shell with a peck of its beak, it is acting
  4865. by instinct, and yet it does but carry on the movement which has borne
  4866. it through embryonic life. Inversely, in the course of embryonic life
  4867. itself (especially when the embryo lives freely in the form of a larva),
  4868. many of the acts accomplished must be referred to instinct. The most
  4869. essential of the primary instincts are really, therefore, vital
  4870. processes. The potential consciousness that accompanies them is
  4871. generally actualized only at the outset of the act, and leaves the rest
  4872. of the process to go on by itself. It would only have to expand more
  4873. widely, and then dive into its own depth completely, to be one with the
  4874. generative force of life.
  4875. When we see in a living body thousands of cells working together to a
  4876. common end, dividing the task between them, living each for itself at
  4877. the same time as for the others, preserving itself, feeding itself,
  4878. reproducing itself, responding to the menace of danger by appropriate
  4879. defensive reactions, how can we help thinking of so many instincts? And
  4880. yet these are the natural functions of the cell, the constitutive
  4881. elements of its vitality. On the other hand, when we see the bees of a
  4882. hive forming a system so strictly organized that no individual can live
  4883. apart from the others beyond a certain time, even though furnished with
  4884. food and shelter, how can we help recognizing that the hive is really,
  4885. and not metaphorically, a single organism, of which each bee is a cell
  4886. united to the others by invisible bonds? The instinct that animates the
  4887. bee is indistinguishable, then, from the force that animates the cell,
  4888. or is only a prolongation of that force. In extreme cases like this,
  4889. instinct coincides with the work of organization.
  4890. Of course there are degrees of perfection in the same instinct. Between
  4891. the humble-bee, and the honey-bee, for instance, the distance is great;
  4892. and we pass from one to the other through a great number of
  4893. intermediaries, which correspond to so many complications of the social
  4894. life. But the same diversity is found in the functioning of
  4895. histological elements belonging to different tissues more or less akin.
  4896. In both cases there are manifold variations on one and the same theme.
  4897. The constancy of the theme is manifest, however, and the variations only
  4898. fit it to the diversity of the circumstances.
  4899. Now, in both cases, in the instinct of the animal and in the vital
  4900. properties of the cell, the same knowledge and the same ignorance are
  4901. shown. All goes on as if the cell knew, of the other cells, what
  4902. concerns itself; as if the animal knew, of the other animals, what it
  4903. can utilize--all else remaining in shade. It seems as if life, as soon
  4904. as it has become bound up in a species, is cut off from the rest of its
  4905. own work, save at one or two points that are of vital concern to the
  4906. species just arisen. Is it not plain that life goes to work here exactly
  4907. like consciousness, exactly like memory? We trail behind us, unawares,
  4908. the whole of our past; but our memory pours into the present only the
  4909. odd recollection or two that in some way complete our present situation.
  4910. Thus the instinctive knowledge which one species possesses of another on
  4911. a certain particular point has its root in the very unity of life, which
  4912. is, to use the expression of an ancient philosopher, a "whole
  4913. sympathetic to itself." It is impossible to consider some of the special
  4914. instincts of the animal and of the plant, evidently arisen in
  4915. extraordinary circumstances, without relating them to those
  4916. recollections, seemingly forgotten, which spring up suddenly under the
  4917. pressure of an urgent need.
  4918. No doubt many secondary instincts, and also many varieties of primary
  4919. instinct, admit of a scientific explanation. Yet it is doubtful whether
  4920. science, with its present methods of explanation, will ever succeed in
  4921. analyzing instinct completely. The reason is that instinct and
  4922. intelligence are two divergent developments of one and the same
  4923. principle, which in the one case remains within itself, in the other
  4924. steps out of itself and becomes absorbed in the utilization of inert
  4925. matter. This gradual divergence testifies to a radical incompatibility,
  4926. and points to the fact that it is impossible for intelligence to
  4927. reabsorb instinct. That which is instinctive in instinct cannot be
  4928. expressed in terms of intelligence, nor, consequently, can it be
  4929. analyzed.
  4930. A man born blind, who had lived among others born blind, could not be
  4931. made to believe in the possibility of perceiving a distant object
  4932. without first perceiving all the objects in between. Yet vision performs
  4933. this miracle. In a certain sense the blind man is right, since vision,
  4934. having its origin in the stimulation of the retina, by the vibrations of
  4935. the light, is nothing else, in fact, but a retinal touch. Such is indeed
  4936. the _scientific_ explanation, for the function of science is just to
  4937. express all perceptions in terms of touch. But we have shown elsewhere
  4938. that the philosophical explanation of perception (if it may still be
  4939. called an explanation) must be of another kind.[67] Now instinct also is
  4940. a knowledge at a distance. It has the same relation to intelligence that
  4941. vision has to touch. Science cannot do otherwise than express it in
  4942. terms of intelligence; but in so doing it constructs an imitation of
  4943. instinct rather than penetrates within it.
  4944. Any one can convince himself of this by studying the ingenious theories
  4945. of evolutionist biology. They may be reduced to two types, which are
  4946. often intermingled. One type, following the principles of neo-Darwinism,
  4947. regards instinct as a sum of accidental differences preserved by
  4948. selection: such and such a useful behavior, naturally adopted by the
  4949. individual in virtue of an accidental predisposition of the germ, has
  4950. been transmitted from germ to germ, waiting for chance to add fresh
  4951. improvements to it by the same method. The other type regards instinct
  4952. as lapsed intelligence: the action, found useful by the species or by
  4953. certain of its representatives, is supposed to have engendered a habit,
  4954. which, by hereditary transmission, has become an instinct. Of these two
  4955. types of theory, the first has the advantage of being able to bring in
  4956. hereditary transmission without raising grave objection; for the
  4957. accidental modification which it places at the origin of the instinct is
  4958. not supposed to have been acquired by the individual, but to have been
  4959. inherent in the germ. But, on the other hand, it is absolutely incapable
  4960. of explaining instincts as sagacious as those of most insects. These
  4961. instincts surely could not have attained, all at once, their present
  4962. degree of complexity; they have probably evolved; but, in a hypothesis
  4963. like that of the neo-Darwinians, the evolution of instinct could have
  4964. come to pass only by the progressive addition of new pieces which, in
  4965. some way, by happy accidents, came to fit into the old. Now it is
  4966. evident that, in most cases, instinct could not have perfected itself by
  4967. simple accretion: each new piece really requires, if all is not to be
  4968. spoiled, a complete recasting of the whole. How could mere chance work a
  4969. recasting of the kind? I agree that an accidental modification of the
  4970. germ may be passed on hereditarily, and may somehow wait for fresh
  4971. accidental modifications to come and complicate it. I agree also that
  4972. natural selection may eliminate all those of the more complicated forms
  4973. of instinct that are not fit to survive. Still, in order that the life
  4974. of the instinct may evolve, complications fit to survive have to be
  4975. produced. Now they will be produced only if, in certain cases, the
  4976. addition of a new element brings about the correlative change of all the
  4977. old elements. No one will maintain that chance could perform such a
  4978. miracle: in one form or another we shall appeal to intelligence. We
  4979. shall suppose that it is by an effort, more or less conscious, that the
  4980. living being develops a higher instinct. But then we shall have to admit
  4981. that an acquired habit can become hereditary, and that it does so
  4982. regularly enough to ensure an evolution. The thing is doubtful, to put
  4983. it mildly. Even if we could refer the instincts of animals to habits
  4984. intelligently acquired and hereditarily transmitted, it is not clear how
  4985. this sort of explanation could be extended to the vegetable world, where
  4986. effort is never intelligent, even supposing it is sometimes conscious.
  4987. And yet, when we see with what sureness and precision climbing plants
  4988. use their tendrils, what marvelously combined manoeuvres the orchids
  4989. perform to procure their fertilization by means of insects,[68] how can
  4990. we help thinking that these are so many instincts?
  4991. This is not saying that the theory of the neo-Darwinians must be
  4992. altogether rejected, any more than that of the neo-Lamarckians. The
  4993. first are probably right in holding that evolution takes place from germ
  4994. to germ rather than from individual to individual; the second are right
  4995. in saying that at the origin of instinct there is an effort (although it
  4996. is something quite different, we believe, from an _intelligent_ effort).
  4997. But the former are probably wrong when they make the evolution of
  4998. instinct an _accidental_ evolution, and the latter when they regard the
  4999. effort from which instinct proceeds as an _individual_ effort. The
  5000. effort by which a species modifies its instinct, and modifies itself as
  5001. well, must be a much deeper thing, dependent solely neither on
  5002. circumstances nor on individuals. It is not purely accidental, although
  5003. accident has a large place in it; and it does not depend solely on the
  5004. initiative of individuals, although individuals collaborate in it.
  5005. Compare the different forms of the same instinct in different species of
  5006. hymenoptera. The impression derived is not always that of an increasing
  5007. complexity made of elements that have been added together one after the
  5008. other. Nor does it suggest the idea of steps up a ladder. Rather do we
  5009. think, in many cases at least, of the circumference of a circle, from
  5010. different points of which these different varieties have started, all
  5011. facing the same centre, all making an effort in that direction, but each
  5012. approaching it only to the extent of its means, and to the extent also
  5013. to which this central point has been illumined for it. In other words,
  5014. instinct is everywhere complete, but it is more or less simplified, and,
  5015. above all, simplified _differently_. On the other hand, in cases where
  5016. we do get the impression of an ascending scale, as if one and the same
  5017. instinct had gone on complicating itself more and more in one direction
  5018. and along a straight line, the species which are thus arranged by their
  5019. instincts into a linear series are by no means always akin. Thus, the
  5020. comparative study, in recent years, of the social instinct in the
  5021. different apidae proves that the instinct of the meliponines is
  5022. intermediary in complexity between the still rudimentary tendency of the
  5023. humble bees and the consummate science of the true bees; yet there can
  5024. be no kinship between the bees and the meliponines.[69] Most likely, the
  5025. degree of complexity of these different societies has nothing to do with
  5026. any greater or smaller number of added elements. We seem rather to be
  5027. before a _musical theme_, which had first been transposed, the theme as
  5028. a whole, into a certain number of tones and on which, still the whole
  5029. theme, different variations had been played, some very simple, others
  5030. very skilful. As to the original theme, it is everywhere and nowhere.
  5031. It is in vain that we try to express it in terms of any idea: it must
  5032. have been, originally, _felt_ rather than _thought_. We get the same
  5033. impression before the paralyzing instinct of certain wasps. We know that
  5034. the different species of hymenoptera that have this paralyzing instinct
  5035. lay their eggs in spiders, beetles or caterpillars, which, having first
  5036. been subjected by the wasp to a skilful surgical operation, will go on
  5037. living motionless a certain number of days, and thus provide the larvae
  5038. with fresh meat. In the sting which they give to the nerve-centres of
  5039. their victim, in order to destroy its power of moving without killing
  5040. it, these different species of hymenoptera take into account, so to
  5041. speak, the different species of prey they respectively attack. The
  5042. Scolia, which attacks a larva of the rose-beetle, stings it in one point
  5043. only, but in this point the motor ganglia are concentrated, and those
  5044. ganglia alone: the stinging of other ganglia might cause death and
  5045. putrefaction, which it must avoid.[70] The yellow-winged Sphex, which
  5046. has chosen the cricket for its victim, knows that the cricket has three
  5047. nerve-centres which serve its three pairs of legs--or at least it acts
  5048. as if it knew this. It stings the insect first under the neck, then
  5049. behind the prothorax, and then where the thorax joins the abdomen.[71]
  5050. The Ammophila Hirsuta gives nine successive strokes of its sting upon
  5051. nine nerve-centres of its caterpillar, and then seizes the head and
  5052. squeezes it in its mandibles, enough to cause paralysis without
  5053. death.[72] The general theme is "the necessity of paralyzing without
  5054. killing"; the variations are subordinated to the structure of the victim
  5055. on which they are played. No doubt the operation is not always perfect.
  5056. It has recently been shown that the Ammophila sometimes kills the
  5057. caterpillar instead of paralyzing it, that sometimes also it paralyzes
  5058. it incompletely.[73] But, because instinct is, like intelligence,
  5059. fallible, because it also shows individual deviations, it does not at
  5060. all follow that the instinct of the Ammophila has been acquired, as has
  5061. been claimed, by tentative intelligent experiments. Even supposing that
  5062. the Ammophila has come in course of time to recognize, one after
  5063. another, by tentative experiment, the points of its victim which must be
  5064. stung to render it motionless, and also the special treatment that must
  5065. be inflicted on the head to bring about paralysis without death, how can
  5066. we imagine that elements so special of a knowledge so precise have been
  5067. regularly transmitted, one by one, by heredity? If, in all our present
  5068. experience, there were a single indisputable example of a transmission
  5069. of this kind, the inheritance of acquired characters would be questioned
  5070. by no one. As a matter of fact, the hereditary transmission of a
  5071. contracted habit is effected in an irregular and far from precise
  5072. manner, supposing it is ever really effected at all.
  5073. But the whole difficulty comes from our desire to express the knowledge
  5074. of the hymenoptera in terms of intelligence. It is this that compels us
  5075. to compare the Ammophila with the entomologist, who knows the
  5076. caterpillar as he knows everything else--from the outside, and without
  5077. having on his part a special or vital interest. The Ammophila, we
  5078. imagine, must learn, one by one, like the entomologist, the positions of
  5079. the nerve-centres of the caterpillar--must acquire at least the
  5080. practical knowledge of these positions by trying the effects of its
  5081. sting. But there is no need for such a view if we suppose a _sympathy_
  5082. (in the etymological sense of the word) between the Ammophila and its
  5083. victim, which teaches it from within, so to say, concerning the
  5084. vulnerability of the caterpillar. This feeling of vulnerability might
  5085. owe nothing to outward perception, but result from the mere presence
  5086. together of the Ammophila and the caterpillar, considered no longer as
  5087. two organisms, but as two activities. It would express, in a concrete
  5088. form, the _relation_ of the one to the other. Certainly, a scientific
  5089. theory cannot appeal to considerations of this kind. It must not put
  5090. action before organization, sympathy before perception and knowledge.
  5091. But, once more, either philosophy has nothing to see here, or its rôle
  5092. begins where that of science ends.
  5093. Whether it makes instinct a "compound reflex," or a habit formed
  5094. intelligently that has become automatism, or a sum of small accidental
  5095. advantages accumulated and fixed by selection, in every case science
  5096. claims to resolve instinct completely either into _intelligent_ actions,
  5097. or into mechanisms built up piece by piece like those combined by our
  5098. _intelligence_. I agree indeed that science is here within its function.
  5099. It gives us, in default of a real analysis of the object, a translation
  5100. of this object in terms of intelligence. But is it not plain that
  5101. science itself invites philosophy to consider things in another way? If
  5102. our biology was still that of Aristotle, if it regarded the series of
  5103. living beings as unilinear, if it showed us the whole of life evolving
  5104. towards intelligence and passing, to that end, through sensibility and
  5105. instinct, we should be right, we, the intelligent beings, in turning
  5106. back towards the earlier and consequently inferior manifestations of
  5107. life and in claiming to fit them, without deforming them, into the molds
  5108. of our understanding. But one of the clearest results of biology has
  5109. been to show that evolution has taken place along divergent lines. It is
  5110. at the extremity of two of these lines--the two principal--that we find
  5111. intelligence and instinct in forms almost pure. Why, then, should
  5112. instinct be resolvable into intelligent elements? Why, even, into terms
  5113. entirely intelligible? Is it not obvious that to think here of the
  5114. intelligent, or of the absolutely intelligible, is to go back to the
  5115. Aristotelian theory of nature? No doubt it is better to go back to that
  5116. than to stop short before instinct as before an unfathomable mystery.
  5117. But, though instinct is not within the domain of intelligence, it is not
  5118. situated beyond the limits of mind. In the phenomena of feeling, in
  5119. unreflecting sympathy and antipathy, we experience in ourselves--though
  5120. under a much vaguer form, and one too much penetrated with
  5121. intelligence--something of what must happen in the consciousness of an
  5122. insect acting by instinct. Evolution does but sunder, in order to
  5123. develop them to the end, elements which, at their origin,
  5124. interpenetrated each other. More precisely, intelligence is, before
  5125. anything else, the faculty of relating one point of space to another,
  5126. one material object to another; it applies to all things, but remains
  5127. outside them; and of a deep cause it perceives only the effects spread
  5128. out side by side. Whatever be the force that is at work in the genesis
  5129. of the nervous system of the caterpillar, to our eyes and our
  5130. intelligence it is only a juxtaposition of nerves and nervous centres.
  5131. It is true that we thus get the whole outer effect of it. The Ammophila,
  5132. no doubt, discerns but a very little of that force, just what concerns
  5133. itself; but at least it discerns it from within, quite otherwise than by
  5134. a process of knowledge--by an intuition (_lived_ rather than
  5135. _represented_), which is probably like what we call divining sympathy.
  5136. A very significant fact is the swing to and fro of scientific theories
  5137. of instinct, from regarding it as intelligent to regarding it as simply
  5138. intelligible, or, shall I say, between likening it to an intelligence
  5139. "lapsed" and reducing it to a pure mechanism.[74] Each of these systems
  5140. of explanation triumphs in its criticism of the other, the first when it
  5141. shows us that instinct cannot be a mere reflex, the other when it
  5142. declares that instinct is something different from intelligence, even
  5143. fallen into unconsciousness. What can this mean but that they are two
  5144. symbolisms, equally acceptable in certain respects, and, in other
  5145. respects, equally inadequate to their object? The concrete explanation,
  5146. no longer scientific, but metaphysical, must be sought along quite
  5147. another path, not in the direction of intelligence, but in that of
  5148. "sympathy."
  5149. * * * * *
  5150. Instinct is sympathy. If this sympathy could extend its object and also
  5151. reflect upon itself, it would give us the key to vital operations--just
  5152. as intelligence, developed and disciplined, guides us into matter.
  5153. For--we cannot too often repeat it--intelligence and instinct are turned
  5154. in opposite directions, the former towards inert matter, the latter
  5155. towards life. Intelligence, by means of science, which is its work, will
  5156. deliver up to us more and more completely the secret of physical
  5157. operations; of life it brings us, and moreover only claims to bring us,
  5158. a translation in terms of inertia. It goes all round life, taking from
  5159. outside the greatest possible number of views of it, drawing it into
  5160. itself instead of entering into it. But it is to the very inwardness of
  5161. life that _intuition_ leads us--by intuition I mean instinct that has
  5162. become disinterested, self-conscious, capable of reflecting upon its
  5163. object and of enlarging it indefinitely.
  5164. That an effort of this kind is not impossible, is proved by the
  5165. existence in man of an aesthetic faculty along with normal perception.
  5166. Our eye perceives the features of the living being, merely as assembled,
  5167. not as mutually organized. The intention of life, the simple movement
  5168. that runs through the lines, that binds them together and gives them
  5169. significance, escapes it. This intention is just what the artist tries
  5170. to regain, in placing himself back within the object by a kind of
  5171. sympathy, in breaking down, by an effort of intuition, the barrier that
  5172. space puts up between him and his model. It is true that this aesthetic
  5173. intuition, like external perception, only attains the individual. But we
  5174. can conceive an inquiry turned in the same direction as art, which would
  5175. take life _in general_ for its object, just as physical science, in
  5176. following to the end the direction pointed out by external perception,
  5177. prolongs the individual facts into general laws. No doubt this
  5178. philosophy will never obtain a knowledge of its object comparable to
  5179. that which science has of its own. Intelligence remains the luminous
  5180. nucleus around which instinct, even enlarged and purified into
  5181. intuition, forms only a vague nebulosity. But, in default of knowledge
  5182. properly so called, reserved to pure intelligence, intuition may enable
  5183. us to grasp what it is that intelligence fails to give us, and indicate
  5184. the means of supplementing it. On the one hand, it will utilize the
  5185. mechanism of intelligence itself to show how intellectual molds cease to
  5186. be strictly applicable; and on the other hand, by its own work, it will
  5187. suggest to us the vague feeling, if nothing more, of what must take the
  5188. place of intellectual molds. Thus, intuition may bring the intellect to
  5189. recognize that life does not quite go into the category of the many nor
  5190. yet into that of the one; that neither mechanical causality nor finality
  5191. can give a sufficient interpretation of the vital process. Then, by the
  5192. sympathetic communication which it establishes between us and the rest
  5193. of the living, by the expansion of our consciousness which it brings
  5194. about, it introduces us into life's own domain, which is reciprocal
  5195. interpenetration, endlessly continued creation. But, though it thereby
  5196. transcends intelligence, it is from intelligence that has come the push
  5197. that has made it rise to the point it has reached. Without intelligence,
  5198. it would have remained in the form of instinct, riveted to the special
  5199. object of its practical interest, and turned outward by it into
  5200. movements of locomotion.
  5201. How theory of knowledge must take account of these two faculties,
  5202. intellect and intuition, and how also, for want of establishing a
  5203. sufficiently clear distinction between them, it becomes involved in
  5204. inextricable difficulties, creating phantoms of ideas to which there
  5205. cling phantoms of problems, we shall endeavor to show a little further
  5206. on. We shall see that the problem of knowledge, from this point of view,
  5207. is one with the metaphysical problem, and that both one and the other
  5208. depend upon experience. On the one hand, indeed, if intelligence is
  5209. charged with matter and instinct with life, we must squeeze them both in
  5210. order to get the double essence from them; metaphysics is therefore
  5211. dependent upon theory of knowledge. But, on the other hand, if
  5212. consciousness has thus split up into intuition and intelligence, it is
  5213. because of the need it had to apply itself to matter at the same time as
  5214. it had to follow the stream of life. The double form of consciousness is
  5215. then due to the double form of the real, and theory of knowledge must be
  5216. dependent upon metaphysics. In fact, each of these two lines of thought
  5217. leads to the other; they form a circle, and there can be no other centre
  5218. to the circle but the empirical study of evolution. It is only in seeing
  5219. consciousness run through matter, lose itself there and find itself
  5220. there again, divide and reconstitute itself, that we shall form an idea
  5221. of the mutual opposition of the two terms, as also, perhaps, of their
  5222. common origin. But, on the other hand, by dwelling on this opposition of
  5223. the two elements and on this identity of origin, perhaps we shall bring
  5224. out more clearly the meaning of evolution itself.
  5225. Such will be the aim of our next chapter. But the facts that we have
  5226. just noticed must have already suggested to us the idea that life is
  5227. connected either with consciousness or with something that resembles it.
  5228. Throughout the whole extent of the animal kingdom, we have said,
  5229. consciousness seems proportionate to the living being's power of choice.
  5230. It lights up the zone of potentialities that surrounds the act. It fills
  5231. the interval between what is done and what might be done. Looked at from
  5232. without, we may regard it as a simple aid to action, a light that action
  5233. kindles, a momentary spark flying up from the friction of real action
  5234. against possible actions. But we must also point out that things would
  5235. go on in just the same way if consciousness, instead of being the
  5236. effect, were the cause. We might suppose that consciousness, even in the
  5237. most rudimentary animal, covers by right an enormous field, but is
  5238. compressed in fact in a kind of vise: each advance of the nervous
  5239. centres, by giving the organism a choice between a larger number of
  5240. actions, calls forth the potentialities that are capable of surrounding
  5241. the real, thus opening the vise wider and allowing consciousness to pass
  5242. more freely. In this second hypothesis, as in the first, consciousness
  5243. is still the instrument of action; but it is even more true to say that
  5244. action is the instrument of consciousness; for the complicating of
  5245. action with action, and the opposing of action to action, are for the
  5246. imprisoned consciousness the only possible means to set itself free.
  5247. How, then, shall we choose between the two hypotheses? If the first is
  5248. true, consciousness must express exactly, at each instant, the state of
  5249. the brain; there is strict parallelism (so far as intelligible) between
  5250. the psychical and the cerebral state. On the second hypothesis, on the
  5251. contrary, there is indeed solidarity and interdependence between the
  5252. brain and consciousness, but not parallelism: the more complicated the
  5253. brain becomes, thus giving the organism greater choice of possible
  5254. actions, the more does consciousness outrun its physical concomitant.
  5255. Thus, the recollection of the same spectacle probably modifies in the
  5256. same way a dog's brain and a man's brain, if the perception has been the
  5257. same; yet the recollection must be very different in the man's
  5258. consciousness from what it is in the dog's. In the dog, the recollection
  5259. remains the captive of perception; it is brought back to consciousness
  5260. only when an analogous perception recalls it by reproducing the same
  5261. spectacle, and then it is manifested by the recognition, _acted_ rather
  5262. than _thought_, of the present perception much more than by an actual
  5263. reappearance of the recollection itself. Man, on the contrary, is
  5264. capable of calling up the recollection at will, at any moment,
  5265. independently of the present perception. He is not limited to _playing_
  5266. his past life again; he _represents_ and _dreams_ it. The local
  5267. modification of the brain to which the recollection is attached being
  5268. the same in each case, the psychological difference between the two
  5269. recollections cannot have its ground in a particular difference of
  5270. detail between the two cerebral mechanisms, but in the difference
  5271. between the two brains taken each as a whole. The more complex of the
  5272. two, in putting a greater number of mechanisms in opposition to one
  5273. another, has enabled consciousness to disengage itself from the
  5274. restraint of one and all and to reach independence. That things do
  5275. happen in this way, that the second of the two hypotheses is that which
  5276. must be chosen, is what we have tried to prove, in a former work, by
  5277. the study of facts that best bring into relief the relation of the
  5278. conscious state to the cerebral state, the facts of normal and
  5279. pathological recognition, in particular the forms of aphasia.[75] But it
  5280. could have been proved by pure reasoning, before even it was evidenced
  5281. by facts. We have shown on what self-contradictory postulate, on what
  5282. confusion of two mutually incompatible symbolisms, the hypothesis of
  5283. equivalence between the cerebral state and the psychic state rests.[76]
  5284. The evolution of life, looked at from this point, receives a clearer
  5285. meaning, although it cannot be subsumed under any actual _idea_. It is
  5286. as if a broad current of consciousness had penetrated matter, loaded, as
  5287. all consciousness is, with an enormous multiplicity of interwoven
  5288. potentialities. It has carried matter along to organization, but its
  5289. movement has been at once infinitely retarded and infinitely divided. On
  5290. the one hand, indeed, consciousness has had to fall asleep, like the
  5291. chrysalis in the envelope in which it is preparing for itself wings;
  5292. and, on the other hand, the manifold tendencies it contained have been
  5293. distributed among divergent series of organisms which, moreover, express
  5294. these tendencies outwardly in movements rather than internally in
  5295. representations. In the course of this evolution, while some beings have
  5296. fallen more and more asleep, others have more and more completely
  5297. awakened, and the torpor of some has served the activity of others. But
  5298. the waking could be effected in two different ways. Life, that is to say
  5299. consciousness launched into matter, fixed its attention either on its
  5300. own movement or on the matter it was passing through; and it has thus
  5301. been turned either in the direction of intuition or in that of
  5302. intellect. Intuition, at first sight, seems far preferable to intellect,
  5303. since in it life and consciousness remain within themselves. But a
  5304. glance at the evolution of living beings shows us that intuition could
  5305. not go very far. On the side of intuition, consciousness found itself so
  5306. restricted by its envelope that intuition had to shrink into instinct,
  5307. that is, to embrace only the very small portion of life that interested
  5308. it; and this it embraces only in the dark, touching it while hardly
  5309. seeing it. On this side, the horizon was soon shut out. On the contrary,
  5310. consciousness, in shaping itself into intelligence, that is to say in
  5311. concentrating itself at first on matter, seems to externalize itself in
  5312. relation to itself; but, just because it adapts itself thereby to
  5313. objects from without, it succeeds in moving among them and in evading
  5314. the barriers they oppose to it, thus opening to itself an unlimited
  5315. field. Once freed, moreover, it can turn inwards on itself, and awaken
  5316. the potentialities of intuition which still slumber within it.
  5317. From this point of view, not only does consciousness appear as the
  5318. motive principle of evolution, but also, among conscious beings
  5319. themselves, man comes to occupy a privileged place. Between him and the
  5320. animals the difference is no longer one of degree, but of kind. We shall
  5321. show how this conclusion is arrived at in our next chapter. Let us now
  5322. show how the preceding analyses suggest it.
  5323. A noteworthy fact is the extraordinary disproportion between the
  5324. consequences of an invention and the invention itself. We have said that
  5325. intelligence is modeled on matter and that it aims in the first place at
  5326. fabrication. But does it fabricate in order to fabricate or does it not
  5327. pursue involuntarily, and even unconsciously, something entirely
  5328. different? Fabricating consists in shaping matter, in making it supple
  5329. and in bending it, in converting it into an instrument in order to
  5330. become master of it. It is this _mastery_ that profits humanity, much
  5331. more even than the material result of the invention itself. Though we
  5332. derive an immediate advantage from the thing made, as an intelligent
  5333. animal might do, and though this advantage be all the inventor sought,
  5334. it is a slight matter compared with the new ideas and new feelings that
  5335. the invention may give rise to in every direction, as if the essential
  5336. part of the effect were to raise us above ourselves and enlarge our
  5337. horizon. Between the effect and the cause the disproportion is so great
  5338. that it is difficult to regard the cause as _producer_ of its effect. It
  5339. releases it, whilst settling, indeed, its direction. Everything happens
  5340. as though the grip of intelligence on matter were, in its main
  5341. intention, to _let something pass_ that matter is holding back.
  5342. The same impression arises when we compare the brain of man with that of
  5343. the animals. The difference at first appears to be only a difference of
  5344. size and complexity. But, judging by function, there must be something
  5345. else besides. In the animal, the motor mechanisms that the brain
  5346. succeeds in setting up, or, in other words, the habits contracted
  5347. voluntarily, have no other object nor effect than the accomplishment of
  5348. the movements marked out in these habits, stored in these mechanisms.
  5349. But, in man, the motor habit may have a second result, out of proportion
  5350. to the first: it can hold other motor habits in check, and thereby, in
  5351. overcoming automatism, set consciousness free. We know what vast regions
  5352. in the human brain language occupies. The cerebral mechanisms that
  5353. correspond to the words have this in particular, that they can be made
  5354. to grapple with other mechanisms, those, for instance, that correspond
  5355. to the things themselves, or even be made to grapple with one another.
  5356. Meanwhile consciousness, which would have been dragged down and drowned
  5357. in the accomplishment of the act, is restored and set free.[77]
  5358. The difference must therefore be more radical than a superficial
  5359. examination would lead us to suppose. It is the difference between a
  5360. mechanism which engages the attention and a mechanism from which it can
  5361. be diverted. The primitive steam-engine, as Newcomen conceived it,
  5362. required the presence of a person exclusively employed to turn on and
  5363. off the taps, either to let the steam into the cylinder or to throw the
  5364. cold spray into it in order to condense the steam. It is said that a boy
  5365. employed on this work, and very tired of having to do it, got the idea
  5366. of tying the handles of the taps, with cords, to the beam of the engine.
  5367. Then the machine opened and closed the taps itself; it worked all alone.
  5368. Now, if an observer had compared the structure of this second machine
  5369. with that of the first without taking into account the two boys left to
  5370. watch over them, he would have found only a slight difference of
  5371. complexity. That is, indeed, all we can perceive when we look only at
  5372. the machines. But if we cast a glance at the two boys, we shall see that
  5373. whilst one is wholly taken up by the watching, the other is free to go
  5374. and play as he chooses, and that, from this point of view, the
  5375. difference between the two machines is radical, the first holding the
  5376. attention captive, the second setting it at liberty. A difference of the
  5377. same kind, we think, would be found between the brain of an animal and
  5378. the human brain.
  5379. If, now, we should wish to express this in terms of finality, we should
  5380. have to say that consciousness, after having been obliged, in order to
  5381. set itself free, to divide organization into two complementary parts,
  5382. vegetables on one hand and animals on the other, has sought an issue in
  5383. the double direction of instinct and of intelligence. It has not found
  5384. it with instinct, and it has not obtained it on the side of intelligence
  5385. except by a sudden leap from the animal to man. So that, in the last
  5386. analysis, man might be considered the reason for the existence of the
  5387. entire organization of life on our planet. But this would be only a
  5388. manner of speaking. There is, in reality, only a current of existence
  5389. and the opposing current; thence proceeds the whole evolution of life.
  5390. We must now grasp more closely the opposition of these two currents.
  5391. Perhaps we shall thus discover for them a common source. By this we
  5392. shall also, no doubt, penetrate the most obscure regions of metaphysics.
  5393. However, as the two directions we have to follow are clearly marked, in
  5394. intelligence on the one hand, in instinct and intuition on the other, we
  5395. are not afraid of straying. A survey of the evolution of life suggests
  5396. to us a certain conception of knowledge, and also a certain metaphysics,
  5397. which imply each other. Once made clear, this metaphysics and this
  5398. critique may throw some light, in their turn, on evolution as a whole.
  5399. FOOTNOTES:
  5400. [Footnote 51: This view of adaptation has been noted by M.F. Marin in a
  5401. remarkable article on the origin of species, "L'Origine des espèces"
  5402. (_Revue scientifique_, Nov. 1901, p. 580).]
  5403. [Footnote 52: De Saporta and Marion, _L'Évolution des cryptogames_,
  5404. 1881, p. 37.]
  5405. [Footnote 53: On fixation and parasitism in general, see the work of
  5406. Houssay, _La Forme et la vie_, Paris, 1900, pp. 721-807.]
  5407. [Footnote 54: Cope, _op. cit._ p. 76.]
  5408. [Footnote 55: Just as the plant, in certain cases, recovers the faculty
  5409. of moving actively which slumbers in it, so the animal, in exceptional
  5410. circumstances, can replace itself in the conditions of the vegetative
  5411. life and develop in itself an equivalent of the chlorophyllian function.
  5412. It appears, indeed, from recent experiments of Maria von Linden, that
  5413. the chrysalides and the caterpillars of certain lepidoptera, under the
  5414. influence of light, fix the carbon of the carbonic acid contained in the
  5415. atmosphere (M. von Linden, "L'Assimilation de l'acide carbonique par les
  5416. chrysalides de Lépidoptères," _C.R. de la Soc. de biologie_, 1905, pp.
  5417. 692 ff.).]
  5418. [Footnote 56: _Archives de physiologie_, 1892.]
  5419. [Footnote 57: De Manacéine, "Quelques observations expérimentales sur
  5420. l'influence de l'insomnie absolue" (_Arch. ital. de biologie_, t. xxi.,
  5421. 1894, pp. 322 ff.). Recently, analogous observations have been made on a
  5422. man who died of inanition after a fast of thirty-five days. See, on this
  5423. subject, in the _Année biologique_ of 1898, p. 338, the résumé of an
  5424. article (in Russian) by Tarakevitch and Stchasny.]
  5425. [Footnote 58: Cuvier said: "The nervous system is, at bottom, the whole
  5426. animal; the other systems are there only to serve it." ("Sur un nouveau
  5427. rapprochement à établir entre les classes qui composent le regne
  5428. animal," _Arch. du Muséum d'histoire naturelle_, Paris, 1812, pp.
  5429. 73-84.) Of course, it would be necessary to apply a great many
  5430. restrictions to this formula--for example, to allow for the cases of
  5431. degradation and retrogression in which the nervous system passes into
  5432. the background. And, moreover, with the nervous system must be included
  5433. the sensorial apparatus on the one hand and the motor on the other,
  5434. between which it acts as intermediary. Cf. Foster, art. "Physiology," in
  5435. the _Encyclopaedia Britannica_, Edinburgh, 1885, p. 17.]
  5436. [Footnote 59: See, on these different points, the work of Gaudry, _Essai
  5437. de paléontologie philosophique_, Paris, 1896, pp. 14-16 and 78-79.]
  5438. [Footnote 60: See, on this subject, Shaler, _The Individual_, New York,
  5439. 1900, pp. 118-125.]
  5440. [Footnote 61: This point is disputed by M. René Quinton, who regards the
  5441. carnivorous and ruminant mammals, as well as certain birds, as
  5442. subsequent to man (R. Quinton, _L'Eau de mer milieu organique_, Paris,
  5443. 1904, p. 435). We may say here that our general conclusions, although
  5444. very different from M. Quinton's, are not irreconcilable with them; for
  5445. if evolution has really been such as we represent it, the vertebrates
  5446. must have made an effort to maintain themselves in the most favorable
  5447. conditions of activity--the very conditions, indeed, which life had
  5448. chosen in the beginning.]
  5449. [Footnote 62: M. Paul Lacombe has laid great stress on the important
  5450. influence that great inventions have exercised on the evolution of
  5451. humanity (P. Lacombe, _De l'histoire considérée comme science_, Paris,
  5452. 1894. See, in particular, pp. 168-247).]
  5453. [Footnote 63: Bouvier, "La Nidification des abeilles à l'air libre"
  5454. (_C.R. de l'Ac. des sciences_, 7 mai 1906).]
  5455. [Footnote 64: Plato, _Phaedrus_, 265 E.]
  5456. [Footnote 65: We shall return to these points in the next chapter.]
  5457. [Footnote 66: We shall return to this point in chapter iii., p. 259.]
  5458. [Footnote 67: _Matière et mémoire_, chap. i.]
  5459. [Footnote 68: See the two works of Darwin, _Climbing Plants_ and _The
  5460. Fertilization of Orchids by Insects_.]
  5461. [Footnote 69: Buttel-Reepen, "Die phylogenetische Entstehung des
  5462. Bienenstaates" (_Biol. Centralblatt_, xxiii. 1903), p. 108 in
  5463. particular.]
  5464. [Footnote 70: Fabre, _Souvenirs entomologiques_, 3^e série, Paris, 1890,
  5465. pp. 1-69.]
  5466. [Footnote 71: Fabre, _Souvenirs entomologiques_, 1^{re} série, Paris,
  5467. 3^e édition, Paris, 1894, pp. 93 ff.]
  5468. [Footnote 72: Fabre, _Nouveaux souvenirs entomologiques_, Paris, 1882,
  5469. pp. 14 ff.]
  5470. [Footnote 73: Peckham, _Wasps, Solitary and Social_, Westminster, 1905,
  5471. pp. 28 ff.]
  5472. [Footnote 74: See, in particular, among recent works, Bethe, "Dürfen wir
  5473. den Ameisen und Bienen psychische Qualitäten zuschreiben?" (_Arch. f. d.
  5474. ges. Physiologie_, 1898), and Forel, "Un Aperçu de psychologie comparée"
  5475. (_Année psychologique_, 1895).]
  5476. [Footnote 75: _Matière et mémoire_, chaps. ii. and iii.]
  5477. [Footnote 76: "Le Paralogisme psycho-physiologique" (_Revue de
  5478. métaphysique_, Nov. 1904).]
  5479. [Footnote 77: A geologist whom we have already had occasion to cite,
  5480. N.S. Shaler, well says that "when we come to man, it seems as if we find
  5481. the ancient subjection of mind to body abolished, and the intellectual
  5482. parts develop with an extraordinary rapidity, the structure of the body
  5483. remaining identical in essentials" (Shaler, _The Interpretation of
  5484. Nature_, Boston, 1899, p. 187).]
  5485. CHAPTER III
  5486. ON THE MEANING OF LIFE--THE ORDER OF NATURE AND THE FORM OF INTELLIGENCE
  5487. In the course of our first chapter we traced a line of demarcation
  5488. between the inorganic and the organized, but we pointed out that the
  5489. division of unorganized matter into separate bodies is relative to our
  5490. senses and to our intellect, and that matter, looked at as an undivided
  5491. whole, must be a flux rather than a thing. In this we were preparing the
  5492. way for a reconciliation between the inert and the living.
  5493. On the other side, we have shown in our second chapter that the same
  5494. opposition is found again between instinct and intelligence, the one
  5495. turned to certain determinations of life, the other molded on the
  5496. configuration of matter. But instinct and intelligence, we have also
  5497. said, stand out from the same background, which, for want of a better
  5498. name, we may call consciousness in general, and which must be
  5499. coextensive with universal life. In this way, we have disclosed the
  5500. possibility of showing the genesis of intelligence in setting out from
  5501. general consciousness, which embraces it.
  5502. We are now, then, to attempt a genesis of intellect at the same time as
  5503. a genesis of material bodies--two enterprises that are evidently
  5504. correlative, if it be true that the main lines of our intellect mark out
  5505. the general form of our action on matter, and that the detail of matter
  5506. is ruled by the requirements of our action. Intellectuality and
  5507. materiality have been constituted, in detail, by reciprocal adaptation.
  5508. Both are derived from a wider and higher form of existence. It is there
  5509. that we must replace them, in order to see them issue forth.
  5510. Such an attempt may appear, at first, more daring than the boldest
  5511. speculations of metaphysicians. It claims to go further than psychology,
  5512. further than cosmology, further than traditional metaphysics; for
  5513. psychology, cosmology and metaphysics take intelligence, in all that is
  5514. essential to it, as given, instead of, as we now propose, engendering it
  5515. in its form and in its matter. The enterprise is in reality much more
  5516. modest, as we are going to show. But let us first say how it differs
  5517. from others.
  5518. To begin with psychology, we are not to believe that it _engenders_
  5519. intelligence when it follows the progressive development of it through
  5520. the animal series. Comparative psychology teaches us that the more an
  5521. animal is intelligent, the more it tends to reflect on the actions by
  5522. which it makes use of things, and thus to approximate to man. But its
  5523. actions have already by themselves adopted the principal lines of human
  5524. action; they have made out the same general directions in the material
  5525. world as we have; they depend upon the same objects bound together by
  5526. the same relations; so that animal intelligence, although it does not
  5527. form concepts properly so called, already moves in a conceptual
  5528. atmosphere. Absorbed at every instant by the actions it performs and the
  5529. attitudes it must adopt, drawn outward by them and so externalized in
  5530. relation to itself, it no doubt plays rather than thinks its ideas; this
  5531. play none the less already corresponds, in the main, to the general plan
  5532. of human intelligence.[78] To explain the intelligence of man by that of
  5533. the animal consists then simply in following the development of an
  5534. embryo of humanity into complete humanity. We show how a certain
  5535. direction has been followed further and further by beings more and more
  5536. intelligent. But the moment we admit the direction, intelligence is
  5537. given.
  5538. In a cosmogony like that of Spencer, intelligence is taken for granted,
  5539. as matter also at the same time. We are shown matter obeying laws,
  5540. objects connected with objects and facts with facts by constant
  5541. relations, consciousness receiving the imprint of these relations and
  5542. laws, and thus adopting the general configuration of nature and shaping
  5543. itself into intellect. But how can we fail to see that intelligence is
  5544. supposed when we admit objects and facts? _A priori_ and apart from any
  5545. hypothesis on the nature of the matter, it is evident that the
  5546. materiality of a body does not stop at the point at which we touch it: a
  5547. body is present wherever its influence is felt; its attractive force, to
  5548. speak only of that, is exerted on the sun, on the planets, perhaps on
  5549. the entire universe. The more physics advances, the more it effaces the
  5550. individuality of bodies and even of the particles into which the
  5551. scientific imagination began by decomposing them: bodies and corpuscles
  5552. tend to dissolve into a universal interaction. Our perceptions give us
  5553. the plan of our eventual action on things much more than that of things
  5554. themselves. The outlines we find in objects simply mark what we can
  5555. attain and modify in them. The lines we see traced through matter are
  5556. just the paths on which we are called to move. Outlines and paths have
  5557. declared themselves in the measure and proportion that consciousness has
  5558. prepared for action on unorganized matter--that is to say, in the
  5559. measure and proportion that intelligence has been formed. It is doubtful
  5560. whether animals built on a different plan--a mollusc or an insect, for
  5561. instance--cut matter up along the same articulations. It is not indeed
  5562. necessary that they should separate it into bodies at all. In order to
  5563. follow the indications of instinct, there is no need to perceive
  5564. _objects_, it is enough to distinguish _properties_. Intelligence, on
  5565. the contrary, even in its humblest form, already aims at getting matter
  5566. to act on matter. If on one side matter lends itself to a division into
  5567. active and passive bodies, or more simply into coexistent and distinct
  5568. fragments, it is from this side that intelligence will regard it; and
  5569. the more it busies itself with dividing, the more it will spread out in
  5570. space, in the form of extension adjoining extension, a matter that
  5571. undoubtedly itself has a tendency to spatiality, but whose parts are yet
  5572. in a state of reciprocal implication and interpenetration. Thus the same
  5573. movement by which the mind is brought to form itself into intellect,
  5574. that is to say, into distinct concepts, brings matter to break itself up
  5575. into objects excluding one another. _The more consciousness is
  5576. intellectualized, the more is matter spatialized._ So that the
  5577. evolutionist philosophy, when it imagines in space a matter cut up on
  5578. the very lines that our action will follow, has given itself in advance,
  5579. ready made, the intelligence of which it claims to show the genesis.
  5580. Metaphysics applies itself to a work of the same kind, though subtler
  5581. and more self-conscious, when it deduces _a priori_ the categories of
  5582. thought. It compresses intellect, reduces it to its quintessence, holds
  5583. it tight in a principle so simple that it can be thought empty: from
  5584. this principle we then draw out what we have virtually put into it. In
  5585. this way we may no doubt show the coherence of intelligence, define
  5586. intellect, give its formula, but we do not trace its genesis. An
  5587. enterprise like that of Fichte, although more philosophical than that of
  5588. Spencer, in that it pays more respect to the true order of things,
  5589. hardly leads us any further. Fichte takes thought in a concentrated
  5590. state, and expands it into reality; Spencer starts from external
  5591. reality, and condenses it into intellect. But, in the one case as in the
  5592. other, the intellect must be taken at the beginning as given--either
  5593. condensed or expanded, grasped in itself by a direct vision or perceived
  5594. by reflection in nature, as in a mirror.
  5595. The agreement of most philosophers on this point comes from the fact
  5596. that they are at one in affirming the unity of nature, and in
  5597. representing this unity under an abstract and geometrical form. Between
  5598. the organized and the unorganized they do not see and they will not see
  5599. the cleft. Some start from the inorganic, and, by compounding it with
  5600. itself, claim to form the living; others place life first, and proceed
  5601. towards matter by a skilfully managed _decrescendo_; but, for both,
  5602. there are only differences of _degree_ in nature--degrees of complexity
  5603. in the first hypothesis, of intensity in the second. Once this principle
  5604. is admitted, intelligence becomes as vast as reality; for it is
  5605. unquestionable that whatever is geometrical in things is entirely
  5606. accessible to human intelligence, and if the continuity between geometry
  5607. and the rest is perfect, all the rest must indeed be equally
  5608. intelligible, equally intelligent. Such is the postulate of most
  5609. systems. Any one can easily be convinced of this by comparing doctrines
  5610. that seem to have no common point, no common measure, those of Fichte
  5611. and Spencer for instance, two names that we happen to have just brought
  5612. together.
  5613. At the root of these speculations, then, there are the two convictions
  5614. correlative and complementary, that nature is one and that the function
  5615. of intellect is to embrace it in its entirety. The faculty of knowing
  5616. being supposed coextensive with the whole of experience, there can no
  5617. longer be any question of engendering it. It is already given, and we
  5618. merely have to use it, as we use our sight to take in the horizon. It
  5619. is true that opinions differ as to the value of the result. For some, it
  5620. is reality itself that the intellect embraces; for others, it is only a
  5621. phantom. But, phantom or reality, what intelligence grasps is thought to
  5622. be all that can be attained.
  5623. Hence the exaggerated confidence of philosophy in the powers of the
  5624. individual mind. Whether it is dogmatic or critical, whether it admits
  5625. the relativity of our knowledge or claims to be established within the
  5626. absolute, a philosophy is generally the work of a philosopher, a single
  5627. and unitary vision of the whole. It is to be taken or left.
  5628. More modest, and also alone capable of being completed and perfected, is
  5629. the philosophy we advocate. Human intelligence, as we represent it, is
  5630. not at all what Plato taught in the allegory of the cave. Its function
  5631. is not to look at passing shadows nor yet to turn itself round and
  5632. contemplate the glaring sun. It has something else to do. Harnessed,
  5633. like yoked oxen, to a heavy task, we feel the play of our muscles and
  5634. joints, the weight of the plow and the resistance of the soil. To act
  5635. and to know that we are acting, to come into touch with reality and even
  5636. to live it, but only in the measure in which it concerns the work that
  5637. is being accomplished and the furrow that is being plowed, such is the
  5638. function of human intelligence. Yet a beneficent fluid bathes us, whence
  5639. we draw the very force to labor and to live. From this ocean of life, in
  5640. which we are immersed, we are continually drawing something, and we feel
  5641. that our being, or at least the intellect that guides it, has been
  5642. formed therein by a kind of local concentration. Philosophy can only be
  5643. an effort to dissolve again into the Whole. Intelligence, reabsorbed
  5644. into its principle, may thus live back again its own genesis. But the
  5645. enterprise cannot be achieved in one stroke; it is necessarily
  5646. collective and progressive. It consists in an interchange of impressions
  5647. which, correcting and adding to each other, will end by expanding the
  5648. humanity in us and making us even transcend it.
  5649. But this method has against it the most inveterate habits of the mind.
  5650. It at once suggests the idea of a vicious circle. In vain, we shall be
  5651. told, you claim to go beyond intelligence: how can you do that except by
  5652. intelligence? All that is clear in your consciousness is intelligence.
  5653. You are inside your own thought; you cannot get out of it. Say, if you
  5654. like, that the intellect is capable of progress, that it will see more
  5655. and more clearly into a greater and greater number of things; but do not
  5656. speak of engendering it, for it is with your intellect itself that you
  5657. would have to do the work.
  5658. The objection presents itself naturally to the mind. But the same
  5659. reasoning would prove also the impossibility of acquiring any new habit.
  5660. It is of the essence of reasoning to shut us up in the circle of the
  5661. given. But action breaks the circle. If we had never seen a man swim, we
  5662. might say that swimming is an impossible thing, inasmuch as, to learn to
  5663. swim, we must begin by holding ourselves up in the water and,
  5664. consequently, already know how to swim. Reasoning, in fact, always nails
  5665. us down to the solid ground. But if, quite simply, I throw myself into
  5666. the water without fear, I may keep myself up well enough at first by
  5667. merely struggling, and gradually adapt myself to the new environment: I
  5668. shall thus have learnt to swim. So, in theory, there is a kind of
  5669. absurdity in trying to know otherwise than by intelligence; but if the
  5670. risk be frankly accepted, action will perhaps cut the knot that
  5671. reasoning has tied and will not unloose.
  5672. Besides, the risk will appear to grow less, the more our point of view
  5673. is adopted. We have shown that intellect has detached itself from a
  5674. vastly wider reality, but that there has never been a clean cut between
  5675. the two; all around conceptual thought there remains an indistinct
  5676. fringe which recalls its origin. And further we compared the intellect
  5677. to a solid nucleus formed by means of condensation. This nucleus does
  5678. not differ radically from the fluid surrounding it. It can only be
  5679. reabsorbed in it because it is made of the same substance. He who throws
  5680. himself into the water, having known only the resistance of the solid
  5681. earth, will immediately be drowned if he does not struggle against the
  5682. fluidity of the new environment: he must perforce still cling to that
  5683. solidity, so to speak, which even water presents. Only on this condition
  5684. can he get used to the fluid's fluidity. So of our thought, when it has
  5685. decided to make the leap.
  5686. But leap it must, that is, leave its own environment. Reason, reasoning
  5687. on its powers, will never succeed in extending them, though the
  5688. extension would not appear at all unreasonable once it were
  5689. accomplished. Thousands and thousands of variations on the theme of
  5690. walking will never yield a rule for swimming: come, enter the water, and
  5691. when you know how to swim, you will understand how the mechanism of
  5692. swimming is connected with that of walking. Swimming is an extension of
  5693. walking, but walking would never have pushed you on to swimming. So you
  5694. may speculate as intelligently as you will on the mechanism of
  5695. intelligence; you will never, by this method, succeed in going beyond
  5696. it. You may get something more complex, but not something higher nor
  5697. even something different. You must take things by storm: you must thrust
  5698. intelligence outside itself by an act of will.
  5699. So the vicious circle is only apparent. It is, on the contrary, real, we
  5700. think, in every other method of philosophy. This we must try to show in
  5701. a few words, if only to prove that philosophy cannot and must not
  5702. accept the relation established by pure intellectualism between the
  5703. theory of knowledge and the theory of the known, between metaphysics and
  5704. science.
  5705. * * * * *
  5706. At first sight, it may seem prudent to leave the consideration of facts
  5707. to positive science, to let physics and chemistry busy themselves with
  5708. matter, the biological and psychological sciences with life. The task of
  5709. the philosopher is then clearly defined. He takes facts and laws from
  5710. the scientists' hand; and whether he tries to go beyond them in order to
  5711. reach their deeper causes, or whether he thinks it impossible to go
  5712. further and even proves it by the analysis of scientific knowledge, in
  5713. both cases he has for the facts and relations, handed over by science,
  5714. the sort of respect that is due to a final verdict. To this knowledge he
  5715. adds a critique of the faculty of knowing, and also, if he thinks
  5716. proper, a metaphysic; but the _matter_ of knowledge he regards as the
  5717. affair of science and not of philosophy.
  5718. But how does he fail to see that the real result of this so-called
  5719. division of labor is to mix up everything and confuse everything? The
  5720. metaphysic or the critique that the philosopher has reserved for himself
  5721. he has to receive, ready-made, from positive science, it being already
  5722. contained in the descriptions and analyses, the whole care of which he
  5723. left to the scientists. For not having wished to intervene, at the
  5724. beginning, in questions of fact, he finds himself reduced, in questions
  5725. of principle, to formulating purely and simply in more precise terms the
  5726. unconscious and consequently inconsistent metaphysic and critique which
  5727. the very attitude of science to reality marks out. Let us not be
  5728. deceived by an apparent analogy between natural things and human things.
  5729. Here we are not in the judiciary domain, where the description of fact
  5730. and the judgment on the fact are two distinct things, distinct for the
  5731. very simple reason that above the fact, and independent of it, there is
  5732. a law promulgated by a legislator. Here the laws are internal to the
  5733. facts and relative to the lines that have been followed in cutting the
  5734. real into distinct facts. We cannot describe the outward appearance of
  5735. the object without prejudging its inner nature and its organization.
  5736. Form is no longer entirely isolable from matter, and he who has begun by
  5737. reserving to philosophy questions of principle, and who has thereby
  5738. tried to put philosophy above the sciences, as a "court of cassation" is
  5739. above the courts of assizes and of appeal, will gradually come to make
  5740. no more of philosophy than a registration court, charged at most with
  5741. wording more precisely the sentences that are brought to it, pronounced
  5742. and irrevocable.
  5743. Positive science is, in fact, a work of pure intellect. Now, whether our
  5744. conception of the intellect be accepted or rejected, there is one point
  5745. on which everybody will agree with us, and that is that the intellect is
  5746. at home in the presence of unorganized matter. This matter it makes use
  5747. of more and more by mechanical inventions, and mechanical inventions
  5748. become the easier to it the more it thinks matter as mechanism. The
  5749. intellect bears within itself, in the form of natural logic, a latent
  5750. geometrism that is set free in the measure and proportion that the
  5751. intellect penetrates into the inner nature of inert matter. Intelligence
  5752. is in tune with this matter, and that is why the physics and metaphysics
  5753. of inert matter are so near each other. Now, when the intellect
  5754. undertakes the study of life, it necessarily treats the living like the
  5755. inert, applying the same forms to this new object, carrying over into
  5756. this new field the same habits that have succeeded so well in the old;
  5757. and it is right to do so, for only on such terms does the living offer
  5758. to our action the same hold as inert matter. But the truth we thus
  5759. arrive at becomes altogether relative to our faculty of action. It is no
  5760. more than a _symbolic_ verity. It cannot have the same value as the
  5761. physical verity, being only an extension of physics to an object which
  5762. we are _a priori_ agreed to look at only in its external aspect. The
  5763. duty of philosophy should be to intervene here actively, to examine the
  5764. living without any reservation as to practical utility, by freeing
  5765. itself from forms and habits that are strictly intellectual. Its own
  5766. special object is to speculate, that is to say, to see; its attitude
  5767. toward the living should not be that of science, which aims only at
  5768. action, and which, being able to act only by means of inert matter,
  5769. presents to itself the rest of reality in this single respect. What must
  5770. the result be, if it leave biological and psychological facts to
  5771. positive science alone, as it has left, and rightly left, physical
  5772. facts? It will accept _a priori_ a mechanistic conception of all nature,
  5773. a conception unreflected and even unconscious, the outcome of the
  5774. material need. It will _a priori_ accept the doctrine of the simple
  5775. unity of knowledge and of the abstract unity of nature.
  5776. The moment it does so, its fate is sealed. The philosopher has no longer
  5777. any choice save between a metaphysical dogmatism and a metaphysical
  5778. skepticism, both of which rest, at bottom, on the same postulate, and
  5779. neither of which adds anything to positive science. He may hypostasize
  5780. the unity of nature, or, what comes to the same thing, the unity of
  5781. science, in a being who is nothing since he does nothing, an ineffectual
  5782. God who simply sums up in himself all the given; or in an eternal Matter
  5783. from whose womb have been poured out the properties of things and the
  5784. laws of nature; or, again, in a pure Form which endeavors to seize an
  5785. unseizable multiplicity, and which is, as we will, the form of nature
  5786. or the form of thought. All these philosophies tell us, in their
  5787. different languages, that science is right to treat the living as the
  5788. inert, and that there is no difference of value, no distinction to be
  5789. made between the results which intellect arrives at in applying its
  5790. categories, whether it rests on inert matter or attacks life.
  5791. In many cases, however, we feel the frame cracking. But as we did not
  5792. begin by distinguishing between the inert and the living, the one
  5793. adapted in advance to the frame in which we insert it, the other
  5794. incapable of being held in the frame otherwise than by a convention
  5795. which eliminates from it all that is essential, we find ourselves, in
  5796. the end, reduced to regarding everything the frame contains with equal
  5797. suspicion. To a metaphysical dogmatism, which has erected into an
  5798. absolute the factitious unity of science, there succeeds a skepticism or
  5799. a relativism that universalizes and extends to all the results of
  5800. science the artificial character of some among them. So philosophy
  5801. swings to and fro between the doctrine that regards absolute reality as
  5802. unknowable and that which, in the idea it gives us of this reality, says
  5803. nothing more than science has said. For having wished to prevent all
  5804. conflict between science and philosophy, we have sacrificed philosophy
  5805. without any appreciable gain to science. And for having tried to avoid
  5806. the seeming vicious circle which consists in using the intellect to
  5807. transcend the intellect, we find ourselves turning in a real circle,
  5808. that which consists in laboriously rediscovering by metaphysics a unity
  5809. that we began by positing _a priori_, a unity that we admitted blindly
  5810. and unconsciously by the very act of abandoning the whole of experience
  5811. to science and the whole of reality to the pure understanding.
  5812. Let us begin, on the contrary, by tracing a line of demarcation between
  5813. the inert and the living. We shall find that the inert enters naturally
  5814. into the frames of the intellect, but that the living is adapted to
  5815. these frames only artificially, so that we must adopt a special attitude
  5816. towards it and examine it with other eyes than those of positive
  5817. science. Philosophy, then, invades the domain of experience. She busies
  5818. herself with many things which hitherto have not concerned her. Science,
  5819. theory of knowledge, and metaphysics find themselves on the same ground.
  5820. At first there may be a certain confusion. All three may think they have
  5821. lost something. But all three will profit from the meeting.
  5822. Positive science, indeed, may pride itself on the uniform value
  5823. attributed to its affirmations in the whole field of experience. But, if
  5824. they are all placed on the same footing, they are all tainted with the
  5825. same relativity. It is not so, if we begin by making the distinction
  5826. which, in our view, is forced upon us. The understanding is at home in
  5827. the domain of unorganized matter. On this matter human action is
  5828. naturally exercised; and action, as we said above, cannot be set in
  5829. motion in the unreal. Thus, of physics--so long as we are considering
  5830. only its general form and not the particular cutting out of matter in
  5831. which it is manifested--we may say that it touches the absolute. On the
  5832. contrary, it is by accident--chance or convention, as you please--that
  5833. science obtains a hold on the living analogous to the hold it has on
  5834. matter. Here the use of conceptual frames is no longer natural. I do not
  5835. wish to say that it is not legitimate, in the scientific meaning of the
  5836. term. If science is to extend our action on things, and if we can act
  5837. only with inert matter for instrument, science can and must continue to
  5838. treat the living as it has treated the inert. But, in doing so, it must
  5839. be understood that the further it penetrates the depths of _life_, the
  5840. more symbolic, the more relative to the contingencies of action, the
  5841. knowledge it supplies to us becomes. On this new ground philosophy ought
  5842. then to follow science, in order to superpose on scientific truth a
  5843. knowledge of another kind, which may be called metaphysical. Thus
  5844. combined, all our knowledge, both scientific and metaphysical, is
  5845. heightened. In the absolute we live and move and have our being. The
  5846. knowledge we possess of it is incomplete, no doubt, but not external or
  5847. relative. It is reality itself, in the profoundest meaning of the word,
  5848. that we reach by the combined and progressive development of science and
  5849. of philosophy.
  5850. Thus, in renouncing the factitious unity which the understanding imposes
  5851. on nature from outside, we shall perhaps find its true, inward and
  5852. living unity. For the effort we make to transcend the pure understanding
  5853. introduces us into that more vast something out of which our
  5854. understanding is cut, and from which it has detached itself. And, as
  5855. matter is determined by intelligence, as there is between them an
  5856. evident agreement, we cannot make the genesis of the one without making
  5857. the genesis of the other. An identical process must have cut out matter
  5858. and the intellect, at the same time, from a stuff that contained both.
  5859. Into this reality we shall get back more and more completely, in
  5860. proportion as we compel ourselves to transcend pure intelligence.
  5861. * * * * *
  5862. Let us then concentrate attention on that which we have that is at the
  5863. same time the most removed from externality and the least penetrated
  5864. with intellectuality. Let us seek, in the depths of our experience, the
  5865. point where we feel ourselves most intimately within our own life. It is
  5866. into pure duration that we then plunge back, a duration in which the
  5867. past, always moving on, is swelling unceasingly with a present that is
  5868. absolutely new. But, at the same time, we feel the spring of our will
  5869. strained to its utmost limit. We must, by a strong recoil of our
  5870. personality on itself, gather up our past which is slipping away, in
  5871. order to thrust it, compact and undivided, into a present which it will
  5872. create by entering. Rare indeed are the moments when we are
  5873. self-possessed to this extent: it is then that our actions are truly
  5874. free. And even at these moments we do not completely possess ourselves.
  5875. Our feeling of duration, I should say the actual coinciding of ourself
  5876. with itself, admits of degrees. But the more the feeling is deep and the
  5877. coincidence complete, the more the life in which it replaces us absorbs
  5878. intellectuality by transcending it. For the natural function of the
  5879. intellect is to bind like to like, and it is only facts that can be
  5880. repeated that are entirely adaptable to intellectual conceptions. Now,
  5881. our intellect does undoubtedly grasp the real moments of real duration
  5882. after they are past; we do so by reconstituting the new state of
  5883. consciousness out of a series of views taken of it from the outside,
  5884. each of which resembles as much as possible something already known; in
  5885. this sense we may say that the state of consciousness contains
  5886. intellectuality implicitly. Yet the state of consciousness overflows the
  5887. intellect; it is indeed incommensurable with the intellect, being itself
  5888. indivisible and new.
  5889. Now let us relax the strain, let us interrupt the effort to crowd as
  5890. much as possible of the past into the present. If the relaxation were
  5891. complete, there would no longer be either memory or will--which amounts
  5892. to saying that, in fact, we never do fall into this absolute passivity,
  5893. any more than we can make ourselves absolutely free. But, in the limit,
  5894. we get a glimpse of an existence made of a present which recommences
  5895. unceasingly--devoid of real duration, nothing but the instantaneous
  5896. which dies and is born again endlessly. Is the existence of matter of
  5897. this nature? Not altogether, for analysis resolves it into elementary
  5898. vibrations, the shortest of which are of very slight duration, almost
  5899. vanishing, but not nothing. It may be presumed, nevertheless, that
  5900. physical existence inclines in this second direction, as psychical
  5901. existence in the first.
  5902. Behind "spirituality" on the one hand, and "materiality" with
  5903. intellectuality on the other, there are then two processes opposite in
  5904. their direction, and we pass from the first to the second by way of
  5905. inversion, or perhaps even by simple interruption, if it is true that
  5906. inversion and interruption are two terms which in this case must be held
  5907. to be synonymous, as we shall show at more length later on. This
  5908. presumption is confirmed when we consider things from the point of view
  5909. of extension, and no longer from that of duration alone.
  5910. The more we succeed in making ourselves conscious of our progress in
  5911. pure duration, the more we feel the different parts of our being enter
  5912. into each other, and our whole personality concentrate itself in a
  5913. point, or rather a sharp edge, pressed against the future and cutting
  5914. into it unceasingly. It is in this that life and action are free. But
  5915. suppose we let ourselves go and, instead of acting, dream. At once the
  5916. self is scattered; our past, which till then was gathered together into
  5917. the indivisible impulsion it communicated to us, is broken up into a
  5918. thousand recollections made external to one another. They give up
  5919. interpenetrating in the degree that they become fixed. Our personality
  5920. thus descends in the direction of space. It coasts around it continually
  5921. in sensation. We will not dwell here on a point we have studied
  5922. elsewhere. Let us merely recall that extension admits of degrees, that
  5923. all sensation is extensive in a certain measure, and that the idea of
  5924. unextended sensations, artificially localized in space, is a mere view
  5925. of the mind, suggested by an unconscious metaphysic much more than by
  5926. psychological observation.
  5927. No doubt we make only the first steps in the direction of the extended,
  5928. even when we let ourselves go as much as we can. But suppose for a
  5929. moment that matter consists in this very movement pushed further, and
  5930. that physics is simply psychics inverted. We shall now understand why
  5931. the mind feels at its ease, moves about naturally in space, when matter
  5932. suggests the more distinct idea of it. This space it already possessed
  5933. as an implicit idea in its own eventual _detension_, that is to say, of
  5934. its own possible _extension_. The mind finds space in things, but could
  5935. have got it without them if it had had imagination strong enough to push
  5936. the inversion of its own natural movement to the end. On the other hand,
  5937. we are able to explain how matter accentuates still more its
  5938. materiality, when viewed by the mind. Matter, at first, aided mind to
  5939. run down its own incline; it gave the impulsion. But, the impulsion once
  5940. received, mind continues its course. The idea that it forms of _pure_
  5941. space is only the _schema_ of the limit at which this movement would
  5942. end. Once in possession of the form of space, mind uses it like a net
  5943. with meshes that can be made and unmade at will, which, thrown over
  5944. matter, divides it as the needs of our action demand. Thus, the space of
  5945. our geometry and the spatiality of things are mutually engendered by the
  5946. reciprocal action and reaction of two terms which are essentially the
  5947. same, but which move each in the direction inverse of the other. Neither
  5948. is space so foreign to our nature as we imagine, nor is matter as
  5949. completely extended in space as our senses and intellect represent it.
  5950. We have treated of the first point elsewhere. As to the second, we will
  5951. limit ourselves to pointing out that perfect spatiality would consist in
  5952. a perfect externality of parts in their relation to one another, that is
  5953. to say, in a complete reciprocal independence. Now, there is no material
  5954. point that does not act on every other material point. When we observe
  5955. that a thing really is there where it _acts_, we shall be led to say (as
  5956. Faraday[79] was) that all the atoms interpenetrate and that each of them
  5957. fills the world. On such a hypothesis, the atom or, more generally, the
  5958. material point, becomes simply a view of the mind, a view which we come
  5959. to take when we continue far enough the work (wholly relative to our
  5960. faculty of acting) by which we subdivide matter into bodies. Yet it is
  5961. undeniable that matter lends itself to this subdivision, and that, in
  5962. supposing it breakable into parts external to one another, we are
  5963. constructing a science sufficiently representative of the real. It is
  5964. undeniable that if there be no entirely isolated system, yet science
  5965. finds means of cutting up the universe into systems relatively
  5966. independent of each other, and commits no appreciable error in doing so.
  5967. What else can this mean but that matter _extends_ itself in space
  5968. without being absolutely _extended_ therein, and that in regarding
  5969. matter as decomposable into isolated systems, in attributing to it quite
  5970. distinct elements which change in relation to each other without
  5971. changing in themselves (which are "displaced," shall we say, without
  5972. being "altered"), in short, in conferring on matter the properties of
  5973. pure space, we are transporting ourselves to the terminal point of the
  5974. movement of which matter simply indicates the direction?
  5975. What the _Transcendental Aesthetic_ of Kant appears to have established
  5976. once for all is that extension is not a material attribute of the same
  5977. kind as others. We cannot reason indefinitely on the notions of heat,
  5978. color, or weight: in order to know the modalities of weight or of heat,
  5979. we must have recourse to experience. Not so of the notion of space.
  5980. Supposing even that it is given empirically by sight and touch (and Kant
  5981. has not questioned the fact) there is this about it that is remarkable
  5982. that our mind, speculating on it with its own powers alone, cuts out in
  5983. it, _a priori_, figures whose properties we determine _a priori_:
  5984. experience, with which we have not kept in touch, yet follows us through
  5985. the infinite complications of our reasonings and invariably justifies
  5986. them. That is the fact. Kant has set it in clear light. But the
  5987. explanation of the fact, we believe, must be sought in a different
  5988. direction to that which Kant followed.
  5989. Intelligence, as Kant represents it to us, is bathed in an atmosphere of
  5990. spatiality to which it is as inseparably united as the living body to
  5991. the air it breathes. Our perceptions reach us only after having passed
  5992. through this atmosphere. They have been impregnated in advance by our
  5993. geometry, so that our faculty of thinking only finds again in matter the
  5994. mathematical properties which our faculty of perceiving has already
  5995. deposed there. We are assured, therefore, of seeing matter yield itself
  5996. with docility to our reasonings; but this matter, in all that it has
  5997. that is intelligible, is our own work; of the reality "in itself" we
  5998. know nothing and never shall know anything, since we only get its
  5999. refraction through the forms of our faculty of perceiving. So that if we
  6000. claim to affirm something of it, at once there rises the contrary
  6001. affirmation, equally demonstrable, equally plausible. The ideality of
  6002. space is proved directly by the analysis of knowledge indirectly by the
  6003. antinomies to which the opposite theory leads. Such is the governing
  6004. idea of the Kantian criticism. It has inspired Kant with a peremptory
  6005. refutation of "empiricist" theories of knowledge. It is, in our opinion,
  6006. definitive in what it denies. But, in what it affirms, does it give us
  6007. the solution of the problem?
  6008. With Kant, space is given as a ready-made form of our perceptive
  6009. faculty--a veritable _deus ex machina_, of which we see neither how it
  6010. arises, nor why it is what it is rather than anything else.
  6011. "Things-in-themselves" are also given, of which he claims that we can
  6012. know nothing: by what right, then, can he affirm their existence, even
  6013. as "problematic"? If the unknowable reality projects into our perceptive
  6014. faculty a "sensuous manifold" capable of fitting into it exactly, is it
  6015. not, by that very fact, in part known? And when we examine this exact
  6016. fitting, shall we not be led, in one point at least, to suppose a
  6017. pre-established harmony between things and our mind--an idle hypothesis,
  6018. which Kant was right in wishing to avoid? At bottom, it is for not
  6019. having distinguished degrees in spatiality that he has had to take space
  6020. ready-made as given--whence the question how the "sensuous manifold" is
  6021. adapted to it. It is for the same reason that he has supposed matter
  6022. wholly developed into parts absolutely external to one another;--whence
  6023. antinomies, of which we may plainly see that the thesis and antithesis
  6024. suppose the perfect coincidence of matter with geometrical space, but
  6025. which vanish the moment we cease to extend to matter what is true only
  6026. of pure space. Whence, finally, the conclusion that there are three
  6027. alternatives, and three only, among which to choose a theory of
  6028. knowledge: either the mind is determined by things, or things are
  6029. determined by the mind, or between mind and things we must suppose a
  6030. mysterious agreement.
  6031. But the truth is that there is a fourth, which does not seem to have
  6032. occurred to Kant--in the first place because he did not think that the
  6033. mind overflowed the intellect, and in the second place (and this is at
  6034. bottom the same thing) because he did not attribute to duration an
  6035. absolute existence, having put time, _a priori_, on the same plane as
  6036. space. This alternative consists, first of all, in regarding the
  6037. intellect as a special function of the mind, essentially turned toward
  6038. inert matter; then in saying that neither does matter determine the form
  6039. of the intellect, nor does the intellect impose its form on matter, nor
  6040. have matter and intellect been regulated in regard to one another by we
  6041. know not what pre-established harmony, but that intellect and matter
  6042. have progressively adapted themselves one to the other in order to
  6043. attain at last a common form. _This adaptation has, moreover, been
  6044. brought about quite naturally, because it is the same inversion of the
  6045. same movement which creates at once the intellectuality of mind and the
  6046. materiality of things._
  6047. From this point of view the knowledge of matter that our perception on
  6048. one hand and science on the other give to us appears, no doubt, as
  6049. approximative, but not as relative. Our perception, whose rôle it is to
  6050. hold up a light to our actions, works a dividing up of matter that is
  6051. always too sharply defined, always subordinated to practical needs,
  6052. consequently always requiring revision. Our science, which aspires to
  6053. the mathematical form, over-accentuates the spatiality of matter; its
  6054. formulae are, in general, too precise, and ever need remaking. For a
  6055. scientific theory to be final, the mind would have to embrace the
  6056. totality of things in block and place each thing in its exact relation
  6057. to every other thing; but in reality we are obliged to consider problems
  6058. one by one, in terms which are, for that very reason, provisional, so
  6059. that the solution of each problem will have to be corrected
  6060. indefinitely by the solution that will be given to the problems that
  6061. will follow: thus, science as a whole is relative to the particular
  6062. order in which the problems happen to have been put. It is in this
  6063. meaning, and to this degree, that science must be regarded as
  6064. conventional. But it is a conventionality of fact so to speak, and not
  6065. of right. In principle, positive science bears on reality itself,
  6066. provided it does not overstep the limits of its own domain, which is
  6067. inert matter.
  6068. Scientific knowledge, thus regarded, rises to a higher plane. In return,
  6069. the theory of knowledge becomes an infinitely difficult enterprise, and
  6070. which passes the powers of the intellect alone. It is not enough to
  6071. determine, by careful analysis, the categories of thought; we must
  6072. engender them. As regards space, we must, by an effort of mind _sui
  6073. generis_, follow the progression or rather the regression of the
  6074. extra-spatial degrading itself into spatiality. When we make ourselves
  6075. self-conscious in the highest possible degree and then let ourselves
  6076. fall back little by little, we get the feeling of extension: we have an
  6077. extension of the self into recollections that are fixed and external to
  6078. one another, in place of the tension it possessed as an indivisible
  6079. active will. But this is only a beginning. Our consciousness, sketching
  6080. the movement, shows us its direction and reveals to us the possibility
  6081. of continuing it to the end; but consciousness itself does not go so
  6082. far. Now, on the other hand, if we consider matter, which seems to us at
  6083. first coincident with space, we find that the more our attention is
  6084. fixed on it, the more the parts which we said were laid side by side
  6085. enter into each other, each of them undergoing the action of the whole,
  6086. which is consequently somehow present in it. Thus, although matter
  6087. stretches itself out in the direction of space, it does not completely
  6088. attain it; whence we may conclude that it only carries very much
  6089. further the movement that consciousness is able to sketch within us in
  6090. its nascent state. We hold, therefore, the two ends of the chain, though
  6091. we do not succeed in seizing the intermediate links. Will they always
  6092. escape us? We must remember that philosophy, as we define it, has not
  6093. yet become completely conscious of itself. Physics understands its rôle
  6094. when it pushes matter in the direction of spatiality; but has
  6095. metaphysics understood its rôle when it has simply trodden in the steps
  6096. of physics, in the chimerical hope of going further in the same
  6097. direction? Should not its own task be, on the contrary, to remount the
  6098. incline that physics descends, to bring back matter to its origins, and
  6099. to build up progressively a cosmology which would be, so to speak, a
  6100. reversed psychology? All that which seems _positive_ to the physicist
  6101. and to the geometrician would become, from this new point of view, an
  6102. interruption or inversion of the true positivity, which would have to be
  6103. defined in psychological terms.
  6104. * * * * *
  6105. When we consider the admirable order of mathematics, the perfect
  6106. agreement of the objects it deals with, the immanent logic in numbers
  6107. and figures, our certainty of always getting the same conclusion,
  6108. however diverse and complex our reasonings on the same subject, we
  6109. hesitate to see in properties apparently so positive a system of
  6110. negations, the absence rather than the presence of a true reality. But
  6111. we must not forget that our intellect, which finds this order and
  6112. wonders at it, is directed in the same line of movement that leads to
  6113. the materiality and spatiality of its object. The more complexity the
  6114. intellect puts into its object by analyzing it, the more complex is the
  6115. order it finds there. And this order and this complexity necessarily
  6116. appear to the intellect as a positive reality, since reality and
  6117. intellectuality are turned in the same direction.
  6118. When a poet reads me his verses, I can interest myself enough in him to
  6119. enter into his thought, put myself into his feelings, live over again
  6120. the simple state he has broken into phrases and words. I sympathize then
  6121. with his inspiration, I follow it with a continuous movement which is,
  6122. like the inspiration itself, an undivided act. Now, I need only relax my
  6123. attention, let go the tension that there is in me, for the sounds,
  6124. hitherto swallowed up in the sense, to appear to me distinctly, one by
  6125. one, in their materiality. For this I have not to do anything; it is
  6126. enough to withdraw something. In proportion as I let myself go, the
  6127. successive sounds will become the more individualized; as the phrases
  6128. were broken into words, so the words will scan in syllables which I
  6129. shall perceive one after another. Let me go farther still in the
  6130. direction of dream: the letters themselves will become loose and will be
  6131. seen to dance along, hand in hand, on some fantastic sheet of paper. I
  6132. shall then admire the precision of the interweavings, the marvelous
  6133. order of the procession, the exact insertion of the letters into the
  6134. syllables, of the syllables into the words and of the words into the
  6135. sentences. The farther I pursue this quite negative direction of
  6136. relaxation, the more extension and complexity I shall create; and the
  6137. more the complexity in its turn increases, the more admirable will seem
  6138. to be the order which continues to reign, undisturbed, among the
  6139. elements. Yet this complexity and extension represent nothing positive;
  6140. they express a deficiency of will. And, on the other hand, the order
  6141. must grow with the complexity, since it is only an aspect of it. The
  6142. more we perceive, symbolically, parts in an indivisible whole, the more
  6143. the number of the relations that the parts have between themselves
  6144. necessarily increases, since the same undividedness of the real whole
  6145. continues to hover over the growing multiplicity of the symbolic
  6146. elements into which the scattering of the attention has decomposed it. A
  6147. comparison of this kind will enable us to understand, in some measure,
  6148. how the same suppression of positive reality, the same inversion of a
  6149. certain original movement, can create at once extension in space and the
  6150. admirable order which mathematics finds there. There is, of course, this
  6151. difference between the two cases, that words and letters have been
  6152. invented by a positive effort of humanity, while space arises
  6153. automatically, as the remainder of a subtraction arises once the two
  6154. numbers are posited.[80] But, in the one case as in the other, the
  6155. infinite complexity of the parts and their perfect coördination among
  6156. themselves are created at one and the same time by an inversion which
  6157. is, at bottom, an interruption, that is to say, a diminution of positive
  6158. reality.
  6159. * * * * *
  6160. All the operations of our intellect tend to geometry, as to the goal
  6161. where they find their perfect fulfilment. But, as geometry is
  6162. necessarily prior to them (since these operations have not as their end
  6163. to construct space and cannot do otherwise than take it as given) it is
  6164. evident that it is a latent geometry, immanent in our idea of space,
  6165. which is the main spring of our intellect and the cause of its working.
  6166. We shall be convinced of this if we consider the two essential functions
  6167. of intellect, the faculty of deduction and that of induction.
  6168. Let us begin with deduction. The same movement by which I trace a figure
  6169. in space engenders its properties: they are visible and tangible in the
  6170. movement itself; I feel, I see in space the relation of the definition
  6171. to its consequences, of the premisses to the conclusion. All the other
  6172. concepts of which experience suggests the idea to me are only in part
  6173. constructible _a priori_; the definition of them is therefore imperfect,
  6174. and the deductions into which these concepts enter, however closely the
  6175. conclusion is linked to the premisses, participate in this imperfection.
  6176. But when I trace roughly in the sand the base of a triangle, as I begin
  6177. to form the two angles at the base, I know positively, and understand
  6178. absolutely, that if these two angles are equal the sides will be equal
  6179. also, the figure being then able to be turned over on itself without
  6180. there being any change whatever. I know it before I have learnt
  6181. geometry. Thus, prior to the science of geometry, there is a natural
  6182. geometry whose clearness and evidence surpass the clearness and evidence
  6183. of other deductions. Now, these other deductions bear on qualities, and
  6184. not on magnitudes purely. They are, then, likely to have been formed on
  6185. the model of the first, and to borrow their force from the fact that,
  6186. behind quality, we see magnitude vaguely showing through. We may notice,
  6187. as a fact, that questions of situation and of magnitude are the first
  6188. that present themselves to our activity, those which intelligence
  6189. externalized in action resolves even before reflective intelligence has
  6190. appeared. The savage understands better than the civilized man how to
  6191. judge distances, to determine a direction, to retrace by memory the
  6192. often complicated plan of the road he has traveled, and so to return in
  6193. a straight line to his starting-point.[81] If the animal does not deduce
  6194. explicitly, if he does not form explicit concepts, neither does he form
  6195. the idea of a homogeneous space. You cannot present this space to
  6196. yourself without introducing, in the same act, a virtual geometry which
  6197. will, of itself, degrade itself into logic. All the repugnance that
  6198. philosophers manifest towards this manner of regarding things comes from
  6199. this, that the logical work of the intellect represents to their eyes a
  6200. positive spiritual effort. But, if we understand by spirituality a
  6201. progress to ever new creations, to conclusions incommensurable with the
  6202. premisses and indeterminable by relation to them, we must say of an idea
  6203. that moves among relations of necessary determination, through premisses
  6204. which contain their conclusion in advance, that it follows the inverse
  6205. direction, that of materiality. What appears, from the point of view of
  6206. the intellect, as an effort, is in itself a letting go. And while, from
  6207. the point of view of the intellect, there is a _petitio principii_ in
  6208. making geometry arise automatically from space, and logic from
  6209. geometry--on the contrary, if space is the ultimate goal of the mind's
  6210. movement of _detension_, space cannot be given without positing also
  6211. logic and geometry, which are along the course of the movement of which
  6212. pure spatial intuition is the goal.
  6213. It has not been enough noticed how feeble is the reach of deduction in
  6214. the psychological and moral sciences. From a proposition verified by
  6215. facts, verifiable consequences can here be drawn only up to a certain
  6216. point, only in a certain measure. Very soon appeal has to be made to
  6217. common sense, that is to say, to the continuous experience of the real,
  6218. in order to inflect the consequences deduced and bend them along the
  6219. sinuosities of life. Deduction succeeds in things moral only
  6220. metaphorically, so to speak, and just in the measure in which the moral
  6221. is transposable into the physical, I should say translatable into
  6222. spatial symbols. The metaphor never goes very far, any more than a curve
  6223. can long be confused with its tangent. Must we not be struck by this
  6224. feebleness of deduction as something very strange and even paradoxical?
  6225. Here is a pure operation of the mind, accomplished solely by the power
  6226. of the mind. It seems that, if anywhere it should feel at home and
  6227. evolve at ease, it would be among the things of the mind, in the domain
  6228. of the mind. Not at all; it is there that it is immediately at the end
  6229. of its tether. On the contrary, in geometry, in astronomy, in physics,
  6230. where we have to do with things external to us, deduction is
  6231. all-powerful! Observation and experience are undoubtedly necessary in
  6232. these sciences to arrive at the principle, that is, to discover the
  6233. aspect under which things must be regarded; but, strictly speaking, we
  6234. might, by good luck, have hit upon it at once; and, as soon as we
  6235. possess this principle, we may draw from it, at any length, consequences
  6236. which experience will always verify. Must we not conclude, therefore,
  6237. that deduction is an operation governed by the properties of matter,
  6238. molded on the mobile articulations of matter, implicitly given, in fact,
  6239. with the space that underlies matter? As long as it turns upon space or
  6240. spatialized time, it has only to let itself go. It is _duration_ that
  6241. puts spokes in its wheels.
  6242. * * * * *
  6243. Deduction, then, does not work unless there be spatial intuition behind
  6244. it. But we may say the same of induction. It is not necessary indeed to
  6245. think geometrically, nor even to think at all, in order to expect from
  6246. the same conditions a repetition of the same fact. The consciousness of
  6247. the animal already does this work, and indeed, independently of all
  6248. consciousness, the living body itself is so constructed that it can
  6249. extract from the successive situations in which it finds itself the
  6250. similarities which interest it, and so respond to the stimuli by
  6251. appropriate reactions. But it is a far cry from a mechanical expectation
  6252. and reaction of the body, to induction properly so called, which is an
  6253. intellectual operation. Induction rests on the belief that there are
  6254. causes and effects, and that the same effects follow the same causes.
  6255. Now, if we examine this double belief, this is what we find. It implies,
  6256. in the first place, that reality is decomposable into groups, which can
  6257. be practically regarded as isolated and independent. If I boil water in
  6258. a kettle on a stove, the operation and the objects that support it are,
  6259. in reality, bound up with a multitude of other objects and a multitude
  6260. of other operations; in the end, I should find that our entire solar
  6261. system is concerned in what is being done at this particular point of
  6262. space. But, in a certain measure, and for the special end I am pursuing,
  6263. I may admit that things happen as if the group _water-kettle-stove_ were
  6264. an independent microcosm. That is my first affirmation. Now, when I say
  6265. that this microcosm will always behave in the same way, that the heat
  6266. will necessarily, at the end of a certain time, cause the boiling of the
  6267. water, I admit that it is sufficient that a certain number of elements
  6268. of the system be given in order that the system should be complete; it
  6269. completes itself automatically, I am not free to complete it in thought
  6270. as I please. The stove, the kettle and the water being given, with a
  6271. certain interval of duration, it seems to me that the boiling, which
  6272. experience showed me yesterday to be the only thing wanting to complete
  6273. the system, will complete it to-morrow, no matter when to-morrow may be.
  6274. What is there at the base of this belief? Notice that the belief is more
  6275. or less assured, according as the case may be, but that it is forced
  6276. upon the mind as an absolute necessity when the microcosm considered
  6277. contains only magnitudes. If two numbers be given, I am not free to
  6278. choose their difference. If two sides of a triangle and the contained
  6279. angle are given, the third side arises of itself and the triangle
  6280. completes itself automatically. I can, it matters not where and it
  6281. matters not when, trace the same two sides containing the same angle: it
  6282. is evident that the new triangles so formed can be superposed on the
  6283. first, and that consequently the same third side will come to complete
  6284. the system. Now, if my certitude is perfect in the case in which I
  6285. reason on pure space determinations, must I not suppose that, in the
  6286. other cases, the certitude is greater the nearer it approaches this
  6287. extreme case? Indeed, may it not be the limiting case which is seen
  6288. through all the others and which colors them, accordingly as they are
  6289. more or less transparent, with a more or less pronounced tinge of
  6290. geometrical necessity?[82] In fact, when I say that the water on the
  6291. fire will boil to-day as it did yesterday, and that this is an absolute
  6292. necessity, I feel vaguely that my imagination is placing the stove of
  6293. yesterday on that of to-day, kettle on kettle, water on water, duration
  6294. on duration, and it seems then that the rest must coincide also, for the
  6295. same reason that, when two triangles are superposed and two of their
  6296. sides coincide, their third sides coincide also. But my imagination acts
  6297. thus only because it shuts its eyes to two essential points. For the
  6298. system of to-day actually to be superimposed on that of yesterday, the
  6299. latter must have waited for the former, time must have halted, and
  6300. everything become simultaneous: that happens in geometry, but in
  6301. geometry alone. Induction therefore implies first that, in the world of
  6302. the physicist as in that of the geometrician, time does not count. But
  6303. it implies also that qualities can be superposed on each other like
  6304. magnitudes. If, in imagination, I place the stove and fire of to-day on
  6305. that of yesterday, I find indeed that the form has remained the same; it
  6306. suffices, for that, that the surfaces and edges coincide; but what is
  6307. the coincidence of two qualities, and how can they be superposed one on
  6308. another in order to ensure that they are identical? Yet I extend to the
  6309. second order of reality all that applies to the first. The physicist
  6310. legitimates this operation later on by reducing, as far as possible,
  6311. differences of quality to differences of magnitude; but, prior to all
  6312. science, I incline to liken qualities to quantities, as if I perceived
  6313. behind the qualities, as through a transparency, a geometrical
  6314. mechanism.[83] The more complete this transparency, the more it seems to
  6315. me that in the same conditions there must be a repetition of the same
  6316. fact. Our inductions are certain, to our eyes, in the exact degree in
  6317. which we make the qualitative differences melt into the homogeneity of
  6318. the space which subtends them, so that geometry is the ideal limit of
  6319. our inductions as well as of our deductions. The movement at the end of
  6320. which is spatiality lays down along its course the faculty of induction
  6321. as well as that of deduction, in fact, intellectuality entire.
  6322. * * * * *
  6323. It creates them in the mind. But it creates also, in things, the "order"
  6324. which our induction, aided by deduction, finds there. This order, on
  6325. which our action leans and in which our intellect recognizes itself,
  6326. seems to us marvelous. Not only do the same general causes always
  6327. produce the same general effects, but beneath the visible causes and
  6328. effects our science discovers an infinity of infinitesimal changes which
  6329. work more and more exactly into one another, the further we push the
  6330. analysis: so much so that, at the end of this analysis, matter becomes,
  6331. it seems to us, geometry itself. Certainly, the intellect is right in
  6332. admiring here the growing order in the growing complexity; both the one
  6333. and the other must have a positive reality for it, since it looks upon
  6334. itself as positive. But things change their aspect when we consider the
  6335. whole of reality as an undivided advance forward to successive
  6336. creations. It seems to us, then, that the complexity of the material
  6337. elements and the mathematical order that binds them together must arise
  6338. automatically when within the whole a partial interruption or inversion
  6339. is produced. Moreover, as the intellect itself is cut out of mind by a
  6340. process of the same kind, it is attuned to this order and complexity,
  6341. and admires them because it recognizes itself in them. But what is
  6342. admirable _in itself_, what really deserves to provoke wonder, is the
  6343. ever-renewed creation which reality, whole and undivided, accomplishes
  6344. in advancing; for no complication of the mathematical order with itself,
  6345. however elaborate we may suppose it, can introduce an atom of novelty
  6346. into the world, whereas this power of creation once given (and it
  6347. exists, for we are conscious of it in ourselves, at least when we act
  6348. freely) has only to be diverted from itself to relax its tension, only
  6349. to relax its tension to extend, only to extend for the mathematical
  6350. order of the elements so distinguished and the inflexible determinism
  6351. connecting them to manifest the interruption of the creative act: in
  6352. fact, inflexible determinism and mathematical order are one with this
  6353. very interruption.
  6354. It is this merely negative tendency that the particular laws of the
  6355. physical world express. None of them, taken separately, has objective
  6356. reality; each is the work of an investigator who has regarded things
  6357. from a certain bias, isolated certain variables, applied certain
  6358. conventional units of measurement. And yet there is an order
  6359. approximately mathematical immanent in matter, an objective order, which
  6360. our science approaches in proportion to its progress. For if matter is a
  6361. relaxation of the inextensive into the extensive and, thereby, of
  6362. liberty into necessity, it does not indeed wholly coincide with pure
  6363. homogeneous space, yet is constituted by the movement which leads to
  6364. space, and is therefore on the way to geometry. It is true that laws of
  6365. mathematical form will never apply to it completely. For that, it would
  6366. have to be pure space and step out of duration.
  6367. We cannot insist too strongly that there is something artificial in the
  6368. mathematical form of a physical law, and consequently in our scientific
  6369. knowledge of things.[84] Our standards of measurement are conventional,
  6370. and, so to say, foreign to the intentions of nature: can we suppose that
  6371. nature has related all the modalities of heat to the expansion of the
  6372. same mass of mercury, or to the change of pressure of the same mass of
  6373. air kept at a constant volume? But we may go further. In a general way,
  6374. _measuring_ is a wholly human operation, which implies that we really or
  6375. ideally superpose two objects one on another a certain number of times.
  6376. Nature did not dream of this superposition. It does not measure, nor
  6377. does it count. Yet physics counts, measures, relates "quantitative"
  6378. variations to one another to obtain laws, and it succeeds. Its success
  6379. would be inexplicable, if the movement which constitutes materiality
  6380. were not the same movement which, prolonged by us to its end, that is to
  6381. say, to homogeneous space, results in making us count, measure, follow
  6382. in their respective variations terms that are functions one of another.
  6383. To effect this prolongation of the movement, our intellect has only to
  6384. let itself go, for it runs naturally to space and mathematics,
  6385. intellectuality and materiality being of the same nature and having been
  6386. produced in the same way.
  6387. If the mathematical order were a positive thing, if there were, immanent
  6388. in matter, laws comparable to those of our codes, the success of our
  6389. science would have in it something of the miraculous. What chances
  6390. should we have indeed of finding the standard of nature and of isolating
  6391. exactly, in order to determine their reciprocal relations, the very
  6392. variables which nature has chosen? But the success of a science of
  6393. mathematical form would be no less incomprehensible, if matter did not
  6394. already possess everything necessary to adapt itself to our formulae.
  6395. One hypothesis only, therefore, remains plausible, namely, that the
  6396. mathematical order is nothing positive, that it is the form toward which
  6397. a certain _interruption_ tends of itself, and that materiality consists
  6398. precisely in an interruption of this kind. We shall understand then why
  6399. our science is contingent, relative to the variables it has chosen,
  6400. relative to the order in which it has successively put the problems, and
  6401. why nevertheless it succeeds. It might have been, as a whole, altogether
  6402. different, and yet have succeeded. This is so, just because there is no
  6403. definite system of mathematical laws, at the base of nature, and because
  6404. mathematics in general represents simply the side to which matter
  6405. inclines. Put one of those little cork dolls with leaden feet in any
  6406. posture, lay it on its back, turn it up on its head, throw it into the
  6407. air: it will always stand itself up again, automatically. So likewise
  6408. with matter: we can take it by any end and handle it in any way, it will
  6409. always fall back into some one of our mathematical formulae, because it
  6410. is weighted with geometry.
  6411. * * * * *
  6412. But the philosopher will perhaps refuse to found a theory of knowledge
  6413. on such considerations. They will be repugnant to him, because the
  6414. mathematical order, being order, will appear to him to contain something
  6415. positive. It is in vain that we assert that this order produces itself
  6416. automatically by the interruption of the inverse order, that it is this
  6417. very interruption. The idea persists, none the less, that _there might
  6418. be no order at all_, and that the mathematical order of things, being a
  6419. conquest over disorder, possesses a positive reality. In examining this
  6420. point, we shall see what a prominent part the idea of _disorder_ plays
  6421. in problems relative to the theory of knowledge. It does not appear
  6422. explicitly, and that is why it escapes our attention. It is, however,
  6423. with the criticism of this idea that a theory of knowledge ought to
  6424. begin, for if the great problem is to know why and how reality submits
  6425. itself to an order, it is because the absence of every kind of order
  6426. appears possible or conceivable. It is this absence of order that
  6427. realists and idealists alike believe they are thinking of--the realist
  6428. when he speaks of the regularity that "objective" laws actually impose
  6429. on a virtual disorder of nature, the idealist when he supposes a
  6430. "sensuous manifold" which is coördinated (and consequently itself
  6431. without order) under the organizing influence of our understanding. The
  6432. idea of disorder, in the sense of _absence of order_, is then what must
  6433. be analyzed first. Philosophy borrows it from daily life. And it is
  6434. unquestionable that, when ordinarily we speak of disorder, we are
  6435. thinking of something. But of what?
  6436. It will be seen in the next chapter how hard it is to determine the
  6437. content of a negative idea, and what illusions one is liable to, what
  6438. hopeless difficulties philosophy falls into, for not having undertaken
  6439. this task. Difficulties and illusions are generally due to this, that we
  6440. accept as final a manner of expression essentially provisional. They are
  6441. due to our bringing into the domain of speculation a procedure made for
  6442. practice. If I choose a volume in my library at random, I may put it
  6443. back on the shelf after glancing at it and say, "This is not verse." Is
  6444. this what I have really seen in turning over the leaves of the book?
  6445. Obviously not. I have not seen, I never shall see, an absence of verse.
  6446. I have seen prose. But as it is poetry I want, I express what I find as
  6447. a function of what I am looking for, and instead of saying, "This is
  6448. prose," I say, "This is not verse." In the same way, if the fancy takes
  6449. me to read prose, and I happen on a volume of verse, I shall say, "This
  6450. is not prose," thus expressing the data of my perception, which shows me
  6451. verse, in the language of my expectation and attention, which are fixed
  6452. on the idea of prose and will hear of nothing else. Now, if Mons.
  6453. Jourdain heard me, he would infer, no doubt, from my two exclamations
  6454. that prose and poetry are two forms of language reserved for books, and
  6455. that these learned forms have come and overlaid a language which was
  6456. neither prose nor verse. Speaking of this thing which is neither verse
  6457. nor prose, he would suppose, moreover, that he was thinking of it: it
  6458. would be only a pseudo-idea, however. Let us go further still: the
  6459. pseudo-idea would create a pseudo-problem, if M. Jourdain were to ask
  6460. his professor of philosophy how the prose form and the poetry form have
  6461. been superadded to that which possessed neither the one nor the other,
  6462. and if he wished the professor to construct a theory of the imposition
  6463. of these two forms upon this formless matter. His question would be
  6464. absurd, and the absurdity would lie in this, that he was hypostasizing
  6465. as the substratum of prose and poetry the simultaneous negation of both,
  6466. forgetting that the negation of the one consists in the affirmation of
  6467. the other.
  6468. Now, suppose that there are two species of order, and that these two
  6469. orders are two contraries within one and the same genus. Suppose also
  6470. that the idea of disorder arises in our mind whenever, seeking one of
  6471. the two kinds of order, we find the other. The idea of disorder would
  6472. then have a clear meaning in the current practice of life: it would
  6473. objectify, for the convenience of language, the disappointment of a mind
  6474. that finds before it an order different from what it wants, an order
  6475. with which it is not concerned at the moment, and which, in this sense,
  6476. does not exist for it. But the idea would not admit a theoretical use.
  6477. So if we claim, notwithstanding, to introduce it into philosophy, we
  6478. shall inevitably lose sight of its true meaning. It denotes the absence
  6479. of a certain order, but _to the profit of another_ (with which we are
  6480. not concerned); only, as it applies to each of the two in turn, and as
  6481. it even goes and comes continually between the two, we take it on the
  6482. way, or rather on the wing, like a shuttlecock between two battledores,
  6483. and treat it as if it represented, not the absence of the one or other
  6484. order as the case may be, but the absence of both together--a thing that
  6485. is neither perceived nor conceived, a simple verbal entity. So there
  6486. arises the problem how order is imposed on disorder, form on matter. In
  6487. analyzing the idea of disorder thus subtilized, we shall see that it
  6488. represents nothing at all, and at the same time the problems that have
  6489. been raised around it will vanish.
  6490. It is true that we must begin by distinguishing, and even by opposing
  6491. one to the other, two kinds of order which we generally confuse. As
  6492. this confusion has created the principal difficulties of the problem of
  6493. knowledge, it will not be useless to dwell once more on the marks by
  6494. which the two orders are distinguished.
  6495. In a general way, reality is _ordered_ exactly to the degree in which it
  6496. satisfies our thought. Order is therefore a certain agreement between
  6497. subject and object. It is the mind finding itself again in things. But
  6498. the mind, we said, can go in two opposite ways. Sometimes it follows its
  6499. natural direction: there is then progress in the form of tension,
  6500. continuous creation, free activity. Sometimes it inverts it, and this
  6501. inversion, pushed to the end, leads to extension, to the necessary
  6502. reciprocal determination of elements externalized each by relation to
  6503. the others, in short, to geometrical mechanism. Now, whether experience
  6504. seems to us to adopt the first direction or whether it is drawn in the
  6505. direction of the second, in both cases we say there is order, for in the
  6506. two processes the mind finds itself again. The confusion between them is
  6507. therefore natural. To escape it, different names would have to be given
  6508. to the two kinds of order, and that is not easy, because of the variety
  6509. and variability of the forms they take. The order of the second kind may
  6510. be defined as geometry, which is its extreme limit; more generally, it
  6511. is that kind of order that is concerned whenever a relation of necessary
  6512. determination is found between causes and effects. It evokes ideas of
  6513. inertia, of passivity, of automatism. As to the first kind of order, it
  6514. oscillates no doubt around finality; and yet we cannot define it as
  6515. finality, for it is sometimes above, sometimes below. In its highest
  6516. forms, it is more than finality, for of a free action or a work of art
  6517. we may say that they show a perfect order, and yet they can only be
  6518. expressed in terms of ideas approximately, and after the event. Life in
  6519. its entirety, regarded as a creative evolution, is something analogous;
  6520. it transcends finality, if we understand by finality the realization of
  6521. an idea conceived or conceivable in advance. The category of finality is
  6522. therefore too narrow for life in its entirety. It is, on the other hand,
  6523. often too wide for a particular manifestation of life taken separately.
  6524. Be that as it may, it is with the _vital_ that we have here to do, and
  6525. the whole present study strives to prove that the vital is in the
  6526. direction of the voluntary. We may say then that this first kind of
  6527. order is that of the _vital_ or of the _willed_, in opposition to the
  6528. second, which is that of the _inert_ and the _automatic_. Common sense
  6529. instinctively distinguishes between the two kinds of order, at least in
  6530. the extreme cases; instinctively, also, it brings them together. We say
  6531. of astronomical phenomena that they manifest an admirable order, meaning
  6532. by this that they can be foreseen mathematically. And we find an order
  6533. no less admirable in a symphony of Beethoven, which is genius,
  6534. originality, and therefore unforeseeability itself.
  6535. But it is exceptional for order of the first kind to take so distinct a
  6536. form. Ordinarily, it presents features that we have every interest in
  6537. confusing with those of the opposite order. It is quite certain, for
  6538. instance, that if we could view the evolution of life in its entirety,
  6539. the spontaneity of its movement and the unforeseeability of its
  6540. procedures would thrust themselves on our attention. But what we meet in
  6541. our daily experience is a certain determinate living being, certain
  6542. special manifestations of life, which repeat, _almost_, forms and facts
  6543. already known; indeed, the similarity of structure that we find
  6544. everywhere between what generates and what is generated--a similarity
  6545. that enables us to include any number of living individuals in the same
  6546. group--is to our eyes the very type of the _generic_: the inorganic
  6547. genera seem to us to take living genera as models. Thus the vital order,
  6548. such as it is offered to us piecemeal in experience, presents the same
  6549. character and performs the same function as the physical order: both
  6550. cause experience to _repeat itself_, both enable our mind to
  6551. _generalize_. In reality, this character has entirely different origins
  6552. in the two cases, and even opposite meanings. In the second case, the
  6553. type of this character, its ideal limit, as also its foundation, is the
  6554. geometrical necessity in virtue of which the same components give the
  6555. same resultant. In the first case, this character involves, on the
  6556. contrary, the intervention of something which manages to obtain the same
  6557. total effect although the infinitely complex elementary causes may be
  6558. quite different. We insisted on this last point in our first chapter,
  6559. when we showed how identical structures are to be met with on
  6560. independent lines of evolution. But, without looking so far, we may
  6561. presume that the reproduction only of the type of the ancestor by his
  6562. descendants is an entirely different thing from the repetition of the
  6563. same composition of forces which yields an identical resultant. When we
  6564. think of the infinity of infinitesimal elements and of infinitesimal
  6565. causes that concur in the genesis of a living being, when we reflect
  6566. that the absence or the deviation of one of them would spoil everything,
  6567. the first impulse of the mind is to consider this army of little workers
  6568. as watched over by a skilled foreman, the "vital principle," which is
  6569. ever repairing faults, correcting effects of neglect or
  6570. absentmindedness, putting things back in place: this is how we try to
  6571. express the difference between the physical and the vital order, the
  6572. former making the same combination of causes give the same combined
  6573. effect, the latter securing the constancy of the effect even when there
  6574. is some wavering in the causes. But that is only a comparison; on
  6575. reflection, we find that there can be no foreman, for the very simple
  6576. reason that there are no workers. The causes and elements that
  6577. physico-chemical analysis discovers are real causes and elements, no
  6578. doubt, as far as the facts of organic destruction are concerned; they
  6579. are then limited in number. But vital phenomena, properly so called, or
  6580. facts of organic creation open up to us, when we analyze them, the
  6581. perspective of an analysis passing away to infinity: whence it may be
  6582. inferred that the manifold causes and elements are here only views of
  6583. the mind, attempting an ever closer and closer imitation of the
  6584. operation of nature, while the operation imitated is an indivisible act.
  6585. The likeness between individuals of the same species has thus an
  6586. entirely different meaning, an entirely different origin, to that of the
  6587. likeness between complex effects obtained by the same composition of the
  6588. same causes. But in the one case as in the other, there is _likeness_,
  6589. and consequently possible generalization. And as that is all that
  6590. interests us in practice, since our daily life is and must be an
  6591. expectation of the same things and the same situations, it is natural
  6592. that this common character, essential from the point of view of our
  6593. action, should bring the two orders together, in spite of a merely
  6594. internal diversity between them which interests speculation only. Hence
  6595. the idea of a _general order of nature_, everywhere the same, hovering
  6596. over life and over matter alike. Hence our habit of designating by the
  6597. same word and representing in the same way the existence of _laws_ in
  6598. the domain of inert matter and that of _genera_ in the domain of life.
  6599. Now, it will be found that this confusion is the origin of most of the
  6600. difficulties raised by the problem of knowledge, among the ancients as
  6601. well as among the moderns. The generality of laws and that of genera
  6602. having been designated by the same word and subsumed under the same
  6603. idea, the geometrical order and the vital order are accordingly confused
  6604. together. According to the point of view, the generality of laws is
  6605. explained by that of genera, or that of genera by that of laws. The
  6606. first view is characteristic of ancient thought; the second belongs to
  6607. modern philosophy. But in both ancient and modern philosophy the idea of
  6608. "generality" is an equivocal idea, uniting in its denotation and in its
  6609. connotation incompatible objects and elements. In both there are grouped
  6610. under the same concept two kinds of order which are alike only in the
  6611. facility they give to our action on things. We bring together the two
  6612. terms in virtue of a quite external likeness, which justifies no doubt
  6613. their designation by the same word for practice, but which does not
  6614. authorize us at all, in the speculative domain, to confuse them in the
  6615. same definition.
  6616. The ancients, indeed, did not ask why nature submits to laws, but why it
  6617. is ordered according to genera. The idea of genus corresponds more
  6618. especially to an objective reality in the domain of life, where it
  6619. expresses an unquestionable fact, heredity. Indeed, there can only be
  6620. genera where there are individual objects; now, while the organized
  6621. being is cut out from the general mass of matter by his very
  6622. organization, that is to say naturally, it is our perception which cuts
  6623. inert matter into distinct bodies. It is guided in this by the interests
  6624. of action, by the nascent reactions that our body indicates--that is, as
  6625. we have shown elsewhere,[85] by the potential genera that are trying to
  6626. gain existence. In this, then, genera and individuals determine one
  6627. another by a semi-artificial operation entirely relative to our future
  6628. action on things. Nevertheless the ancients did not hesitate to put all
  6629. genera in the same rank, to attribute the same absolute existence to
  6630. all of them. Reality thus being a system of genera, it is to the
  6631. generality of the genera (that is, in effect, to the generality
  6632. expressive of the vital order) that the generality of laws itself had to
  6633. be brought. It is interesting, in this respect, to compare the
  6634. Aristotelian theory of the fall of bodies with the explanation furnished
  6635. by Galileo. Aristotle is concerned solely with the concepts "high" and
  6636. "low," "own proper place" as distinguished from "place occupied,"
  6637. "natural movement" and "forced movement;"[86] the physical law in virtue
  6638. of which the stone falls expresses for him that the stone regains the
  6639. "natural place" of all stones, to wit, the earth. The stone, in his
  6640. view, is not quite stone so long as it is not in its normal place; in
  6641. falling back into this place it aims at completing itself, like a living
  6642. being that grows, thus realizing fully the essence of the genus
  6643. stone.[87] If this conception of the physical law were exact, the law
  6644. would no longer be a mere relation established by the mind; the
  6645. subdivision of matter into bodies would no longer be relative to our
  6646. faculty of perceiving; all bodies would have the same individuality as
  6647. living bodies, and the laws of the physical universe would express
  6648. relations of real kinship between real genera. We know what kind of
  6649. physics grew out of this, and how, for having believed in a science
  6650. unique and final, embracing the totality of the real and at one with the
  6651. absolute, the ancients were confined, in fact, to a more or less clumsy
  6652. interpretation of the physical in terms of the vital.
  6653. But there is the same confusion in the moderns, with this difference,
  6654. however, that the relation between the two terms is inverted: laws are
  6655. no longer reduced to genera, but genera to laws; and science, still
  6656. supposed to be uniquely one, becomes altogether relative, instead of
  6657. being, as the ancients wished, altogether at one with the absolute. A
  6658. noteworthy fact is the eclipse of the problem of genera in modern
  6659. philosophy. Our theory of knowledge turns almost entirely on the
  6660. question of laws: genera are left to make shift with laws as best they
  6661. can. The reason is, that modern philosophy has its point of departure in
  6662. the great astronomical and physical discoveries of modern times. The
  6663. laws of Kepler and of Galileo have remained for it the ideal and unique
  6664. type of all knowledge. Now, a law is a relation between things or
  6665. between facts. More precisely, a law of mathematical form expresses the
  6666. fact that a certain magnitude is a function of one or several other
  6667. variables appropriately chosen. Now, the choice of the variable
  6668. magnitudes, the distribution of nature into objects and into facts, has
  6669. already something of the contingent and the conventional. But, admitting
  6670. that the choice is hinted at, if not prescribed, by experience, the law
  6671. remains none the less a relation, and a relation is essentially a
  6672. comparison; it has objective reality only for an intelligence that
  6673. represents to itself several terms at the same time. This intelligence
  6674. may be neither mine nor yours: a science which bears on laws may
  6675. therefore be an objective science, which experience contains in advance
  6676. and which we simply make it disgorge; but it is none the less true that
  6677. a comparison of some kind must be effected here, impersonally if not by
  6678. any one in particular, and that an experience made of laws, that is, of
  6679. terms _related_ to other terms, is an experience made of comparisons,
  6680. which, before we receive it, has already had to pass through an
  6681. atmosphere of intellectuality. The idea of a science and of an
  6682. experience entirely relative to the human understanding was therefore
  6683. implicitly contained in the conception of a science one and integral,
  6684. composed of laws: Kant only brought it to light. But this conception is
  6685. the result of an arbitrary confusion between the generality of laws and
  6686. that of genera. Though an intelligence be necessary to condition terms
  6687. by relation to each other, we may conceive that in certain cases the
  6688. terms themselves may exist independently. And if, beside relations of
  6689. term to term, experience also presents to us independent terms, the
  6690. living genera being something quite different from systems of laws, one
  6691. half, at least, of our knowledge bears on the "thing-in-itself," the
  6692. very reality. This knowledge may be very difficult, just because it no
  6693. longer builds up its own object and is obliged, on the contrary, to
  6694. submit to it; but, however little it cuts into its object, it is into
  6695. the absolute itself that it bites. We may go further: the other half of
  6696. knowledge is no longer so radically, so definitely relative as certain
  6697. philosophers say, if we can establish that it bears on a reality of
  6698. inverse order, a reality which we always express in mathematical laws,
  6699. that is to say in relations that imply comparisons, but which lends
  6700. itself to this work only because it is weighted with spatiality and
  6701. consequently with geometry. Be that as it may, it is the confusion of
  6702. two kinds of order that lies behind the relativism of the moderns, as it
  6703. lay behind the dogmatism of the ancients.
  6704. We have said enough to mark the origin of this confusion. It is due to
  6705. the fact that the "vital" order, which is essentially creation, is
  6706. manifested to us less in its essence than in some of its accidents,
  6707. those which _imitate_ the physical and geometrical order; like it, they
  6708. present to us repetitions that make generalization possible, and in that
  6709. we have all that interests us. There is no doubt that life as a whole is
  6710. an evolution, that is, an unceasing transformation. But life can
  6711. progress only by means of the living, which are its depositaries.
  6712. Innumerable living beings, almost alike, have to repeat each other in
  6713. space and in time for the novelty they are working out to grow and
  6714. mature. It is like a book that advances towards a new edition by going
  6715. through thousands of reprints with thousands of copies. There is,
  6716. however, this difference between the two cases, that the successive
  6717. impressions are identical, as well as the simultaneous copies of the
  6718. same impression, whereas representatives of one and the same species are
  6719. never entirely the same, either in different points of space or at
  6720. different moments of time. Heredity does not only transmit characters;
  6721. it transmits also the impetus in virtue of which the characters are
  6722. modified, and this impetus is vitality itself. That is why we say that
  6723. the repetition which serves as the base of our generalizations is
  6724. essential in the physical order, accidental in the vital order. The
  6725. physical order is "automatic;" the vital order is, I will not say
  6726. voluntary, but analogous to the order "willed."
  6727. Now, as soon as we have clearly distinguished between the order that is
  6728. "willed" and the order that is "automatic," the ambiguity that underlies
  6729. the idea of _disorder_ is dissipated, and, with it, one of the principal
  6730. difficulties of the problem of knowledge.
  6731. The main problem of the theory of knowledge is to know how science is
  6732. possible, that is to say, in effect, why there is order and not disorder
  6733. in things. That order exists is a _fact_. But, on the other hand,
  6734. disorder, _which appears to us to be less than order_, is, it seems, of
  6735. _right_. The existence of order is then a mystery to be cleared up, at
  6736. any rate a problem to be solved. More simply, when we undertake to found
  6737. order, we regard it as contingent, if not in things, at least as viewed
  6738. by the mind: of a thing that we do not judge to be contingent we do not
  6739. require an explanation. If order did not appear to us as a conquest over
  6740. something, or as an addition to something (which something is thought to
  6741. be the "absence of order"), ancient realism would not have spoken of a
  6742. "matter" to which the Idea superadded itself, nor would modern idealism
  6743. have supposed a "sensuous manifold" that the understanding organizes
  6744. into nature. Now, it is unquestionable that all order is contingent, and
  6745. conceived as such. But contingent in relation to what?
  6746. The reply, to our thinking, is not doubtful. An order is contingent, and
  6747. seems so, in relation to the inverse order, as verse is contingent in
  6748. relation to prose and prose in relation to verse. But, just as all
  6749. speech which is not prose is verse and necessarily conceived as verse,
  6750. just as all speech which is not verse is prose and necessarily conceived
  6751. as prose, so any state of things that is not one of the two orders is
  6752. the other and is necessarily conceived as the other. But it may happen
  6753. that we do not realize what we are actually thinking of, and perceive
  6754. the idea really present to our mind only through a mist of affective
  6755. states. Any one can be convinced of this by considering the use we make
  6756. of the idea of disorder in daily life. When I enter a room and pronounce
  6757. it to be "in disorder," what do I mean? The position of each object is
  6758. explained by the automatic movements of the person who has slept in the
  6759. room, or by the efficient causes, whatever they may be, that have caused
  6760. each article of furniture, clothing, etc., to be where it is: the order,
  6761. in the second sense of the word, is perfect. But it is order of the
  6762. first kind that I am expecting, the order that a methodical person
  6763. consciously puts into his life, the willed order and not the automatic:
  6764. so I call the absence of this order "disorder." At bottom, all there is
  6765. that is real, perceived and even conceived, in this absence of one of
  6766. the two kinds of order, is the presence of the other. But the second is
  6767. indifferent to me, _I am interested only in the first_, and I express
  6768. the presence of the second as a function of the first, instead of
  6769. expressing it, so to speak, as a function of itself, by saying it is
  6770. _disorder_. Inversely, when we affirm that we are imagining a chaos,
  6771. that is to say a state of things in which the physical world no longer
  6772. obeys laws, what are we thinking of? We imagine facts that appear and
  6773. disappear _capriciously_. First we think of the physical universe as we
  6774. know it, with effects and causes well proportioned to each other; then,
  6775. by a series of arbitrary decrees, we augment, diminish, suppress, so as
  6776. to obtain what we call disorder. In reality we have substituted _will_
  6777. for the mechanism of nature; we have replaced the "automatic order" by a
  6778. multitude of elementary wills, just to the extent that we imagine the
  6779. apparition or vanishing of phenomena. No doubt, for all these little
  6780. wills to constitute a "willed order," they must have accepted the
  6781. direction of a higher will. But, on looking closely at them, we see that
  6782. that is just what they do: our own will is there, which objectifies
  6783. itself in each of these capricious wills in turn, and takes good care
  6784. not to connect the same with the same, nor to permit the effect to be
  6785. proportional to the cause--in fact makes one simple intention hover over
  6786. the whole of the elementary volitions. Thus, here again, the absence of
  6787. one of the two orders consists in the presence of the other. In
  6788. analyzing the idea of chance, which is closely akin to the idea of
  6789. disorder, we find the same elements. When the wholly mechanical play of
  6790. the causes which stop the wheel on a number makes me win, and
  6791. consequently acts like a good genius, careful of my interests, or when
  6792. the wholly mechanical force of the wind tears a tile off the roof and
  6793. throws it on to my head, that is to say acts like a bad genius,
  6794. conspiring against my person: in both cases I find a mechanism where I
  6795. should have looked for, where, indeed, it seems as if I ought to have
  6796. found, an intention. That is what I express in speaking of _chance_. And
  6797. of an anarchical world, in which phenomena succeed each other
  6798. capriciously, I should say again that it is a realm of chance, meaning
  6799. that I find before me wills, or rather _decrees_, when what I am
  6800. expecting is mechanism. Thus is explained the singular vacillation of
  6801. the mind when it tries to define chance. Neither efficient cause nor
  6802. final cause can furnish the definition sought. The mind swings to and
  6803. fro, unable to rest, between the idea of an absence of final cause and
  6804. that of an absence of efficient cause, each of these definitions sending
  6805. it back to the other. The problem remains insoluble, in fact, so long as
  6806. the idea of chance is regarded as a pure idea, without mixture of
  6807. feeling. But, in reality, chance merely objectifies the state of mind of
  6808. one who, expecting one of the two kinds of order, finds himself
  6809. confronted with the other. Chance and disorder are therefore necessarily
  6810. conceived as relative. So if we wish to represent them to ourselves as
  6811. absolute, we perceive that we are going to and fro like a shuttle
  6812. between the two kinds of order, passing into the one just at the moment
  6813. at which we might catch ourself in the other, and that the supposed
  6814. absence of all order is really the presence of both, with, besides, the
  6815. swaying of a mind that cannot rest finally in either. Neither in things
  6816. nor in our idea of things can there be any question of presenting this
  6817. disorder as the substratum of order, since it implies the two kinds of
  6818. order and is made of their combination.
  6819. But our intelligence is not stopped by this. By a simple _sic jubeo_ it
  6820. posits a disorder which is an "absence of order." In so doing it thinks
  6821. a word or a set of words, nothing more. If it seeks to attach an idea
  6822. to the word, it finds that disorder may indeed be the negation of order,
  6823. but that this negation is then the implicit affirmation of the presence
  6824. of the opposite order, which we shut our eyes to because it does not
  6825. interest us, or which we evade by denying the second order in its
  6826. turn--that is, at bottom, by re-establishing the first. How can we
  6827. speak, then, of an incoherent diversity which an understanding
  6828. organizes? It is no use for us to say that no one supposes this
  6829. incoherence to be realized or realizable: when we speak of it, we
  6830. believe we are thinking of it; now, in analyzing the idea actually
  6831. present, we find, as we said before, only the disappointment of the mind
  6832. confronted with an order that does not interest it, or a swaying of the
  6833. mind between two kinds of order, or, finally, the idea pure and simple
  6834. of the empty word that we have created by joining a negative prefix to a
  6835. word which itself signifies something. But it is this analysis that we
  6836. neglect to make. We omit it, precisely because it does not occur to us
  6837. to distinguish two kinds of order that are irreducible to one another.
  6838. We said, indeed, that all order necessarily appears as contingent. If
  6839. there are two kinds of order, this contingency of order is explained:
  6840. one of the forms is contingent in relation to the other. Where I find
  6841. the geometrical order, the vital was possible; where the order is vital,
  6842. it might have been geometrical. But suppose that the order is everywhere
  6843. of the same kind, and simply admits of degrees which go from the
  6844. geometrical to the vital: if a determinate order still appears to me to
  6845. be contingent, and can no longer be so by relation to an order of
  6846. another kind, I shall necessarily believe that the order is contingent
  6847. by relation to an _absence of itself_, that is to say by relation to a
  6848. state of things "in which there is no order at all." And this state of
  6849. things I shall believe that I am thinking of, because it is implied, it
  6850. seems, in the very contingency of order, which is an unquestionable
  6851. fact. I shall therefore place at the summit of the hierarchy the vital
  6852. order; then, as a diminution or lower complication of it, the
  6853. geometrical order; and finally, at the bottom of all, an absence of
  6854. order, incoherence itself, on which order is superposed. This is why
  6855. incoherence has the effect on me of a word behind which there must be
  6856. something real, if not in things, at least in thought. But if I observe
  6857. that the state of things implied by the contingency of a determinate
  6858. order is simply the presence of the contrary order, and if by this very
  6859. fact I posit two kinds of order, each the inverse of the other, I
  6860. perceive that no intermediate degrees can be imagined between the two
  6861. orders, and that there is no going down from the two orders to the
  6862. "incoherent." Either the incoherent is only a word, devoid of meaning,
  6863. or, if I give it a meaning, it is on condition of putting incoherence
  6864. midway between the two orders, and not below both of them. There is not
  6865. first the incoherent, then the geometrical, then the vital; there is
  6866. only the geometrical and the vital, and then, by a swaying of the mind
  6867. between them, the idea of the incoherent. To speak of an uncoördinated
  6868. diversity to which order is superadded is therefore to commit a
  6869. veritable _petitio principii_; for in imagining the uncoördinated we
  6870. really posit an order, or rather two.
  6871. * * * * *
  6872. This long analysis was necessary to show how the real can pass from
  6873. tension to extension and from freedom to mechanical necessity by way of
  6874. inversion. It was not enough to prove that this relation between the two
  6875. terms is suggested to us, at once, by consciousness and by sensible
  6876. experience. It was necessary to prove that the geometrical order has no
  6877. need of explanation, being purely and simply the suppression of the
  6878. inverse order. And, for that, it was indispensable to prove that
  6879. suppression is always a substitution and is even necessarily conceived
  6880. as such: it is the requirements of practical life alone that suggest to
  6881. us here a way of speaking that deceives us both as to what happens in
  6882. things and as to what is present to our thought. We must now examine
  6883. more closely the inversion whose consequences we have just described.
  6884. What, then, is the principle that has only to let go its tension--may we
  6885. say to _detend_--in order to _extend_, the interruption of the cause
  6886. here being equivalent to a reversal of the effect?
  6887. For want of a better word we have called it consciousness. But we do not
  6888. mean the narrowed consciousness that functions in each of us. Our own
  6889. consciousness is the consciousness of a certain living being, placed in
  6890. a certain point of space; and though it does indeed move in the same
  6891. direction as its principle, it is continually drawn the opposite way,
  6892. obliged, though it goes forward, to look behind. This retrospective
  6893. vision is, as we have shown, the natural function of the intellect, and
  6894. consequently of distinct consciousness. In order that our consciousness
  6895. shall coincide with something of its principle, it must detach itself
  6896. from the _already-made_ and attach itself to the _being-made_. It needs
  6897. that, turning back on itself and twisting on itself, the faculty of
  6898. _seeing_ should be made to be one with the act of _willing_--a painful
  6899. effort which we can make suddenly, doing violence to our nature, but
  6900. cannot sustain more than a few moments. In free action, when we contract
  6901. our whole being in order to thrust it forward, we have the more or less
  6902. clear consciousness of motives and of impelling forces, and even, at
  6903. rare moments, of the becoming by which they are organized into an act:
  6904. but the pure willing, the current that runs through this matter,
  6905. communicating life to it, is a thing which we hardly feel, which at most
  6906. we brush lightly as it passes. Let us try, however, to instal ourselves
  6907. within it, if only for a moment; even then it is an individual and
  6908. fragmentary will that we grasp. To get to the principle of all life, as
  6909. also of all materiality, we must go further still. Is it impossible? No,
  6910. by no means; the history of philosophy is there to bear witness. There
  6911. is no durable system that is not, at least in some of its parts,
  6912. vivified by intuition. Dialectic is necessary to put intuition to the
  6913. proof, necessary also in order that intuition should break itself up
  6914. into concepts and so be propagated to other men; but all it does, often
  6915. enough, is to develop the result of that intuition which transcends it.
  6916. The truth is, the two procedures are of opposite direction: the same
  6917. effort, by which ideas are connected with ideas, causes the intuition
  6918. which the ideas were storing up to vanish. The philosopher is obliged to
  6919. abandon intuition, once he has received from it the impetus, and to rely
  6920. on himself to carry on the movement by pushing the concepts one after
  6921. another. But he soon feels he has lost foothold; he must come into touch
  6922. with intuition again; he must undo most of what he has done. In short,
  6923. dialectic is what ensures the agreement of our thought with itself. But
  6924. by dialectic--which is only a relaxation of intuition--many different
  6925. agreements are possible, while there is only one truth. Intuition, if it
  6926. could be prolonged beyond a few instants, would not only make the
  6927. philosopher agree with his own thought, but also all philosophers with
  6928. each other. Such as it is, fugitive and incomplete, it is, in each
  6929. system, what is worth more than the system and survives it. The object
  6930. of philosophy would be reached if this intuition could be sustained,
  6931. generalized and, above all, assured of external points of reference in
  6932. order not to go astray. To that end a continual coming and going is
  6933. necessary between nature and mind.
  6934. When we put back our being into our will, and our will itself into the
  6935. impulsion it prolongs, we understand, we feel, that reality is a
  6936. perpetual growth, a creation pursued without end. Our will already
  6937. performs this miracle. Every human work in which there is invention,
  6938. every voluntary act in which there is freedom, every movement of an
  6939. organism that manifests spontaneity, brings something new into the
  6940. world. True, these are only creations of form. How could they be
  6941. anything else? We are not the vital current itself; we are this current
  6942. already loaded with matter, that is, with congealed parts of its own
  6943. substance which it carries along its course. In the composition of a
  6944. work of genius, as in a simple free decision, we do, indeed, stretch the
  6945. spring of our activity to the utmost and thus create what no mere
  6946. assemblage of materials could have given (what assemblage of curves
  6947. already known can ever be equivalent to the pencil-stroke of a great
  6948. artist?) but there are, none the less, elements here that pre-exist and
  6949. survive their organization. But if a simple arrest of the action that
  6950. generates form could constitute matter (are not the original lines drawn
  6951. by the artist themselves already the fixation and, as it were,
  6952. congealment of a movement?), a creation of matter would be neither
  6953. incomprehensible nor inadmissible. For we seize from within, we live at
  6954. every instant, a creation of form, and it is just in those cases in
  6955. which the form is pure, and in which the creative current is momentarily
  6956. interrupted, that there is a creation of matter. Consider the letters of
  6957. the alphabet that enter into the composition of everything that has ever
  6958. been written: we do not conceive that new letters spring up and come to
  6959. join themselves to the others in order to make a new poem. But that the
  6960. poet creates the poem and that human thought is thereby made richer, we
  6961. understand very well: this creation is a simple act of the mind, and
  6962. action has only to make a pause, instead of continuing into a new
  6963. creation, in order that, of itself, it may break up into words which
  6964. dissociate themselves into letters which are added to all the letters
  6965. there are already in the world. Thus, that the number of atoms composing
  6966. the material universe at a given moment should increase runs counter to
  6967. our habits of mind, contradicts the whole of our experience; but that a
  6968. reality of quite another order, which contrasts with the atom as the
  6969. thought of the poet with the letters of the alphabet, should increase by
  6970. sudden additions, is not inadmissible; and the reverse of each addition
  6971. might indeed be a world, which we then represent to ourselves,
  6972. symbolically, as an assemblage of atoms.
  6973. The mystery that spreads over the existence of the universe comes in
  6974. great part from this, that we want the genesis of it to have been
  6975. accomplished at one stroke or the whole of matter to be eternal. Whether
  6976. we speak of creation or posit an uncreated matter, it is the totality of
  6977. the universe that we are considering at once. At the root of this habit
  6978. of mind lies the prejudice which we will analyze in our next chapter,
  6979. the idea, common to materialists and to their opponents, that there is
  6980. no really acting duration, and that the absolute--matter or mind--can
  6981. have no place in concrete time, in the time which we feel to be the very
  6982. stuff of our life. From which it follows that everything is given once
  6983. for all, and that it is necessary to posit from all eternity either
  6984. material multiplicity itself, or the act creating this multiplicity,
  6985. given in block in the divine essence. Once this prejudice is eradicated,
  6986. the idea of creation becomes more clear, for it is merged in that of
  6987. growth. But it is no longer then of the universe in its totality that we
  6988. must speak.
  6989. Why should we speak of it? The universe is an assemblage of solar
  6990. systems which we have every reason to believe analogous to our own. No
  6991. doubt they are not absolutely independent of one another. Our sun
  6992. radiates heat and light beyond the farthest planet, and, on the other
  6993. hand, our entire solar system is moving in a definite direction as if it
  6994. were drawn. There is, then, a bond between the worlds. But this bond may
  6995. be regarded as infinitely loose in comparison with the mutual dependence
  6996. which unites the parts of the same world among themselves; so that it is
  6997. not artificially, for reasons of mere convenience, that we isolate our
  6998. solar system: nature itself invites us to isolate it. As living beings,
  6999. we depend on the planet on which we are, and on the sun that provides
  7000. for it, but on nothing else. As thinking beings, we may apply the laws
  7001. of our physics to our own world, and extend them to each of the worlds
  7002. taken separately; but nothing tells us that they apply to the entire
  7003. universe, nor even that such an affirmation has any meaning; for the
  7004. universe is not made, but is being made continually. It is growing,
  7005. perhaps indefinitely, by the addition of new worlds.
  7006. Let us extend, then, to the whole of our solar system the two most
  7007. general laws of our science, the principle of conservation of energy and
  7008. that of its degradation--limiting them, however, to this relatively
  7009. closed system and to other systems relatively closed. Let us see what
  7010. will follow. We must remark, first of all, that these two principles
  7011. have not the same metaphysical scope. The first is a quantitative law,
  7012. and consequently relative, in part, to our methods of measurement. It
  7013. says that, in a system presumed to be closed, the total energy, that is
  7014. to say the sum of its kinetic and potential energy, remains constant.
  7015. Now, if there were only kinetic energy in the world, or even if there
  7016. were, besides kinetic energy, only one single kind of potential energy,
  7017. but no more, the artifice of measurement would not make the law
  7018. artificial. The law of the conservation of energy would express indeed
  7019. that _something_ is preserved in constant quantity. But there are, in
  7020. fact, energies of various kinds,[88] and the measurement of each of them
  7021. has evidently been so chosen as to justify the principle of conservation
  7022. of energy. Convention, therefore, plays a large part in this principle,
  7023. although there is undoubtedly, between the variations of the different
  7024. energies composing one and the same system, a mutual dependence which is
  7025. just what has made the extension of the principle possible by
  7026. measurements suitably chosen. If, therefore, the philosopher applies
  7027. this principle to the solar system complete, he must at least soften its
  7028. outlines. The law of the conservation of energy cannot here express the
  7029. objective permanence of a certain quantity of a certain thing, but
  7030. rather the necessity for every change that is brought about to be
  7031. counterbalanced in some way by a change in an opposite direction. That
  7032. is to say, even if it governs the whole of our solar system, the law of
  7033. the conservation of energy is concerned with the relationship of a
  7034. fragment of this world to another fragment rather than with the nature
  7035. of the whole.
  7036. It is otherwise with the second principle of thermodynamics. The law of
  7037. the degradation of energy does not bear essentially on magnitudes. No
  7038. doubt the first idea of it arose, in the thought of Carnot, out of
  7039. certain quantitative considerations on the yield of thermic machines.
  7040. Unquestionably, too, the terms in which Clausius generalized it were
  7041. mathematical, and a calculable magnitude, "entropy," was, in fact, the
  7042. final conception to which he was led. Such precision is necessary for
  7043. practical applications. But the law might have been vaguely conceived,
  7044. and, if absolutely necessary, it might have been roughly formulated,
  7045. even though no one had ever thought of measuring the different energies
  7046. of the physical world, even though the concept of energy had not been
  7047. created. Essentially, it expresses the fact that all physical changes
  7048. have a tendency to be degraded into heat, and that heat tends to be
  7049. distributed among bodies in a uniform manner. In this less precise form,
  7050. it becomes independent of any convention; it is the most metaphysical of
  7051. the laws of physics since it points out without interposed symbols,
  7052. without artificial devices of measurements, the direction in which the
  7053. world is going. It tells us that changes that are visible and
  7054. heterogeneous will be more and more diluted into changes that are
  7055. invisible and homogeneous, and that the instability to which we owe the
  7056. richness and variety of the changes taking place in our solar system
  7057. will gradually give way to the relative stability of elementary
  7058. vibrations continually and perpetually repeated. Just so with a man who
  7059. keeps up his strength as he grows old, but spends it less and less in
  7060. actions, and comes, in the end, to employ it entirely in making his
  7061. lungs breathe and his heart beat.
  7062. From this point of view, a world like our solar system is seen to be
  7063. ever exhausting something of the mutability it contains. In the
  7064. beginning, it had the maximum of possible utilization of energy: this
  7065. mutability has gone on diminishing unceasingly. Whence does it come? We
  7066. might at first suppose that it has come from some other point of space,
  7067. but the difficulty is only set back, and for this external source of
  7068. mutability the same question springs up. True, it might be added that
  7069. the number of worlds capable of passing mutability to each other is
  7070. unlimited, that the sum of mutability contained in the universe is
  7071. infinite, that there is therefore no ground on which to seek its origin
  7072. or to foresee its end. A hypothesis of this kind is as irrefutable as it
  7073. is indemonstrable; but to speak of an infinite universe is to admit a
  7074. perfect coincidence of matter with abstract space, and consequently an
  7075. absolute externality of all the parts of matter in relation to one
  7076. another. We have seen above what we must think of this theory, and how
  7077. difficult it is to reconcile with the idea of a reciprocal influence of
  7078. all the parts of matter on one another, an influence to which indeed it
  7079. itself makes appeal. Again it might be supposed that the general
  7080. instability has arisen from a general state of stability; that the
  7081. period in which we now are, and in which the utilizable energy is
  7082. diminishing, has been preceded by a period in which the mutability was
  7083. increasing, and that the alternations of increase and diminution succeed
  7084. each other for ever. This hypothesis is theoretically conceivable, as
  7085. has been demonstrated quite recently; but, according to the calculations
  7086. of Boltzmann, the mathematical improbability of it passes all
  7087. imagination and practically amounts to absolute impossibility.[89] In
  7088. reality, the problem remains insoluble as long as we keep on the ground
  7089. of physics, for the physicist is obliged to attach energy to extended
  7090. particles, and, even if he regards the particles only as reservoirs of
  7091. energy, he remains in space: he would belie his rôle if he sought the
  7092. origin of these energies in an extra-spatial process. It is there,
  7093. however, in our opinion, that it must be sought.
  7094. Is it extension in general that we are considering _in abstracto_?
  7095. _Extension_, we said, appears only as a _tension_ which is interrupted.
  7096. Or, are we considering the concrete reality that fills this extension?
  7097. The order which reigns there, and which is manifested by the laws of
  7098. nature, is an order which must be born of itself when the inverse order
  7099. is suppressed; a detension of the will would produce precisely this
  7100. suppression. Lastly, we find that the direction, which this reality
  7101. takes, suggests to us the idea of a thing _unmaking itself_; such, no
  7102. doubt, is one of the essential characters of materiality. What
  7103. conclusion are we to draw from all this, if not that the process by
  7104. which this thing _makes itself_ is directed in a contrary way to that of
  7105. physical processes, and that it is therefore, by its very definition,
  7106. immaterial? The vision we have of the material world is that of a weight
  7107. which falls: no image drawn from matter, properly so called, will ever
  7108. give us the idea of the weight rising. But this conclusion will come
  7109. home to us with still greater force if we press nearer to the concrete
  7110. reality, and if we consider, no longer only matter in general, but,
  7111. within this matter, living bodies.
  7112. All our analyses show us, in life, an effort to remount the incline that
  7113. matter descends. In that, they reveal to us the possibility, the
  7114. necessity even of a process the inverse of materiality, creative of
  7115. matter by its interruption alone. The life that evolves on the surface
  7116. of our planet is indeed attached to matter. If it were pure
  7117. consciousness, _a fortiori_ if it were supra-consciousness, it would be
  7118. pure creative activity. In fact, it is riveted to an organism that
  7119. subjects it to the general laws of inert matter. But everything happens
  7120. as if it were doing its utmost to set itself free from these laws. It
  7121. has not the power to reverse the direction of physical changes, such as
  7122. the principle of Carnot determines it. It does, however, behave
  7123. absolutely as a force would behave which, left to itself, would work in
  7124. the inverse direction. Incapable of _stopping_ the course of material
  7125. changes downwards, it succeeds in _retarding_ it. The evolution of life
  7126. really continues, as we have shown, an initial impulsion: this
  7127. impulsion, which has determined the development of the chlorophyllian
  7128. function in the plant and of the sensori-motor system in the animal,
  7129. brings life to more and more efficient acts by the fabrication and use
  7130. of more and more powerful explosives. Now, what do these explosives
  7131. represent if not a storing-up of the solar energy, the degradation of
  7132. which energy is thus provisionally suspended on some of the points where
  7133. it was being poured forth? The usable energy which the explosive
  7134. conceals will be expended, of course, at the moment of the explosion;
  7135. but it would have been expended sooner if an organism had not happened
  7136. to be there to arrest its dissipation, in order to retain it and save it
  7137. up. As we see it to-day, at the point to which it was brought by a
  7138. scission of the mutually complementary tendencies which it contained
  7139. within itself, life is entirely dependent on the chlorophyllian function
  7140. of the plant. This means that, looked at in its initial impulsion,
  7141. before any scission, life was a tendency to accumulate in a reservoir,
  7142. as do especially the green parts of vegetables, with a view to an
  7143. instantaneous effective discharge, like that which an animal brings
  7144. about, something that would have otherwise flowed away. It is like an
  7145. effort to raise the weight which falls. True, it succeeds only in
  7146. retarding the fall. But at least it can give us an idea of what the
  7147. raising of the weight was.[90]
  7148. Let us imagine a vessel full of steam at a high pressure, and here and
  7149. there in its sides a crack through which the steam is escaping in a jet.
  7150. The steam thrown into the air is nearly all condensed into little drops
  7151. which fall back, and this condensation and this fall represent simply
  7152. the loss of something, an interruption, a deficit. But a small part of
  7153. the jet of steam subsists, uncondensed, for some seconds; it is making
  7154. an effort to raise the drops which are falling; it succeeds at most in
  7155. retarding their fall. So, from an immense reservoir of life, jets must
  7156. be gushing out unceasingly, of which each, falling back, is a world. The
  7157. evolution of living species within this world represents what subsists
  7158. of the primitive direction of the original jet, and of an impulsion
  7159. which continues itself in a direction the inverse of materiality. But
  7160. let us not carry too far this comparison. It gives us but a feeble and
  7161. even deceptive image of reality, for the crack, the jet of steam, the
  7162. forming of the drops, are determined necessarily, whereas the creation
  7163. of a world is a free act, and the life within the material world
  7164. participates in this liberty. Let us think rather of an action like that
  7165. of raising the arm; then let us suppose that the arm, left to itself,
  7166. falls back, and yet that there subsists in it, striving to raise it up
  7167. again, something of the will that animates it. In this image of a
  7168. _creative action which unmakes itself_ we have already a more exact
  7169. representation of matter. In vital activity we see, then, that which
  7170. subsists of the direct movement in the inverted movement, _a reality
  7171. which is making itself in a reality which is unmaking itself_.
  7172. Everything is obscure in the idea of creation if we think of _things_
  7173. which are created and a _thing_ which creates, as we habitually do, as
  7174. the understanding cannot help doing. We shall show the origin of this
  7175. illusion in our next chapter. It is natural to our intellect, whose
  7176. function is essentially practical, made to present to us things and
  7177. states rather than changes and acts. But things and states are only
  7178. views, taken by our mind, of becoming. There are no things, there are
  7179. only actions. More particularly, if I consider the world in which we
  7180. live, I find that the automatic and strictly determined evolution of
  7181. this well-knit whole is action which is unmaking itself, and that the
  7182. unforeseen forms which life cuts out in it, forms capable of being
  7183. themselves prolonged into unforeseen movements, represent the action
  7184. that is making itself. Now, I have every reason to believe that the
  7185. other worlds are analogous to ours, that things happen there in the same
  7186. way. And I know they were not all constructed at the same time, since
  7187. observation shows me, even to-day, nebulae in course of concentration.
  7188. Now, if the same kind of action is going on everywhere, whether it is
  7189. that which is unmaking itself or whether it is that which is striving to
  7190. remake itself, I simply express this probable similitude when I speak of
  7191. a centre from which worlds shoot out like rockets in a fireworks
  7192. display--provided, however, that I do not present this centre as a
  7193. _thing_, but as a continuity of shooting out. God thus defined, has
  7194. nothing of the already made; He is unceasing life, action, freedom.
  7195. Creation, so conceived, is not a mystery; we experience it in ourselves
  7196. when we act freely. That new things can join things already existing is
  7197. absurd, no doubt, since the _thing_ results from a solidification
  7198. performed by our understanding, and there are never any things other
  7199. than those that the understanding has thus constituted. To speak of
  7200. things creating themselves would therefore amount to saying that the
  7201. understanding presents to itself more than it presents to itself--a
  7202. self-contradictory affirmation, an empty and vain idea. But that action
  7203. increases as it goes on, that it creates in the measure of its advance,
  7204. is what each of us finds when he watches himself act. Things are
  7205. constituted by the instantaneous cut which the understanding practices,
  7206. at a given moment, on a flux of this kind, and what is mysterious when
  7207. we compare the cuts together becomes clear when we relate them to the
  7208. flux. Indeed, the modalities of creative action, in so far as it is
  7209. still going on in the organization of living forms, are much simplified
  7210. when they are taken in this way. Before the complexity of an organism
  7211. and the practically infinite multitude of interwoven analyses and
  7212. syntheses it presupposes, our understanding recoils disconcerted. That
  7213. the simple play of physical and chemical forces, left to themselves,
  7214. should have worked this marvel, we find hard to believe. And if it is a
  7215. profound science which is at work, how are we to understand the
  7216. influence exercised on this matter without form by this form without
  7217. matter? But the difficulty arises from this, that we represent
  7218. statically ready-made material particles juxtaposed to one another, and,
  7219. also statically, an external cause which plasters upon them a skilfully
  7220. contrived organization. In reality, life is a movement, materiality is
  7221. the inverse movement, and each of these two movements is simple, the
  7222. matter which forms a world being an undivided flux, and undivided also
  7223. the life that runs through it, cutting out in it living beings all along
  7224. its track. Of these two currents the second runs counter to the first,
  7225. but the first obtains, all the same, something from the second. There
  7226. results between them a _modus vivendi_, which is organization. This
  7227. organization takes, for our senses and for our intellect, the form of
  7228. parts entirely external to other parts in space and in time. Not only do
  7229. we shut our eyes to the unity of the impulse which, passing through
  7230. generations, links individuals with individuals, species with species,
  7231. and makes of the whole series of the living one single immense wave
  7232. flowing over matter, but each individual itself seems to us as an
  7233. aggregate, aggregate of molecules and aggregate of facts. The reason of
  7234. this lies in the structure of our intellect, which is formed to act on
  7235. matter from without, and which succeeds by making, in the flux of the
  7236. real, instantaneous cuts, each of which becomes, in its fixity,
  7237. endlessly decomposable. Perceiving, in an organism, only parts external
  7238. to parts, the understanding has the choice between two systems of
  7239. explanation only: either to regard the infinitely complex (and thereby
  7240. infinitely well-contrived) organization as a fortuitous concatenation of
  7241. atoms, or to relate it to the incomprehensible influence of an external
  7242. force that has grouped its elements together. But this complexity is the
  7243. work of the understanding; this incomprehensibility is also its work.
  7244. Let us try to see, no longer with the eyes of the intellect alone, which
  7245. grasps only the already made and which looks from the outside, but with
  7246. the spirit, I mean with that faculty of seeing which is immanent in the
  7247. faculty of acting and which springs up, somehow, by the twisting of the
  7248. will on itself, when action is turned into knowledge, like heat, so to
  7249. say, into light. To movement, then, everything will be restored, and
  7250. into movement everything will be resolved. Where the understanding,
  7251. working on the image supposed to be fixed of the progressing action,
  7252. shows us parts infinitely manifold and an order infinitely well
  7253. contrived, we catch a glimpse of a simple process, an action which is
  7254. making itself across an action of the same kind which is unmaking
  7255. itself, like the fiery path torn by the last rocket of a fireworks
  7256. display through the black cinders of the spent rockets that are falling
  7257. dead.
  7258. * * * * *
  7259. From this point of view, the general considerations we have presented
  7260. concerning the evolution of life will be cleared up and completed. We
  7261. will distinguish more sharply what is accidental from what is essential
  7262. in this evolution.
  7263. The impetus of life, of which we are speaking, consists in a need of
  7264. creation. It cannot create absolutely, because it is confronted with
  7265. matter, that is to say with the movement that is the inverse of its own.
  7266. But it seizes upon this matter, which is necessity itself, and strives
  7267. to introduce into it the largest possible amount of indetermination and
  7268. liberty. How does it go to work?
  7269. An animal high in the scale may be represented in a general way, we
  7270. said, as a sensori-motor nervous system imposed on digestive,
  7271. respiratory, circulatory systems, etc. The function of these latter is
  7272. to cleanse, repair and protect the nervous system, to make it as
  7273. independent as possible of external circumstances, but, above all, to
  7274. furnish it with energy to be expended in movements. The increasing
  7275. complexity of the organism is therefore due theoretically (in spite of
  7276. innumerable exceptions due to accidents of evolution) to the necessity
  7277. of complexity in the nervous system. No doubt, each complication of any
  7278. part of the organism involves many others in addition, because this part
  7279. itself must live, and every change in one point of the body
  7280. reverberates, as it were, throughout. The complication may therefore go
  7281. on to infinity in all directions; but it is the complication of the
  7282. nervous system which conditions the others in right, if not always in
  7283. fact. Now, in what does the progress of the nervous system itself
  7284. consist? In a simultaneous development of automatic activity and of
  7285. voluntary activity, the first furnishing the second with an appropriate
  7286. instrument. Thus, in an organism such as ours, a considerable number of
  7287. motor mechanisms are set up in the medulla and in the spinal cord,
  7288. awaiting only a signal to release the corresponding act: the will is
  7289. employed, in some cases, in setting up the mechanism itself, and in the
  7290. others in choosing the mechanisms to be released, the manner of
  7291. combining them and the moment of releasing them. The will of an animal
  7292. is the more effective and the more intense, the greater the number of
  7293. the mechanisms it can choose from, the more complicated the switchboard
  7294. on which all the motor paths cross, or, in other words, the more
  7295. developed its brain. Thus, the progress of the nervous system assures to
  7296. the act increasing precision, increasing variety, increasing efficiency
  7297. and independence. The organism behaves more and more like a machine for
  7298. action, which reconstructs itself entirely for every new act, as if it
  7299. were made of india-rubber and could, at any moment, change the shape of
  7300. all its parts. But, prior to the nervous system, prior even to the
  7301. organism properly so called, already in the undifferentiated mass of the
  7302. amoeba, this essential property of animal life is found. The amoeba
  7303. deforms itself in varying directions; its entire mass does what the
  7304. differentiation of parts will localize in a sensori-motor system in the
  7305. developed animal. Doing it only in a rudimentary manner, it is dispensed
  7306. from the complexity of the higher organisms; there is no need here of
  7307. the auxiliary elements that pass on to motor elements the energy to
  7308. expend; the animal moves as a whole, and, as a whole also, procures
  7309. energy by means of the organic substances it assimilates. Thus, whether
  7310. low or high in the animal scale, we always find that animal life
  7311. consists (1) in procuring a provision of energy; (2) in expending it, by
  7312. means of a matter as supple as possible, in directions variable and
  7313. unforeseen.
  7314. Now, whence comes the energy? From the ingested food, for food is a kind
  7315. of explosive, which needs only the spark to discharge the energy it
  7316. stores. Who has made this explosive? The food may be the flesh of an
  7317. animal nourished on animals and so on; but, in the end it is to the
  7318. vegetable we always come back. Vegetables alone gather in the solar
  7319. energy, and the animals do but borrow it from them, either directly or
  7320. by some passing it on to others. How then has the plant stored up this
  7321. energy? Chiefly by the chlorophyllian function, a chemicism _sui
  7322. generis_ of which we do not possess the key, and which is probably
  7323. unlike that of our laboratories. The process consists in using solar
  7324. energy to fix the carbon of carbonic acid, and thereby to store this
  7325. energy as we should store that of a water-carrier by employing him to
  7326. fill an elevated reservoir: the water, once brought up, can set in
  7327. motion a mill or a turbine, as we will and when we will. Each atom of
  7328. carbon fixed represents something like the elevation of the weight of
  7329. water, or like the stretching of an elastic thread uniting the carbon to
  7330. the oxygen in the carbonic acid. The elastic is relaxed, the weight
  7331. falls back again, in short the energy held in reserve is restored, when,
  7332. by a simple release, the carbon is permitted to rejoin its oxygen.
  7333. So that all life, animal and vegetable, seems in its essence like an
  7334. effort to accumulate energy and then to let it flow into flexible
  7335. channels, changeable in shape, at the end of which it will accomplish
  7336. infinitely varied kinds of work. That is what the _vital impetus_,
  7337. passing through matter, would fain do all at once. It would succeed, no
  7338. doubt, if its power were unlimited, or if some reinforcement could come
  7339. to it from without. But the impetus is finite, and it has been given
  7340. once for all. It cannot overcome all obstacles. The movement it starts
  7341. is sometimes turned aside, sometimes divided, always opposed; and the
  7342. evolution of the organized world is the unrolling of this conflict. The
  7343. first great scission that had to be effected was that of the two
  7344. kingdoms, vegetable and animal, which thus happen to be mutually
  7345. complementary, without, however, any agreement having been made between
  7346. them. It is not for the animal that the plant accumulates energy, it is
  7347. for its own consumption; but its expenditure on itself is less
  7348. discontinuous, and less concentrated, and therefore less efficacious,
  7349. than was required by the initial impetus of life, essentially directed
  7350. toward free actions: the same organism could not with equal force
  7351. sustain the two functions at once, of gradual storage and sudden use. Of
  7352. themselves, therefore, and without any external intervention, simply by
  7353. the effect of the duality of the tendency involved in the original
  7354. impetus and of the resistance opposed by matter to this impetus, the
  7355. organisms leaned some in the first direction, others in the second. To
  7356. this scission there succeeded many others. Hence the diverging lines of
  7357. evolution, at least what is essential in them. But we must take into
  7358. account retrogressions, arrests, accidents of every kind. And we must
  7359. remember, above all, that each species behaves as if the general
  7360. movement of life stopped at it instead of passing through it. It thinks
  7361. only of itself, it lives only for itself. Hence the numberless
  7362. struggles that we behold in nature. Hence a discord, striking and
  7363. terrible, but for which the original principle of life must not be held
  7364. responsible.
  7365. The part played by contingency in evolution is therefore great.
  7366. Contingent, generally, are the forms adopted, or rather invented.
  7367. Contingent, relative to the obstacles encountered in a given place and
  7368. at a given moment, is the dissociation of the primordial tendency into
  7369. such and such complementary tendencies which create divergent lines of
  7370. evolution. Contingent the arrests and set-backs; contingent, in large
  7371. measure, the adaptations. Two things only are necessary: (1) a gradual
  7372. accumulation of energy; (2) an elastic canalization of this energy in
  7373. variable and indeterminable directions, at the end of which are free
  7374. acts.
  7375. This twofold result has been obtained in a particular way on our planet.
  7376. But it might have been obtained by entirely different means. It was not
  7377. necessary that life should fix its choice mainly upon the carbon of
  7378. carbonic acid. What was essential for it was to store solar energy; but,
  7379. instead of asking the sun to separate, for instance, atoms of oxygen and
  7380. carbon, it might (theoretically at least, and, apart from practical
  7381. difficulties possibly insurmountable) have put forth other chemical
  7382. elements, which would then have had to be associated or dissociated by
  7383. entirely different physical means. And if the element characteristic of
  7384. the substances that supply energy to the organism had been other than
  7385. carbon, the element characteristic of the plastic substances would
  7386. probably have been other than nitrogen, and the chemistry of living
  7387. bodies would then have been radically different from what it is. The
  7388. result would have been living forms without any analogy to those we
  7389. know, whose anatomy would have been different, whose physiology also
  7390. would have been different. Alone, the sensori-motor function would have
  7391. been preserved, if not in its mechanism, at least in its effects. It is
  7392. therefore probable that life goes on in other planets, in other solar
  7393. systems also, under forms of which we have no idea, in physical
  7394. conditions to which it seems to us, from the point of view of our
  7395. physiology, to be absolutely opposed. If its essential aim is to catch
  7396. up usable energy in order to expend it in explosive actions, it probably
  7397. chooses, in each solar system and on each planet, as it does on the
  7398. earth, the fittest means to get this result in the circumstances with
  7399. which it is confronted. That is at least what reasoning by analogy leads
  7400. to, and we use analogy the wrong way when we declare life to be
  7401. impossible wherever the circumstances with which it is confronted are
  7402. other than those on the earth. The truth is that life is possible
  7403. wherever energy descends the incline indicated by Carnot's law and where
  7404. a cause of inverse direction can retard the descent--that is to say,
  7405. probably, in all the worlds suspended from all the stars. We go further:
  7406. it is not even necessary that life should be concentrated and determined
  7407. in organisms properly so called, that is, in definite bodies presenting
  7408. to the flow of energy ready-made though elastic canals. It can be
  7409. conceived (although it can hardly be imagined) that energy might be
  7410. saved up, and then expended on varying lines running across a matter not
  7411. yet solidified. Every essential of life would still be there, since
  7412. there would still be slow accumulation of energy and sudden release.
  7413. There would hardly be more difference between this vitality, vague and
  7414. formless, and the definite vitality we know, than there is, in our
  7415. psychical life, between the state of dream and the state of waking. Such
  7416. may have been the condition of life in our nebula before the
  7417. condensation of matter was complete, if it be true that life springs
  7418. forward at the very moment when, as the effect of an inverse movement,
  7419. the nebular matter appears.
  7420. It is therefore conceivable that life might have assumed a totally
  7421. different outward appearance and designed forms very different from
  7422. those we know. With another chemical substratum, in other physical
  7423. conditions, the impulsion would have remained the same, but it would
  7424. have split up very differently in course of progress; and the whole
  7425. would have traveled another road--whether shorter or longer who can
  7426. tell? In any case, in the entire series of living beings no term would
  7427. have been what it now is. Now, was it necessary that there should be a
  7428. series, or terms? Why should not the unique impetus have been impressed
  7429. on a unique body, which might have gone on evolving?
  7430. This question arises, no doubt, from the comparison of life to an
  7431. impetus. And it must be compared to an impetus, because no image
  7432. borrowed from the physical world can give more nearly the idea of it.
  7433. But it is only an image. In reality, life is of the psychological order,
  7434. and it is of the essence of the psychical to enfold a confused plurality
  7435. of interpenetrating terms. In space, and in space only, is distinct
  7436. multiplicity possible: a point is absolutely external to another point.
  7437. But pure and empty unity, also, is met with only in space; it is that of
  7438. a mathematical point. Abstract unity and abstract multiplicity are
  7439. determinations of space or categories of the understanding, whichever we
  7440. will, spatiality and intellectuality being molded on each other. But
  7441. what is of psychical nature cannot entirely correspond with space, nor
  7442. enter perfectly into the categories of the understanding. Is my own
  7443. person, at a given moment, one or manifold? If I declare it one, inner
  7444. voices arise and protest--those of the sensations, feelings, ideas,
  7445. among which my individuality is distributed. But, if I make it
  7446. distinctly manifold, my consciousness rebels quite as strongly; it
  7447. affirms that my sensations, my feelings, my thoughts are abstractions
  7448. which I effect on myself, and that each of my states implies all the
  7449. others. I am then (we must adopt the language of the understanding,
  7450. since only the understanding has a language) a unity that is multiple
  7451. and a multiplicity that is one;[91] but unity and multiplicity are only
  7452. views of my personality taken by an understanding that directs its
  7453. categories at me; I enter neither into one nor into the other nor into
  7454. both at once, although both, united, may give a fair imitation of the
  7455. mutual interpenetration and continuity that I find at the base of my own
  7456. self. Such is my inner life, and such also is life in general. While, in
  7457. its contact with matter, life is comparable to an impulsion or an
  7458. impetus, regarded in itself it is an immensity of potentiality, a mutual
  7459. encroachment of thousands and thousands of tendencies which nevertheless
  7460. are "thousands and thousands" only when once regarded as outside of each
  7461. other, that is, when spatialized. Contact with matter is what determines
  7462. this dissociation. Matter divides actually what was but potentially
  7463. manifold; and, in this sense, individuation is in part the work of
  7464. matter, in part the result of life's own inclination. Thus, a poetic
  7465. sentiment, which bursts into distinct verses, lines and words, may be
  7466. said to have already contained this multiplicity of individuated
  7467. elements, and yet, in fact, it is the materiality of language that
  7468. creates it.
  7469. But through the words, lines and verses runs the simple inspiration
  7470. which is the whole poem. So, among the dissociated individuals, one
  7471. life goes on moving: everywhere the tendency to individualize is opposed
  7472. and at the same time completed by an antagonistic and complementary
  7473. tendency to associate, as if the manifold unity of life, drawn in the
  7474. direction of multiplicity, made so much the more effort to withdraw
  7475. itself on to itself. A part is no sooner detached than it tends to
  7476. reunite itself, if not to all the rest, at least to what is nearest to
  7477. it. Hence, throughout the whole realm of life, a balancing between
  7478. individuation and association. Individuals join together into a society;
  7479. but the society, as soon as formed, tends to melt the associated
  7480. individuals into a new organism, so as to become itself an individual,
  7481. able in its turn to be part and parcel of a new association. At the
  7482. lowest degree of the scale of organisms we already find veritable
  7483. associations, microbial colonies, and in these associations, according
  7484. to a recent work, a tendency to individuate by the constitution of a
  7485. nucleus.[92] The same tendency is met with again at a higher stage, in
  7486. the protophytes, which, once having quitted the parent cell by way of
  7487. division, remain united to each other by the gelatinous substance that
  7488. surrounds them--also in those protozoa which begin by mingling their
  7489. pseudopodia and end by welding themselves together. The "colonial"
  7490. theory of the genesis of higher organisms is well known. The protozoa,
  7491. consisting of one single cell, are supposed to have formed, by
  7492. assemblage, aggregates which, relating themselves together in their
  7493. turn, have given rise to aggregates of aggregates; so organisms more and
  7494. more complicated, and also more and more differentiated, are born of the
  7495. association of organisms barely differentiated and elementary.[93] In
  7496. this extreme form, the theory is open to grave objections: more and
  7497. more the idea seems to be gaining ground, that polyzoism is an
  7498. exceptional and abnormal fact.[94] But it is none the less true that
  7499. things happen _as if_ every higher organism was born of an association
  7500. of cells that have subdivided the work between them. Very probably it is
  7501. not the cells that have made the individual by means of association; it
  7502. is rather the individual that has made the cells by means of
  7503. dissociation.[95] But this itself reveals to us, in the genesis of the
  7504. individual, a haunting of the social form, as if the individual could
  7505. develop only on the condition that its substance should be split up into
  7506. elements having themselves an appearance of individuality and united
  7507. among themselves by an appearance of sociality. There are numerous cases
  7508. in which nature seems to hesitate between the two forms, and to ask
  7509. herself if she shall make a society or an individual. The slightest push
  7510. is enough, then, to make the balance weigh on one side or the other. If
  7511. we take an infusorian sufficiently large, such as the Stentor, and cut
  7512. it into two halves each containing a part of the nucleus, each of the
  7513. two halves will generate an independent Stentor; but if we divide it
  7514. incompletely, so that a protoplasmic communication is left between the
  7515. two halves, we shall see them execute, each from its side, corresponding
  7516. movements: so that in this case it is enough that a thread should be
  7517. maintained or cut in order that life should affect the social or the
  7518. individual form. Thus, in rudimentary organisms consisting of a single
  7519. cell, we already find that the apparent individuality of the whole is
  7520. the composition of an _undefined_ number of potential individualities
  7521. potentially associated. But, from top to bottom of the series of living
  7522. beings, the same law is manifested. And it is this that we express when
  7523. we say that unity and multiplicity are categories of inert matter, that
  7524. the vital impetus is neither pure unity nor pure multiplicity, and that
  7525. if the matter to which it communicates itself compels it to choose one
  7526. of the two, its choice will never be definitive: it will leap from one
  7527. to the other indefinitely. The evolution of life in the double direction
  7528. of individuality and association has therefore nothing accidental about
  7529. it: it is due to the very nature of life.
  7530. Essential also is the progress to reflexion. If our analysis is correct,
  7531. it is consciousness, or rather supra-consciousness, that is at the
  7532. origin of life. Consciousness, or supra-consciousness, is the name for
  7533. the rocket whose extinguished fragments fall back as matter;
  7534. consciousness, again, is the name for that which subsists of the rocket
  7535. itself, passing through the fragments and lighting them up into
  7536. organisms. But this consciousness, which is a _need of creation_, is
  7537. made manifest to itself only where creation is possible. It lies dormant
  7538. when life is condemned to automatism; it wakens as soon as the
  7539. possibility of a choice is restored. That is why, in organisms
  7540. unprovided with a nervous system, it varies according to the power of
  7541. locomotion and of deformation of which the organism disposes. And in
  7542. animals with a nervous system, it is proportional to the complexity of
  7543. the switchboard on which the paths called sensory and the paths called
  7544. motor intersect--that is, of the brain. How must this solidarity between
  7545. the organism and consciousness be understood?
  7546. We will not dwell here on a point that we have dealt with in former
  7547. works. Let us merely recall that a theory such as that according to
  7548. which consciousness is attached to certain neurons, and is thrown off
  7549. from their work like a phosphorescence, may be accepted by the scientist
  7550. for the detail of analysis; it is a convenient mode of expression. But
  7551. it is nothing else. In reality, a living being is a centre of action. It
  7552. represents a certain sum of contingency entering into the world, that is
  7553. to say, a certain quantity of possible action--a quantity variable with
  7554. individuals and especially with species. The nervous system of an animal
  7555. marks out the flexible lines on which its action will run (although the
  7556. potential energy is accumulated in the muscles rather than in the
  7557. nervous system itself); its nervous centres indicate, by their
  7558. development and their configuration, the more or less extended choice it
  7559. will have among more or less numerous and complicated actions. Now,
  7560. since the awakening of consciousness in a living creature is the more
  7561. complete, the greater the latitude of choice allowed to it and the
  7562. larger the amount of action bestowed upon it, it is clear that the
  7563. development of consciousness will appear to be dependent on that of the
  7564. nervous centres. On the other hand, every state of consciousness being,
  7565. in one aspect of it, a question put to the motor activity and even the
  7566. beginning of a reply, there is no psychical event that does not imply
  7567. the entry into play of the cortical mechanisms. Everything seems,
  7568. therefore, to happen _as if_ consciousness sprang from the brain, and
  7569. _as if_ the detail of conscious activity were modeled on that of the
  7570. cerebral activity. In reality, consciousness does not spring from the
  7571. brain; but brain and consciousness correspond because equally they
  7572. measure, the one by the complexity of its structure and the other by the
  7573. intensity of its awareness, the quantity of _choice_ that the living
  7574. being has at its disposal.
  7575. It is precisely because a cerebral state expresses simply what there is
  7576. of nascent action in the corresponding psychical state, that the
  7577. psychical state tells us more than the cerebral state. The consciousness
  7578. of a living being, as we have tried to prove elsewhere, is inseparable
  7579. from its brain in the sense in which a sharp knife is inseparable from
  7580. its edge: the brain is the sharp edge by which consciousness cuts into
  7581. the compact tissue of events, but the brain is no more coextensive with
  7582. consciousness than the edge is with the knife. Thus, from the fact that
  7583. two brains, like that of the ape and that of the man, are very much
  7584. alike, we cannot conclude that the corresponding consciousnesses are
  7585. comparable or commensurable.
  7586. But the two brains may perhaps be less alike than we suppose. How can we
  7587. help being struck by the fact that, while man is capable of learning any
  7588. sort of exercise, of constructing any sort of object, in short of
  7589. acquiring any kind of motor habit whatsoever, the faculty of combining
  7590. new movements is strictly limited in the best-endowed animal, even in
  7591. the ape? The cerebral characteristic of man is there. The human brain is
  7592. made, like every brain, to set up motor mechanisms and to enable us to
  7593. choose among them, at any instant, the one we shall put in motion by the
  7594. pull of a trigger. But it differs from other brains in this, that the
  7595. number of mechanisms it can set up, and consequently the choice that it
  7596. gives as to which among them shall be released, is unlimited. Now, from
  7597. the limited to the unlimited there is all the distance between the
  7598. closed and the open. It is not a difference of degree, but of kind.
  7599. Radical therefore, also, is the difference between animal consciousness,
  7600. even the most intelligent, and human consciousness. For consciousness
  7601. corresponds exactly to the living being's power of choice; it is
  7602. coextensive with the fringe of possible action that surrounds the real
  7603. action: consciousness is synonymous with invention and with freedom.
  7604. Now, in the animal, invention is never anything but a variation on the
  7605. theme of routine. Shut up in the habits of the species, it succeeds, no
  7606. doubt, in enlarging them by its individual initiative; but it escapes
  7607. automatism only for an instant, for just the time to create a new
  7608. automatism. The gates of its prison close as soon as they are opened; by
  7609. pulling at its chain it succeeds only in stretching it. With man,
  7610. consciousness breaks the chain. In man, and in man alone, it sets itself
  7611. free. The whole history of life until man has been that of the effort of
  7612. consciousness to raise matter, and of the more or less complete
  7613. overwhelming of consciousness by the matter which has fallen back on it.
  7614. The enterprise was paradoxical, if, indeed, we may speak here otherwise
  7615. than by metaphor of enterprise and of effort. It was to create with
  7616. matter, which is necessity itself, an instrument of freedom, to make a
  7617. machine which should triumph over mechanism, and to use the determinism
  7618. of nature to pass through the meshes of the net which this very
  7619. determinism had spread. But, everywhere except in man, consciousness has
  7620. let itself be caught in the net whose meshes it tried to pass through:
  7621. it has remained the captive of the mechanisms it has set up. Automatism,
  7622. which it tries to draw in the direction of freedom, winds about it and
  7623. drags it down. It has not the power to escape, because the energy it has
  7624. provided for acts is almost all employed in maintaining the infinitely
  7625. subtle and essentially unstable equilibrium into which it has brought
  7626. matter. But man not only maintains his machine, he succeeds in using it
  7627. as he pleases. Doubtless he owes this to the superiority of his brain,
  7628. which enables him to build an unlimited number of motor mechanisms, to
  7629. oppose new habits to the old ones unceasingly, and, by dividing
  7630. automatism against itself, to rule it. He owes it to his language,
  7631. which furnishes consciousness with an immaterial body in which to
  7632. incarnate itself and thus exempts it from dwelling exclusively on
  7633. material bodies, whose flux would soon drag it along and finally swallow
  7634. it up. He owes it to social life, which stores and preserves efforts as
  7635. language stores thought, fixes thereby a mean level to which individuals
  7636. must raise themselves at the outset, and by this initial stimulation
  7637. prevents the average man from slumbering and drives the superior man to
  7638. mount still higher. But our brain, our society, and our language are
  7639. only the external and various signs of one and the same internal
  7640. superiority. They tell, each after its manner, the unique, exceptional
  7641. success which life has won at a given moment of its evolution. They
  7642. express the difference of kind, and not only of degree, which separates
  7643. man from the rest of the animal world. They let us guess that, while at
  7644. the end of the vast spring-board from which life has taken its leap, all
  7645. the others have stepped down, finding the cord stretched too high, man
  7646. alone has cleared the obstacle.
  7647. It is in this quite special sense that man is the "term" and the "end"
  7648. of evolution. Life, we have said, transcends finality as it transcends
  7649. the other categories. It is essentially a current sent through matter,
  7650. drawing from it what it can. There has not, therefore, properly
  7651. speaking, been any project or plan. On the other hand, it is abundantly
  7652. evident that the rest of nature is not for the sake of man: we struggle
  7653. like the other species, we have struggled against other species.
  7654. Moreover, if the evolution of life had encountered other accidents in
  7655. its course, if, thereby, the current of life had been otherwise divided,
  7656. we should have been, physically and morally, far different from what we
  7657. are. For these various reasons it would be wrong to regard humanity,
  7658. such as we have it before our eyes, as pre-figured in the evolutionary
  7659. movement. It cannot even be said to be the outcome of the whole of
  7660. evolution, for evolution has been accomplished on several divergent
  7661. lines, and while the human species is at the end of one of them, other
  7662. lines have been followed with other species at their end. It is in a
  7663. quite different sense that we hold humanity to be the ground of
  7664. evolution.
  7665. From our point of view, life appears in its entirety as an immense wave
  7666. which, starting from a centre, spreads outwards, and which on almost the
  7667. whole of its circumference is stopped and converted into oscillation: at
  7668. one single point the obstacle has been forced, the impulsion has passed
  7669. freely. It is this freedom that the human form registers. Everywhere but
  7670. in man, consciousness has had to come to a stand; in man alone it has
  7671. kept on its way. Man, then, continues the vital movement indefinitely,
  7672. although he does not draw along with him all that life carries in
  7673. itself. On other lines of evolution there have traveled other tendencies
  7674. which life implied, and of which, since everything interpenetrates, man
  7675. has, doubtless, kept something, but of which he has kept only very
  7676. little. _It is as if a vague and formless being, whom we may call, as we
  7677. will_, man _or_ superman, _had sought to realize himself, and had
  7678. succeeded only by abandoning a part of himself on the way_. The losses
  7679. are represented by the rest of the animal world, and even by the
  7680. vegetable world, at least in what these have that is positive and above
  7681. the accidents of evolution.
  7682. From this point of view, the discordances of which nature offers us the
  7683. spectacle are singularly weakened. The organized world as a whole
  7684. becomes as the soil on which was to grow either man himself or a being
  7685. who morally must resemble him. The animals, however distant they may be
  7686. from our species, however hostile to it, have none the less been useful
  7687. traveling companions, on whom consciousness has unloaded whatever
  7688. encumbrances it was dragging along, and who have enabled it to rise, in
  7689. man, to heights from which it sees an unlimited horizon open again
  7690. before it.
  7691. It is true that it has not only abandoned cumbersome baggage on the way;
  7692. it has also had to give up valuable goods. Consciousness, in man, is
  7693. pre-eminently intellect. It might have been, it ought, so it seems, to
  7694. have been also intuition. Intuition and intellect represent two opposite
  7695. directions of the work of consciousness: intuition goes in the very
  7696. direction of life, intellect goes in the inverse direction, and thus
  7697. finds itself naturally in accordance with the movement of matter. A
  7698. complete and perfect humanity would be that in which these two forms of
  7699. conscious activity should attain their full development. And, between
  7700. this humanity and ours, we may conceive any number of possible stages,
  7701. corresponding to all the degrees imaginable of intelligence and of
  7702. intuition. In this lies the part of contingency in the mental structure
  7703. of our species. A different evolution might have led to a humanity
  7704. either more intellectual still or more intuitive. In the humanity of
  7705. which we are a part, intuition is, in fact, almost completely sacrificed
  7706. to intellect. It seems that to conquer matter, and to reconquer its own
  7707. self, consciousness has had to exhaust the best part of its power. This
  7708. conquest, in the particular conditions in which it has been
  7709. accomplished, has required that consciousness should adapt itself to the
  7710. habits of matter and concentrate all its attention on them, in fact
  7711. determine itself more especially as intellect. Intuition is there,
  7712. however, but vague and above all discontinuous. It is a lamp almost
  7713. extinguished, which only glimmers now and then, for a few moments at
  7714. most. But it glimmers wherever a vital interest is at stake. On our
  7715. personality, on our liberty, on the place we occupy in the whole of
  7716. nature, on our origin and perhaps also on our destiny, it throws a light
  7717. feeble and vacillating, but which none the less pierces the darkness of
  7718. the night in which the intellect leaves us.
  7719. These fleeting intuitions, which light up their object only at distant
  7720. intervals, philosophy ought to seize, first to sustain them, then to
  7721. expand them and so unite them together. The more it advances in this
  7722. work, the more will it perceive that intuition is mind itself, and, in a
  7723. certain sense, life itself: the intellect has been cut out of it by a
  7724. process resembling that which has generated matter. Thus is revealed the
  7725. unity of the spiritual life. We recognize it only when we place
  7726. ourselves in intuition in order to go from intuition to the intellect,
  7727. for from the intellect we shall never pass to intuition.
  7728. Philosophy introduces us thus into the spiritual life. And it shows us
  7729. at the same time the relation of the life of the spirit to that of the
  7730. body. The great error of the doctrines on the spirit has been the idea
  7731. that by isolating the spiritual life from all the rest, by suspending it
  7732. in space as high as possible above the earth, they were placing it
  7733. beyond attack, as if they were not thereby simply exposing it to be
  7734. taken as an effect of mirage! Certainly they are right to listen to
  7735. conscience when conscience affirms human freedom; but the intellect is
  7736. there, which says that the cause determines its effect, that like
  7737. conditions like, that all is repeated and that all is given. They are
  7738. right to believe in the absolute reality of the person and in his
  7739. independence toward matter; but science is there, which shows the
  7740. interdependence of conscious life and cerebral activity. They are right
  7741. to attribute to man a privileged place in nature, to hold that the
  7742. distance is infinite between the animal and man; but the history of life
  7743. is there, which makes us witness the genesis of species by gradual
  7744. transformation, and seems thus to reintegrate man in animality. When a
  7745. strong instinct assures the probability of personal survival, they are
  7746. right not to close their ears to its voice; but if there exist "souls"
  7747. capable of an independent life, whence do they come? When, how and why
  7748. do they enter into this body which we see arise, quite naturally, from a
  7749. mixed cell derived from the bodies of its two parents? All these
  7750. questions will remain unanswered, a philosophy of intuition will be a
  7751. negation of science, will be sooner or later swept away by science, if
  7752. it does not resolve to see the life of the body just where it really is,
  7753. on the road that leads to the life of the spirit. But it will then no
  7754. longer have to do with definite living beings. Life as a whole, from the
  7755. initial impulsion that thrust it into the world, will appear as a wave
  7756. which rises, and which is opposed by the descending movement of matter.
  7757. On the greater part of its surface, at different heights, the current is
  7758. converted by matter into a vortex. At one point alone it passes freely,
  7759. dragging with it the obstacle which will weigh on its progress but will
  7760. not stop it. At this point is humanity; it is our privileged situation.
  7761. On the other hand, this rising wave is consciousness, and, like all
  7762. consciousness, it includes potentialities without number which
  7763. interpenetrate and to which consequently neither the category of unity
  7764. nor that of multiplicity is appropriate, made as they both are for inert
  7765. matter. The matter that it bears along with it, and in the interstices
  7766. of which it inserts itself, alone can divide it into distinct
  7767. individualities. On flows the current, running through human
  7768. generations, subdividing itself into individuals. This subdivision was
  7769. vaguely indicated in it, but could not have been made clear without
  7770. matter. Thus souls are continually being created, which, nevertheless,
  7771. in a certain sense pre-existed. They are nothing else than the little
  7772. rills into which the great river of life divides itself, flowing through
  7773. the body of humanity. The movement of the stream is distinct from the
  7774. river bed, although it must adopt its winding course. Consciousness is
  7775. distinct from the organism it animates, although it must undergo its
  7776. vicissitudes. As the possible actions which a state of consciousness
  7777. indicates are at every instant beginning to be carried out in the
  7778. nervous centres, the brain underlines at every instant the motor
  7779. indications of the state of consciousness; but the interdependency of
  7780. consciousness and brain is limited to this; the destiny of consciousness
  7781. is not bound up on that account with the destiny of cerebral matter.
  7782. Finally, consciousness is essentially free; it is freedom itself; but it
  7783. cannot pass through matter without settling on it, without adapting
  7784. itself to it: this adaptation is what we call intellectuality; and the
  7785. intellect, turning itself back toward active, that is to say free,
  7786. consciousness, naturally makes it enter into the conceptual forms into
  7787. which it is accustomed to see matter fit. It will therefore always
  7788. perceive freedom in the form of necessity; it will always neglect the
  7789. part of novelty or of creation inherent in the free act; it will always
  7790. substitute for action itself an imitation artificial, approximative,
  7791. obtained by compounding the old with the old and the same with the same.
  7792. Thus, to the eyes of a philosophy that attempts to reabsorb intellect in
  7793. intuition, many difficulties vanish or become light. But such a doctrine
  7794. does not only facilitate speculation; it gives us also more power to act
  7795. and to live. For, with it, we feel ourselves no longer isolated in
  7796. humanity, humanity no longer seems isolated in the nature that it
  7797. dominates. As the smallest grain of dust is bound up with our entire
  7798. solar system, drawn along with it in that undivided movement of descent
  7799. which is materiality itself, so all organized beings, from the humblest
  7800. to the highest, from the first origins of life to the time in which we
  7801. are, and in all places as in all times, do but evidence a single
  7802. impulsion, the inverse of the movement of matter, and in itself
  7803. indivisible. All the living hold together, and all yield to the same
  7804. tremendous push. The animal takes its stand on the plant, man bestrides
  7805. animality, and the whole of humanity, in space and in time, is one
  7806. immense army galloping beside and before and behind each of us in an
  7807. overwhelming charge able to beat down every resistance and clear the
  7808. most formidable obstacles, perhaps even death.
  7809. FOOTNOTES:
  7810. [Footnote 78: We have developed this point in _Matière et mémoire_,
  7811. chaps. ii. and iii., notably pp. 78-80 and 169-186.]
  7812. [Footnote 79: Faraday, _A Speculation concerning Electric Conduction_
  7813. (_Philosophical Magazine_, 3d. series, vol. xxiv.).]
  7814. [Footnote 80: Our comparison does no more than develop the content of
  7815. the term [Greek: logos], as Plotinus understands it. For while the
  7816. [Greek: logos] of this philosopher is a generating and informing power,
  7817. an aspect or a fragment of the [Greek: psychê], on the other hand
  7818. Plotinus sometimes speaks of it as of a _discourse_. More generally, the
  7819. relation that we establish in the present chapter between "extension"
  7820. and "detension" resembles in some aspects that which Plotinus supposes
  7821. (some developments of which must have inspired M. Ravaisson) when he
  7822. makes extension not indeed an inversion of original Being, but an
  7823. enfeeblement of its essence, one of the last stages of the procession,
  7824. (see in particular, _Enn._ IV. iii. 9-11, and III. vi. 17-18). Yet
  7825. ancient philosophy did not see what consequences would result from this
  7826. for mathematics, for Plotinus, like Plato, erected mathematical essences
  7827. into absolute realities. Above all, it suffered itself to be deceived by
  7828. the purely superficial analogy of duration with extension. It treated
  7829. the one as it treated the other, regarding change as a degradation of
  7830. immutability, the sensible as a fall from the intelligible. Whence, as
  7831. we shall show in the next chapter, a philosophy which fails to recognize
  7832. the real function and scope of the intellect.]
  7833. [Footnote 81: Bastian, _The Brain as an Organ of the Mind_, pp. 214-16.]
  7834. [Footnote 82: We have dwelt on this point in a former work. See the
  7835. _Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience_, Paris, 1889, pp.
  7836. 155-160.]
  7837. [Footnote 83: _Op. cit._ chaps. i. and ii. _passim_.]
  7838. [Footnote 84: Cf. especially the profound studies of M. Ed. Le Roy in
  7839. the _Revue de métaph. et de morale_.]
  7840. [Footnote 85: _Matière et mémoire_, chapters iii. and iv.]
  7841. [Footnote 86: See in particular, _Phys._, iv. 215 a 2; v. 230 b 12;
  7842. viii. 255 a 2; and _De Caelo_, iv. 1-5; ii. 296 b 27; iv. 308 a 34.]
  7843. [Footnote 87: _De Caelo_, iv. 310 a 34 [Greek: to d' eis ton autou topon
  7844. pherethai hekaoton to eis to autou eidos esti pheresthai].]
  7845. [Footnote 88: On these differences of quality see the work of Duhem,
  7846. _L'Évolution de la mécanique_, Paris, 1905, pp. 197 ff.]
  7847. [Footnote 89: Boltzmann, _Vorlesungen über Gastheorie_, Leipzig, 1898,
  7848. pp. 253 ff.]
  7849. [Footnote 90: In a book rich in facts and in ideas (_La Dissolution
  7850. opposée a l'évolution_, Paris, 1899), M. André Lalande shows us
  7851. everything going towards death, in spite of the momentary resistance
  7852. which organisms seem to oppose.--But, even from the side of unorganized
  7853. matter, have we the right to extend to the entire universe
  7854. considerations drawn from the present state of our solar system? Beside
  7855. the worlds which are dying, there are without doubt worlds that are
  7856. being born. On the other hand, in the organized world, the death of
  7857. individuals does not seem at all like a diminution of "life in general,"
  7858. or like a necessity which life submits to reluctantly. As has been more
  7859. than once remarked, life has never made an effort to prolong
  7860. indefinitely the existence of the individual, although on so many other
  7861. points it has made so many successful efforts. Everything is _as if_
  7862. this death had been willed, or at least accepted, for the greater
  7863. progress of life in general.]
  7864. [Footnote 91: We have dwelt on this point in an article entitled
  7865. "Introduction à la métaphysique" (_Revue de métaphysique et de morale_,
  7866. January, 1903, pp. 1-25).]
  7867. [Footnote 92: Cf. a paper written (in Russian) by Serkovski, and
  7868. reviewed in the _Année biologique_, 1898, p. 317.]
  7869. [Footnote 93: Ed. Perrier, _Les Colonies animales_, Paris, 1897 (2nd
  7870. edition).]
  7871. [Footnote 94: Delage, _L'Hérédité_, 2nd edition, Paris, 1903, p. 97. Cf.
  7872. by the same author, "La Conception polyzoïque des êtres" (_Revue
  7873. scientifique_, 1896, pp. 641-653).]
  7874. [Footnote 95: This is the theory maintained by Kunstler, Delage,
  7875. Sedgwick, Labbé, etc. Its development, with bibliographical references,
  7876. will be found in the work of Busquet, _Les êtres vivants_, Paris, 1899.]
  7877. CHAPTER IV
  7878. THE CINEMATOGRAPHICAL MECHANISM OF THOUGHT AND THE MECHANISTIC
  7879. ILLUSION--A GLANCE AT THE HISTORY OF SYSTEMS[96]--REAL BECOMING AND
  7880. FALSE EVOLUTIONISM.
  7881. It remains for us to examine in themselves two theoretical illusions
  7882. which we have frequently met with before, but whose consequences rather
  7883. than principle have hitherto concerned us. Such is the object of the
  7884. present chapter. It will afford us the opportunity of removing certain
  7885. objections, of clearing up certain misunderstandings, and, above all, of
  7886. defining more precisely, by contrasting it with others, a philosophy
  7887. which sees in duration the very stuff of reality.
  7888. Matter or mind, reality has appeared to us as a perpetual becoming. It
  7889. makes itself or it unmakes itself, but it is never something made. Such
  7890. is the intuition that we have of mind when we draw aside the veil which
  7891. is interposed between our consciousness and ourselves. This, also, is
  7892. what our intellect and senses themselves would show us of matter, if
  7893. they could obtain a direct and disinterested idea of it. But,
  7894. preoccupied before everything with the necessities of action, the
  7895. intellect, like the senses, is limited to taking, at intervals, views
  7896. that are instantaneous and by that very fact immobile of the becoming of
  7897. matter. Consciousness, being in its turn formed on the intellect, sees
  7898. clearly of the inner life what is already made, and only feels
  7899. confusedly the making. Thus, we pluck out of duration those moments that
  7900. interest us, and that we have gathered along its course. These alone we
  7901. retain. And we are right in so doing, while action only is in question.
  7902. But when, in _speculating_ on the _nature_ of the real, we go on
  7903. regarding it as our practical interest requires us to regard it, we
  7904. become unable to perceive the true evolution, the radical becoming. Of
  7905. becoming we perceive only states, of duration only instants, and even
  7906. when we speak of duration and of becoming, it is of another thing that
  7907. we are thinking. Such is the most striking of the two illusions we wish
  7908. to examine. It consists in supposing that we can think the unstable by
  7909. means of the stable, the moving by means of the immobile.
  7910. The other illusion is near akin to the first. It has the same origin,
  7911. being also due to the fact that we import into speculation a procedure
  7912. made for practice. All action aims at getting something that we feel the
  7913. want of, or at creating something that does not yet exist. In this very
  7914. special sense, it fills a void, and goes from the empty to the full,
  7915. from an absence to a presence, from the unreal to the real. Now the
  7916. unreality which is here in question is purely relative to the direction
  7917. in which our attention is engaged, for we are immersed in realities and
  7918. cannot pass out of them; only, if the present reality is not the one we
  7919. are seeking, we speak of the _absence_ of this sought-for reality
  7920. wherever we find the _presence_ of another. We thus express what we have
  7921. as a function of what we want. This is quite legitimate in the sphere of
  7922. action. But, whether we will or no, we keep to this way of speaking,
  7923. and also of thinking, when we speculate on the nature of things
  7924. independently of the interest they have for us. Thus arises the second
  7925. of the two illusions. We propose to examine this first. It is due, like
  7926. the other, to the static habits that our intellect contracts when it
  7927. prepares our action on things. Just as we pass through the immobile to
  7928. go to the moving, so we make use of the void in order to think the full.
  7929. We have met with this illusion already in dealing with the fundamental
  7930. problem of knowledge. The question, we then said, is to know why there
  7931. is order, and not disorder, in things. But the question has meaning only
  7932. if we suppose that disorder, understood as an absence of order, is
  7933. possible, or imaginable, or conceivable. Now, it is only order that is
  7934. real; but, as order can take two forms, and as the presence of the one
  7935. may be said to consist in the absence of the other, we speak of disorder
  7936. whenever we have before us that one of the two orders for which we are
  7937. not looking. The idea of disorder is then entirely practical. It
  7938. corresponds to the disappointment of a certain expectation, and it does
  7939. not denote the absence of all order, but only the presence of that order
  7940. which does not offer us actual interest. So that whenever we try to deny
  7941. order completely, absolutely, we find that we are leaping from one kind
  7942. of order to the other indefinitely, and that the supposed suppression of
  7943. the one and the other implies the presence of the two. Indeed, if we go
  7944. on, and persist in shutting our eyes to this movement of the mind and
  7945. all it involves, we are no longer dealing with an idea; all that is left
  7946. of disorder is a word. Thus the problem of knowledge is complicated, and
  7947. possibly made insoluble, by the idea that order fills a void and that
  7948. its actual presence is superposed on its virtual absence. We go from
  7949. absence to presence, from the void to the full, in virtue of the
  7950. fundamental illusion of our understanding. That is the error of which we
  7951. noticed one consequence in our last chapter. As we then anticipated, we
  7952. must come to close quarters with this error, and finally grapple with
  7953. it. We must face it in itself, in the radically false conception which
  7954. it implies of negation, of the void and of the nought.[97]
  7955. Philosophers have paid little attention to the idea of the nought. And
  7956. yet it is often the hidden spring, the invisible mover of philosophical
  7957. thinking. From the first awakening of reflection, it is this that pushes
  7958. to the fore, right under the eyes of consciousness, the torturing
  7959. problems, the questions that we cannot gaze at without feeling giddy and
  7960. bewildered. I have no sooner commenced to philosophize than I ask myself
  7961. why I exist; and when I take account of the intimate connection in which
  7962. I stand to the rest of the universe, the difficulty is only pushed back,
  7963. for I want to know why the universe exists; and if I refer the universe
  7964. to a Principle immanent or transcendent that supports it or creates it,
  7965. my thought rests on this principle only a few moments, for the same
  7966. problem recurs, this time in its full breadth and generality: Whence
  7967. comes it, and how can it be understood, that anything exists? Even here,
  7968. in the present work, when matter has been defined as a kind of descent,
  7969. this descent as the interruption of a rise, this rise itself as a
  7970. growth, when finally a Principle of creation has been put at the base of
  7971. things, the same question springs up: How--why does this principle exist
  7972. rather than nothing?
  7973. Now, if I push these questions aside and go straight to what hides
  7974. behind them, this is what I find:--Existence appears to me like a
  7975. conquest over nought. I say to myself that there might be, that indeed
  7976. there ought to be, nothing, and I then wonder that there is something.
  7977. Or I represent all reality extended on nothing as on a carpet: at first
  7978. was nothing, and being has come by superaddition to it. Or, yet again,
  7979. if something has always existed, nothing must always have served as its
  7980. substratum or receptacle, and is therefore eternally prior. A glass may
  7981. have always been full, but the liquid it contains nevertheless fills a
  7982. void. In the same way, being may have always been there, but the nought
  7983. which is filled, and, as it were, stopped up by it, pre-exists for it
  7984. none the less, if not in fact at least in right. In short, I cannot get
  7985. rid of the idea that the full is an embroidery on the canvas of the
  7986. void, that being is superimposed on nothing, and that in the idea of
  7987. "nothing" there is _less_ than in that of "something." Hence all the
  7988. mystery.
  7989. It is necessary that this mystery should be cleared up. It is more
  7990. especially necessary, if we put duration and free choice at the base of
  7991. things. For the disdain of metaphysics for all reality that endures
  7992. comes precisely from this, that it reaches being only by passing through
  7993. "not-being," and that an existence which endures seems to it not strong
  7994. enough to conquer non-existence and itself posit itself. It is for this
  7995. reason especially that it is inclined to endow true being with a
  7996. _logical_, and not a psychological nor a physical existence. For the
  7997. nature of a purely logical existence is such that it seems to be
  7998. self-sufficient and to posit itself by the effect alone of the force
  7999. immanent in truth. If I ask myself why bodies or minds exist rather than
  8000. nothing, I find no answer; but that a logical principle, such as A=A,
  8001. should have the power of creating itself, triumphing over the nought
  8002. throughout eternity, seems to me natural. A circle drawn with chalk on
  8003. a blackboard is a thing which needs explanation: this entirely physical
  8004. existence has not by itself wherewith to vanquish non-existence. But the
  8005. "logical essence" of the circle, that is to say, the possibility of
  8006. drawing it according to a certain law--in short, its definition--is a
  8007. thing which appears to me eternal: it has neither place nor date; for
  8008. nowhere, at no moment, has the drawing of a circle begun to be possible.
  8009. Suppose, then, that the principle on which all things rest, and which
  8010. all things manifest possesses an existence of the same nature as that of
  8011. the definition of the circle, or as that of the axiom A=A: the mystery
  8012. of existence vanishes, for the being that is at the base of everything
  8013. posits itself then in eternity, as logic itself does. True, it will cost
  8014. us rather a heavy sacrifice: if the principle of all things exists after
  8015. the manner of a logical axiom or of a mathematical definition, the
  8016. things themselves must go forth from this principle like the
  8017. applications of an axiom or the consequences of a definition, and there
  8018. will no longer be place, either in the things nor in their principle,
  8019. for efficient causality understood in the sense of a free choice. Such
  8020. are precisely the conclusions of a doctrine like that of Spinoza, or
  8021. even that of Leibniz, and such indeed has been their genesis.
  8022. Now, if we could prove that the idea of the nought, in the sense in
  8023. which we take it when we oppose it to that of existence, is a
  8024. pseudo-idea, the problems that are raised around it would become
  8025. pseudo-problems. The hypothesis of an absolute that acts freely, that in
  8026. an eminent sense endures, would no longer raise up intellectual
  8027. prejudices. The road would be cleared for a philosophy more nearly
  8028. approaching intuition, and which would no longer ask the same sacrifices
  8029. of common sense.
  8030. Let us then see what we are thinking about when we speak of "Nothing."
  8031. To represent "Nothing," we must either imagine it or conceive it. Let us
  8032. examine what this image or this idea may be. First, the image.
  8033. I am going to close my eyes, stop my ears, extinguish one by one the
  8034. sensations that come to me from the outer world. Now it is done; all my
  8035. perceptions vanish, the material universe sinks into silence and the
  8036. night.--I subsist, however, and cannot help myself subsisting. I am
  8037. still there, with the organic sensations which come to me from the
  8038. surface and from the interior of my body, with the recollections which
  8039. my past perceptions have left behind them--nay, with the impression,
  8040. most positive and full, of the void I have just made about me. How can I
  8041. suppress all this? How eliminate myself? I can even, it may be, blot out
  8042. and forget my recollections up to my immediate past; but at least I keep
  8043. the consciousness of my present reduced to its extremest poverty, that
  8044. is to say, of the actual state of my body. I will try, however, to do
  8045. away even with this consciousness itself. I will reduce more and more
  8046. the sensations my body sends in to me: now they are almost gone; now
  8047. they are gone, they have disappeared in the night where all things else
  8048. have already died away. But no! At the very instant that my
  8049. consciousness is extinguished, another consciousness lights up--or
  8050. rather, it was already alight: it had arisen the instant before, in
  8051. order to witness the extinction of the first; for the first could
  8052. disappear only for another and in the presence of another. I see myself
  8053. annihilated only if I have already resuscitated myself by an act which
  8054. is positive, however involuntary and unconscious. So, do what I will, I
  8055. am always perceiving something, either from without or from within. When
  8056. I no longer know anything of external objects, it is because I have
  8057. taken refuge in the consciousness that I have of myself. If I abolish
  8058. this inner self, its very abolition becomes an object for an imaginary
  8059. self which now perceives as an external object the self that is dying
  8060. away. Be it external or internal, some object there always is that my
  8061. imagination is representing. My imagination, it is true, can go from one
  8062. to the other, I can by turns imagine a nought of external perception or
  8063. a nought of internal perception, but not both at once, for the absence
  8064. of one consists, at bottom, in the exclusive presence of the other. But,
  8065. from the fact that two relative noughts are imaginable in turn, we
  8066. wrongly conclude that they are imaginable together: a conclusion the
  8067. absurdity of which must be obvious, for we cannot imagine a nought
  8068. without perceiving, at least confusedly, that we are imagining it,
  8069. consequently that we are acting, that we are thinking, and therefore
  8070. that something still subsists.
  8071. The image, then, properly so called, of a suppression of everything is
  8072. never formed by thought. The effort by which we strive to create this
  8073. image simply ends in making us swing to and fro between the vision of an
  8074. outer and that of an inner reality. In this coming and going of our mind
  8075. between the without and the within, there is a point, at equal distance
  8076. from both, in which it seems to us that we no longer perceive the one,
  8077. and that we do not yet perceive the other: it is there that the image of
  8078. "Nothing" is formed. In reality, we then perceive both, having reached
  8079. the point where the two terms come together, and the image of Nothing,
  8080. so defined, is an image full of things, an image that includes at once
  8081. that of the subject and that of the object and, besides, a perpetual
  8082. leaping from one to the other and the refusal ever to come to rest
  8083. finally on either. Evidently this is not the nothing that we can oppose
  8084. to being, and put before or beneath being, for it already includes
  8085. existence in general.
  8086. But we shall be told that, if the representation of Nothing, visible or
  8087. latent, enters into the reasonings of philosophers, it is not as an
  8088. image, but as an idea. It may be agreed that we do not imagine the
  8089. annihilation of everything, but it will be claimed that we can conceive
  8090. it. We conceive a polygon with a thousand sides, said Descartes,
  8091. although we do not see it in imagination: it is enough that we can
  8092. clearly represent the possibility of constructing it. So with the idea
  8093. of the annihilation of everything. Nothing simpler, it will be said,
  8094. than the procedure by which we construct the idea of it. There is, in
  8095. fact, not a single object of our experience that we cannot suppose
  8096. annihilated. Extend this annihilation of a first object to a second,
  8097. then to a third, and so on as long as you please: the nought is the
  8098. limit toward which the operation tends. And the nought so defined is the
  8099. annihilation of everything. That is the theory. We need only consider it
  8100. in this form to see the absurdity it involves.
  8101. An idea constructed by the mind is an idea only if its pieces are
  8102. capable of coexisting; it is reduced to a mere word if the elements that
  8103. we bring together to compose it are driven away as fast as we assemble
  8104. them. When I have defined the circle, I easily represent a black or a
  8105. white circle, a circle in cardboard, iron, or brass, a transparent or an
  8106. opaque circle--but not a square circle, because the law of the
  8107. generation of the circle excludes the possibility of defining this
  8108. figure with straight lines. So my mind can represent any existing thing
  8109. whatever as annihilated;--but if the annihilation of anything by the
  8110. mind is an operation whose mechanism implies that it works on a part of
  8111. the whole, and not on the whole itself, then the extension of such an
  8112. operation to the totality of things becomes self-contradictory and
  8113. absurd, and the idea of an annihilation of everything presents the same
  8114. character as that of a square circle: it is not an idea, it is only a
  8115. word. So let us examine more closely the mechanism of the operation.
  8116. In fact, the object suppressed is either external or internal: it is a
  8117. thing or it is a state of consciousness. Let us consider the first case.
  8118. I annihilate in thought an external object: in the place where it was,
  8119. there is no longer anything.--No longer anything of that object, of
  8120. course, but another object has taken its place: there is no absolute
  8121. void in nature. But admit that an absolute void is possible: it is not
  8122. of that void that I am thinking when I say that the object, once
  8123. annihilated, leaves its place unoccupied; for by the hypothesis it is a
  8124. _place_, that is a void limited by precise outlines, or, in other words,
  8125. a kind of _thing_. The void of which I speak, therefore, is, at bottom,
  8126. only the absence of some definite object, which was here at first, is
  8127. now elsewhere and, in so far as it is no longer in its former place,
  8128. leaves behind it, so to speak, the void of itself. A being unendowed
  8129. with memory or prevision would not use the words "void" or "nought;" he
  8130. would express only what is and what is perceived; now, what is, and what
  8131. is perceived, is the _presence_ of one thing or of another, never the
  8132. _absence_ of anything. There is absence only for a being capable of
  8133. remembering and expecting. He remembered an object, and perhaps expected
  8134. to encounter it again; he finds another, and he expresses the
  8135. disappointment of his expectation (an expectation sprung from
  8136. recollection) by saying that he no longer finds anything, that he
  8137. encounters "nothing." Even if he did not expect to encounter the object,
  8138. it is a possible expectation of it, it is still the falsification of his
  8139. eventual expectation that he expresses by saying that the object is no
  8140. longer where it was. What he perceives in reality, what he will succeed
  8141. in effectively thinking of, is the presence of the old object in a new
  8142. place or that of a new object in the old place; the rest, all that is
  8143. expressed negatively by such words as "nought" or the "void," is not so
  8144. much thought as feeling, or, to speak more exactly, it is the tinge that
  8145. feeling gives to thought. The idea of annihilation or of partial
  8146. nothingness is therefore formed here in the course of the substitution
  8147. of one thing for another, whenever this substitution is thought by a
  8148. mind that would prefer to keep the old thing in the place of the new, or
  8149. at least conceives this preference as possible. The idea implies on the
  8150. subjective side a preference, on the objective side a substitution, and
  8151. is nothing else but a combination of, or rather an interference between,
  8152. this feeling of preference and this idea of substitution.
  8153. Such is the mechanism of the operation by which our mind annihilates an
  8154. object and succeeds in representing in the external world a partial
  8155. nought. Let us now see how it represents it within itself. We find in
  8156. ourselves phenomena that are produced, and not phenomena that are not
  8157. produced. I experience a sensation or an emotion, I conceive an idea, I
  8158. form a resolution: my consciousness perceives these facts, which are so
  8159. many _presences_, and there is no moment in which facts of this kind are
  8160. not present to me. I can, no doubt, interrupt by thought the course of
  8161. my inner life; I may suppose that I sleep without dreaming or that I
  8162. have ceased to exist; but at the very instant when I make this
  8163. supposition, I conceive myself, I imagine myself watching over my
  8164. slumber or surviving my annihilation, and I give up perceiving myself
  8165. from within only by taking refuge in the perception of myself from
  8166. without. That is to say that here again the full always succeeds the
  8167. full, and that an intelligence that was only intelligence, that had
  8168. neither regret nor desire, whose movement was governed by the movement
  8169. of its object, could not even conceive an absence or a void. The
  8170. conception of a void arises here when consciousness, lagging behind
  8171. itself, remains attached to the recollection of an old state when
  8172. another state is already present. It is only a comparison between what
  8173. is and what could or ought to be, between the full and the full. In a
  8174. word, whether it be a void of matter or a void of consciousness, _the
  8175. representation of the void is always a representation which is full and
  8176. which resolves itself on analysis into two positive elements: the idea,
  8177. distinct or confused, of a substitution, and the feeling, experienced or
  8178. imagined, of a desire or a regret_.
  8179. It follows from this double analysis that the idea of the absolute
  8180. nought, in the sense of the annihilation of everything, is a
  8181. self-destructive idea, a pseudo-idea, a mere word. If suppressing a
  8182. thing consists in replacing it by another, if thinking the absence of
  8183. one thing is only possible by the more or less explicit representation
  8184. of the presence of some other thing, if, in short, annihilation
  8185. signifies before anything else substitution, the idea of an
  8186. "annihilation of everything" is as absurd as that of a square circle.
  8187. The absurdity is not obvious, because there exists no particular object
  8188. that cannot be supposed annihilated; then, from the fact that there is
  8189. nothing to prevent each thing in turn being suppressed in thought, we
  8190. conclude that it is possible to suppose them suppressed altogether. We
  8191. do not see that suppressing each thing in turn consists precisely in
  8192. replacing it in proportion and degree by another, and therefore that the
  8193. suppression of absolutely everything implies a downright contradiction
  8194. in terms, since the operation consists in destroying the very condition
  8195. that makes the operation possible.
  8196. But the illusion is tenacious. Though suppressing one thing consists _in
  8197. fact_ in substituting another for it, we do not conclude, we are
  8198. unwilling to conclude, that the annihilation of a thing _in thought_
  8199. implies the substitution in thought of a new thing for the old. We agree
  8200. that a thing is always replaced by another thing, and even that our mind
  8201. cannot think the disappearance of an object, external or internal,
  8202. without thinking--under an indeterminate and confused form, it is
  8203. true--that another object is substituted for it. But we add that the
  8204. representation of a disappearance is that of a phenomenon that is
  8205. produced in space or at least in time, that consequently it still
  8206. implies the calling up of an image, and that it is precisely here that
  8207. we have to free ourselves from the imagination in order to appeal to the
  8208. pure understanding. "Let us therefore no longer speak," it will be said,
  8209. "of disappearance or annihilation; these are physical operations. Let us
  8210. no longer represent the object A as annihilated or absent. Let us say
  8211. simply that we think it "non-existent." To annihilate it is to act on it
  8212. in time and perhaps also in space; it is to accept, consequently, the
  8213. condition of spatial and temporal existence, to accept the universal
  8214. connection that binds an object to all others, and prevents it from
  8215. disappearing without being at the same time replaced. But we can free
  8216. ourselves from these conditions; all that is necessary is that by an
  8217. effort of abstraction we should call up the idea of the object A by
  8218. itself, that we should agree first to consider it as existing, and then,
  8219. by a stroke of the intellectual pen, blot out the clause. The object
  8220. will then be, by our decree, non-existent."
  8221. Very well, let us strike out the clause. We must not suppose that our
  8222. pen-stroke is self-sufficient--that it can be isolated from the rest of
  8223. things. We shall see that it carries with it, whether we will or no,
  8224. all that we tried to abstract from. Let us compare together the two
  8225. ideas--the object A supposed to exist, and the same object supposed
  8226. "non-existent."
  8227. The idea of the object A, supposed existent, is the representation pure
  8228. and simple of the object A, for we cannot represent an object without
  8229. attributing to it, by the very fact of representing it, a certain
  8230. reality. Between thinking an object and thinking it existent, there is
  8231. absolutely no difference. Kant has put this point in clear light in his
  8232. criticism of the ontological argument. Then, what is it to think the
  8233. object A non-existent? To represent it non-existent cannot consist in
  8234. withdrawing from the idea of the object A the idea of the attribute
  8235. "existence," since, I repeat, the representation of the existence of the
  8236. object is inseparable from the representation of the object, and indeed
  8237. is one with it. To represent the object A non-existent can only consist,
  8238. therefore, in _adding_ something to the idea of this object: we add to
  8239. it, in fact, the idea of an _exclusion_ of this particular object by
  8240. actual reality in general. To think the object A as non-existent is
  8241. first to think the object and consequently to think it existent; it is
  8242. then to think that another reality, with which it is incompatible,
  8243. supplants it. Only, it is useless to represent this latter reality
  8244. explicitly; we are not concerned with what it is; it is enough for us to
  8245. know that it drives out the object A, which alone is of interest to us.
  8246. That is why we think of the expulsion rather than of the cause which
  8247. expels. But this cause is none the less present to the mind; it is there
  8248. in the implicit state, that which expels being inseparable from the
  8249. expulsion as the hand which drives the pen is inseparable from the
  8250. pen-stroke. The act by which we declare an object unreal therefore
  8251. posits the existence of the real in general. In other words, to
  8252. represent an object as unreal cannot consist in depriving it of every
  8253. kind of existence, since the representation of an object is necessarily
  8254. that of the object existing. Such an act consists simply in declaring
  8255. that the existence attached by our mind to the object, and inseparable
  8256. from its representation, is an existence wholly ideal--that of a mere
  8257. _possible_. But the "ideality" of an object, and the "simple
  8258. possibility" of an object, have meaning only in relation to a reality
  8259. that drives into the region of the ideal, or of the merely possible, the
  8260. object which is incompatible with it. Suppose the stronger and more
  8261. substantial existence annihilated: it is the attenuated and weaker
  8262. existence of the merely possible that becomes the reality itself, and
  8263. you will no longer be representing the object, then, as non-existent. In
  8264. other words, and however strange our assertion may seem, _there is_
  8265. more, _and not_ less, _in the idea of an object conceived as "not
  8266. existing" than in the idea of this same object conceived as "existing";
  8267. for the idea of the object "not existing" is necessarily the idea of the
  8268. object "existing" with, in addition, the representation of an exclusion
  8269. of this object by the actual reality taken in block_.
  8270. But it will be claimed that our idea of the non-existent is not yet
  8271. sufficiently cut loose from every imaginative element, that it is not
  8272. negative enough. "No matter," we shall be told, "though the unreality of
  8273. a thing consist in its exclusion by other things; we want to know
  8274. nothing about that. Are we not free to direct our attention where we
  8275. please and how we please? Well then, after having called up the idea of
  8276. an object, and thereby, if you will have it so, supposed it existent, we
  8277. shall merely couple to our affirmation a 'not,' and that will be enough
  8278. to make us think it non-existent. This is an operation entirely
  8279. intellectual, independent of what happens outside the mind. So let us
  8280. think of anything or let us think of the totality of things, and then
  8281. write in the margin of our thought the 'not,' which prescribes the
  8282. rejection of what it contains: we annihilate everything mentally by the
  8283. mere fact of decreeing its annihilation."--Here we have it! The very
  8284. root of all the difficulties and errors with which we are confronted is
  8285. to be found in the power ascribed here to negation. We represent
  8286. negation as exactly symmetrical with affirmation. We imagine that
  8287. negation, like affirmation, is self-sufficient. So that negation, like
  8288. affirmation, would have the power of creating ideas, with this sole
  8289. difference that they would be negative ideas. By affirming one thing,
  8290. and then another, and so on _ad infinitum_, I form the idea of "All;"
  8291. so, by denying one thing and then other things, finally by denying All,
  8292. I arrive at the idea of Nothing.--But it is just this assimilation which
  8293. is arbitrary. We fail to see that while affirmation is a complete act of
  8294. the mind, which can succeed in building up an idea, negation is but the
  8295. half of an intellectual act, of which the other half is understood, or
  8296. rather put off to an indefinite future. We fail to see that while
  8297. affirmation is a purely intellectual act, there enters into negation an
  8298. element which is not intellectual, and that it is precisely to the
  8299. intrusion of this foreign element that negation owes its specific
  8300. character.
  8301. To begin with the second point, let us note that to deny always consists
  8302. in setting aside a possible affirmation.[98] Negation is only an
  8303. attitude taken by the mind toward an eventual affirmation. When I say,
  8304. "This table is black," I am speaking of the table; I have seen it
  8305. black, and my judgment expresses what I have seen. But if I say, "This
  8306. table is not white," I surely do not express something I have perceived,
  8307. for I have seen black, and not an absence of white. It is therefore, at
  8308. bottom, not on the table itself that I bring this judgment to bear, but
  8309. rather on the judgment that would declare the table white. I judge a
  8310. judgment and not the table. The proposition, "This table is not white,"
  8311. implies that you might believe it white, that you did believe it such,
  8312. or that I was going to believe it such. I warn you or myself that this
  8313. judgment is to be replaced by another (which, it is true, I leave
  8314. undetermined). Thus, while affirmation bears directly on the thing,
  8315. negation aims at the thing only indirectly, through an interposed
  8316. affirmation. An affirmative proposition expresses a judgment on an
  8317. object; a negative proposition expresses a judgment on a judgment.
  8318. _Negation, therefore, differs from affirmation properly so called in
  8319. that it is an affirmation of the second degree: it affirms something of
  8320. an affirmation which itself affirms something of an object._
  8321. But it follows at once from this that negation is not the work of pure
  8322. mind, I should say of a mind placed before objects and concerned with
  8323. them alone. When we deny, we give a lesson to others, or it may be to
  8324. ourselves. We take to task an interlocutor, real or possible, whom we
  8325. find mistaken and whom we put on his guard. He was affirming something:
  8326. we tell him he ought to affirm something else (though without specifying
  8327. the affirmation which must be substituted). There is no longer then,
  8328. simply, a person and an object; there is, in face of the object, a
  8329. person speaking to a person, opposing him and aiding him at the same
  8330. time; there is a beginning of society. Negation aims at some one, and
  8331. not only, like a purely intellectual operation, at some thing. It is of
  8332. a pedagogical and social nature. It sets straight or rather warns, the
  8333. person warned and set straight being possibly, by a kind of doubling,
  8334. the very person that speaks.
  8335. So much for the second point; now for the first. We said that negation
  8336. is but the half of an intellectual act, of which the other half is left
  8337. indeterminate. If I pronounce the negative proposition, "This table is
  8338. not white," I mean that you ought to substitute for your judgment, "The
  8339. table is white," another judgment. I give you an admonition, and the
  8340. admonition refers to the necessity of a substitution. As to what you
  8341. ought to substitute for your affirmation, I tell you nothing, it is
  8342. true. This may be because I do not know the color of the table; but it
  8343. is also, it is indeed even more, because the white color is that alone
  8344. that interests us for the moment, so that I only need to tell you that
  8345. some other color will have to be substituted for white, without having
  8346. to say which. A negative judgment is therefore really one which
  8347. indicates a need of substituting for an affirmative judgment another
  8348. affirmative judgment, the nature of which, however, is not specified,
  8349. sometimes because it is not known, more often because it fails to offer
  8350. any actual interest, the attention bearing only on the substance of the
  8351. first.
  8352. Thus, whenever I add a "not" to an affirmation, whenever I deny, I
  8353. perform two very definite acts: (1) I interest myself in what one of my
  8354. fellow-men affirms, or in what he was going to say, or in what might
  8355. have been said by another _Me_, whom I anticipate; (2) I announce that
  8356. some other affirmation, whose content I do not specify, will have to be
  8357. substituted for the one I find before me. Now, in neither of these two
  8358. acts is there anything but affirmation. The _sui generis_ character of
  8359. negation is due to superimposing the first of these acts upon the
  8360. second. It is in vain, then, that we attribute to negation the power of
  8361. creating ideas _sui generis_, symmetrical with those that affirmation
  8362. creates, and directed in a contrary sense. No idea will come forth from
  8363. negation, for it has no other content than that of the affirmative
  8364. judgment which it judges.
  8365. To be more precise, let us consider an existential, instead of an
  8366. attributive, judgment. If I say, "The object A does not exist," I mean
  8367. by that, first, that we might believe that the object A exists: how,
  8368. indeed, can we think of the object A without thinking it existing, and,
  8369. once again, what difference can there be between the idea of the object
  8370. A existing and the idea pure and simple of the object A? Therefore,
  8371. merely by saying "The object A," I attribute to it some kind of
  8372. existence, though it be that of a mere _possible_, that is to say, of a
  8373. pure idea. And consequently, in the judgment "The object A is not,"
  8374. there is at first an affirmation such as "The object A has been," or
  8375. "The object A will be," or, more generally, "The object A exists at
  8376. least as a mere _possible_." Now, when I add the two words "is not," I
  8377. can only mean that if we go further, if we erect the possible object
  8378. into a real object, we shall be mistaken, and that the possible of which
  8379. I am speaking is excluded from the actual reality as incompatible with
  8380. it. Judgments that posit the non-existence of a thing are therefore
  8381. judgments that formulate a contrast between the possible and the actual
  8382. (that is, between two kinds of _existence_, one thought and the other
  8383. found), where a person, real or imaginary, wrongly believes that a
  8384. certain possible is realized. Instead of this possible, there is a
  8385. reality that differs from it and rejects it: the negative judgment
  8386. expresses this contrast, but it expresses the contrast in an
  8387. intentionally incomplete form, because it is addressed to a person who
  8388. is supposed to be interested exclusively in the possible that is
  8389. indicated, and is not concerned to know by what kind of reality the
  8390. possible is replaced. The expression of the substitution is therefore
  8391. bound to be cut short. Instead of affirming that a second term is
  8392. substituted for the first, the attention which was originally directed
  8393. to the first term will be kept fixed upon it, and upon it alone. And,
  8394. without going beyond the first, we shall implicitly affirm that a second
  8395. term replaces it in saying that the first "is not." We shall thus judge
  8396. a judgment instead of judging a thing. We shall warn others or warn
  8397. ourselves of a possible error instead of supplying positive information.
  8398. Suppress every intention of this kind, give knowledge back its
  8399. exclusively scientific or philosophical character, suppose in other
  8400. words that reality comes itself to inscribe itself on a mind that cares
  8401. only for things and is not interested in persons: we shall affirm that
  8402. such or such a thing is, we shall never affirm that a thing is not.
  8403. How comes it, then, that affirmation and negation are so persistently
  8404. put on the same level and endowed with an equal objectivity? How comes
  8405. it that we have so much difficulty in recognizing that negation is
  8406. subjective, artificially cut short, relative to the human mind and still
  8407. more to the social life? The reason is, no doubt, that _both_ negation
  8408. and affirmation are expressed in propositions, and that _any_
  8409. proposition, being formed of _words_, which symbolize _concepts_, is
  8410. something relative to social life and to the human intellect. Whether I
  8411. say "The ground is damp" or "The ground is not damp," in both cases the
  8412. terms "ground" and "damp" are concepts more or less artificially created
  8413. by the mind of man--extracted, by his free initiative, from the
  8414. continuity of experience. In both cases the concepts are represented by
  8415. the same conventional words. In both cases we can say indeed that the
  8416. proposition aims at a social and pedagogical end, since the first would
  8417. propagate a truth as the second would prevent an error. From this point
  8418. of view, which is that of formal logic, to affirm and to deny are indeed
  8419. two mutually symmetrical acts, of which the first establishes a relation
  8420. of agreement and the second a relation of disagreement between a subject
  8421. and an attribute. But how do we fail to see that the symmetry is
  8422. altogether external and the likeness superficial? Suppose language
  8423. fallen into disuse, society dissolved, every intellectual initiative,
  8424. every faculty of self-reflection and of self-judgment atrophied in man:
  8425. the dampness of the ground will subsist none the less, capable of
  8426. inscribing itself automatically in sensation and of sending a vague idea
  8427. to the deadened intellect. The intellect will still affirm, in implicit
  8428. terms. And consequently, neither distinct concepts, nor words, nor the
  8429. desire of spreading the truth, nor that of bettering oneself, are of the
  8430. very essence of the affirmation. But this passive intelligence,
  8431. mechanically keeping step with experience, neither anticipating nor
  8432. following the course of the real, would have no wish to deny. It could
  8433. not receive an imprint of negation; for, once again, that which exists
  8434. may come to be recorded, but the non-existence of the non-existing
  8435. cannot. For such an intellect to reach the point of denying, it must
  8436. awake from its torpor, formulate the disappointment of a real or
  8437. possible expectation, correct an actual or possible error--in short,
  8438. propose to teach others or to teach itself.
  8439. It is rather difficult to perceive this in the example we have chosen,
  8440. but the example is indeed the more instructive and the argument the more
  8441. cogent on that account. If dampness is able automatically to come and
  8442. record itself, it is the same, it will be said, with non-dampness; for
  8443. the dry as well as the damp can give impressions to sense, which will
  8444. transmit them, as more or less distinct ideas, to the intelligence. In
  8445. this sense the negation of dampness is as objective a thing, as purely
  8446. intellectual, as remote from every pedagogical intention, as
  8447. affirmation.--But let us look at it more closely: we shall see that the
  8448. negative proposition, "The ground is not damp," and the affirmative
  8449. proposition, "The ground is dry," have entirely different contents. The
  8450. second implies that we know the dry, that we have experienced the
  8451. specific sensations, tactile or visual for example, that are at the base
  8452. of this idea. The first requires nothing of the sort; it could equally
  8453. well have been formulated by an intelligent fish, who had never
  8454. perceived anything but the wet. It would be necessary, it is true, that
  8455. this fish should have risen to the distinction between the real and the
  8456. possible, and that he should care to anticipate the error of his
  8457. fellow-fishes, who doubtless consider as alone possible the condition of
  8458. wetness in which they actually live. Keep strictly to the terms of the
  8459. proposition, "The ground is not damp," and you will find that it means
  8460. two things: (1) that one might believe that the ground is damp, (2) that
  8461. the dampness is replaced in fact by a certain quality _x_. This quality
  8462. is left indeterminate, either because we have no positive knowledge of
  8463. it, or because it has no actual interest for the person to whom the
  8464. negation is addressed. To deny, therefore, always consists in presenting
  8465. in an abridged form a system of two affirmations: the one determinate,
  8466. which applies to a certain _possible_; the other indeterminate,
  8467. referring to the unknown or indifferent reality that supplants this
  8468. possibility. The second affirmation is virtually contained in the
  8469. judgment we apply to the first, a judgment which is negation itself. And
  8470. what gives negation its subjective character is precisely this, that in
  8471. the discovery of a replacement it takes account only of the replaced,
  8472. and is not concerned with what replaces. The replaced exists only as a
  8473. conception of the mind. It is necessary, in order to continue to see it,
  8474. and consequently in order to speak of it, to turn our back on the
  8475. reality, which flows from the past to the present, advancing from
  8476. behind. It is this that we do when we deny. We discover the change, or
  8477. more generally the substitution, as a traveller would see the course of
  8478. his carriage if he looked out behind, and only knew at each moment the
  8479. point at which he had ceased to be; he could never determine his actual
  8480. position except by relation to that which he had just quitted, instead
  8481. of grasping it in itself.
  8482. To sum up, for a mind which should follow purely and simply the thread
  8483. of experience, there would be no void, no nought, even relative or
  8484. partial, no possible negation. Such a mind would see facts succeed
  8485. facts, states succeed states, things succeed things. What it would note
  8486. at each moment would be things existing, states appearing, events
  8487. happening. It would live in the actual, and, if it were capable of
  8488. judging, it would never affirm anything except the existence of the
  8489. present.
  8490. Endow this mind with memory, and especially with the desire to dwell on
  8491. the past; give it the faculty of dissociating and of distinguishing: it
  8492. will no longer only note the present state of the passing reality; it
  8493. will represent the passing as a change, and therefore as a contrast
  8494. between what has been and what is. And as there is no essential
  8495. difference between a past that we remember and a past that we imagine,
  8496. it will quickly rise to the idea of the "possible" in general.
  8497. It will thus be shunted on to the siding of negation. And especially it
  8498. will be at the point of representing a disappearance. But it will not
  8499. yet have reached it. To represent that a thing has disappeared, it is
  8500. not enough to perceive a contrast between the past and the present; it
  8501. is necessary besides to turn our back on the present, to dwell on the
  8502. past, and to think the contrast of the past with the present in terms of
  8503. the past only, without letting the present appear in it.
  8504. The idea of annihilation is therefore not a pure idea; it implies that
  8505. we regret the past or that we conceive it as regrettable, that we have
  8506. some reason to linger over it. The idea arises when the phenomenon of
  8507. substitution is cut in two by a mind which considers only the first
  8508. half, because that alone interests it. Suppress all interest, all
  8509. feeling, and there is nothing left but the reality that flows, together
  8510. with the knowledge ever renewed that it impresses on us of its present
  8511. state.
  8512. From annihilation to negation, which is a more general operation, there
  8513. is now only a step. All that is necessary is to represent the contrast
  8514. of what is, not only with what has been, but also with all that might
  8515. have been. And we must express this contrast as a function of what might
  8516. have been, and not of what is; we must affirm the existence of the
  8517. actual while looking only at the possible. The formula we thus obtain no
  8518. longer expresses merely a disappointment of the individual; it is made
  8519. to correct or guard against an error, which is rather supposed to be the
  8520. error of another. In this sense, negation has a pedagogical and social
  8521. character.
  8522. Now, once negation is formulated, it presents an aspect symmetrical with
  8523. that of affirmation; if affirmation affirms an objective reality, it
  8524. seems that negation must affirm a non-reality equally objective, and, so
  8525. to say, equally real. In which we are both right and wrong: wrong,
  8526. because negation cannot be objectified, in so far as it is negative;
  8527. right, however, in that the negation of a thing implies the latent
  8528. affirmation of its replacement by something else, which we
  8529. systematically leave on one side. But the negative form of negation
  8530. benefits by the affirmation at the bottom of it. Bestriding the positive
  8531. solid reality to which it is attached, this phantom objectifies itself.
  8532. Thus is formed the idea of the void or of a partial nought, a thing
  8533. being supposed to be replaced, not by another thing, but by a void which
  8534. it leaves, that is, by the negation of itself. Now, as this operation
  8535. works on anything whatever, we suppose it performed on each thing in
  8536. turn, and finally on all things in block. We thus obtain the idea of
  8537. absolute Nothing. If now we analyze this idea of Nothing, we find that
  8538. it is, at bottom, the idea of Everything, together with a movement of
  8539. the mind that keeps jumping from one thing to another, refuses to stand
  8540. still, and concentrates all its attention on this refusal by never
  8541. determining its actual position except by relation to that which it has
  8542. just left. It is therefore an idea eminently comprehensive and full, as
  8543. full and comprehensive as the idea of _All_, to which it is very closely
  8544. akin.
  8545. How then can the idea of Nought be opposed to that of All? Is it not
  8546. plain that this is to oppose the full to the full, and that the
  8547. question, "Why does something exist?" is consequently without meaning, a
  8548. pseudo-problem raised about a pseudo-idea? Yet we must say once more why
  8549. this phantom of a problem haunts the mind with such obstinacy. In vain
  8550. do we show that in the idea of an "annihilation of the real" there is
  8551. only the image of all realities expelling one another endlessly, in a
  8552. circle; in vain do we add that the idea of non-existence is only that of
  8553. the expulsion of an imponderable existence, or a "merely possible"
  8554. existence, by a more substantial existence which would then be the true
  8555. reality; in vain do we find in the _sui generis_ form of negation an
  8556. element which is not intellectual--negation being the judgment of a
  8557. judgment, an admonition given to some one else or to oneself, so that it
  8558. is absurd to attribute to negation the power of creating ideas of a new
  8559. kind, viz. ideas without content;--in spite of all, the conviction
  8560. persists that before things, or at least under things, there is
  8561. "Nothing." If we seek the reason of this fact, we shall find it
  8562. precisely in the feeling, in the social and, so to speak, practical
  8563. element, that gives its specific form to negation. The greatest
  8564. philosophic difficulties arise, as we have said, from the fact that the
  8565. forms of human action venture outside of their proper sphere. We are
  8566. made in order to act as much as, and more than, in order to think--or
  8567. rather, when we follow the bent of our nature, it is in order to act
  8568. that we think. It is therefore no wonder that the habits of action give
  8569. their tone to those of thought, and that our mind always perceives
  8570. things in the same order in which we are accustomed to picture them when
  8571. we propose to act on them. Now, it is unquestionable, as we remarked
  8572. above, that every human action has its starting-point in a
  8573. dissatisfaction, and thereby in a feeling of absence. We should not act
  8574. if we did not set before ourselves an end, and we seek a thing only
  8575. because we feel the lack of it. Our action proceeds thus from "nothing"
  8576. to "something," and its very essence is to embroider "something" on the
  8577. canvas of "nothing." The truth is that the "nothing" concerned here is
  8578. the absence not so much of a thing as of a utility. If I bring a visitor
  8579. into a room that I have not yet furnished, I say to him that "there is
  8580. nothing in it." Yet I know the room is full of air; but, as we do not
  8581. sit on air, the room truly contains nothing that at this moment, for the
  8582. visitor and for myself, counts for anything. In a general way, human
  8583. work consists in creating utility; and, as long as the work is not
  8584. done, there is "nothing"--nothing that we want. Our life is thus spent
  8585. in filling voids, which our intellect conceives under the influence, by
  8586. no means intellectual, of desire and of regret, under the pressure of
  8587. vital necessities; and if we mean by void an absence of utility and not
  8588. of things, we may say, in this quite relative sense, that we are
  8589. constantly going from the void to the full: such is the direction which
  8590. our action takes. Our speculation cannot help doing the same; and,
  8591. naturally, it passes from the relative sense to the absolute sense,
  8592. since it is exercised on things themselves and not on the utility they
  8593. have for us. Thus is implanted in us the idea that reality fills a void,
  8594. and that Nothing, conceived as an absence of everything, pre-exists
  8595. before all things in right, if not in fact. It is this illusion that we
  8596. have tried to remove by showing that the idea of Nothing, if we try to
  8597. see in it that of an annihilation of all things, is self-destructive and
  8598. reduced to a mere word; and that if, on the contrary, it is truly an
  8599. idea, then we find in it as much matter as in the idea of All.
  8600. * * * * *
  8601. This long analysis has been necessary to show that _a self-sufficient
  8602. reality is not necessarily a reality foreign to duration_. If we pass
  8603. (consciously or unconsciously) through the idea of the nought in order
  8604. to reach that of being, the being to which we come is a logical or
  8605. mathematical essence, therefore non-temporal. And, consequently, a
  8606. static conception of the real is forced on us: everything appears given
  8607. once for all, in eternity. But we must accustom ourselves to think being
  8608. directly, without making a detour, without first appealing to the
  8609. phantom of the nought which interposes itself between it and us. We must
  8610. strive to see in order to see, and no longer to see in order to act.
  8611. Then the Absolute is revealed very near us and, in a certain measure,
  8612. in us. It is of psychological and not of mathematical nor logical
  8613. essence. It lives with us. Like us, but in certain aspects infinitely
  8614. more concentrated and more gathered up in itself, it _endures_.
  8615. But do we ever think true duration? Here again a direct taking
  8616. possession is necessary. It is no use trying to approach duration: we
  8617. must install ourselves within it straight away. This is what the
  8618. intellect generally refuses to do, accustomed as it is to think the
  8619. moving by means of the unmovable.
  8620. The function of the intellect is to preside over actions. Now, in
  8621. action, it is the result that interests us; the means matter little
  8622. provided the end is attained. Thence it comes that we are altogether
  8623. bent on the end to be realized, generally trusting ourselves to it in
  8624. order that the idea may become an act; and thence it comes also that
  8625. only the goal where our activity will rest is pictured explicitly to our
  8626. mind: the movements constituting the action itself either elude our
  8627. consciousness or reach it only confusedly. Let us consider a very simple
  8628. act, like that of lifting the arm. Where should we be if we had to
  8629. imagine beforehand all the elementary contractions and tensions this act
  8630. involves, or even to perceive them, one by one, as they are
  8631. accomplished? But the mind is carried immediately to the end, that is to
  8632. say, to the schematic and simplified vision of the act supposed
  8633. accomplished. Then, if no antagonistic idea neutralizes the effect of
  8634. the first idea, the appropriate movements come of themselves to fill out
  8635. the plan, drawn in some way by the void of its gaps. The intellect,
  8636. then, only represents to the activity ends to attain, that is to say,
  8637. points of rest. And, from one end attained to another end attained, from
  8638. one rest to another rest, our activity is carried by a series of leaps,
  8639. during which our consciousness is turned away as much as possible from
  8640. the movement going on, to regard only the anticipated image of the
  8641. movement accomplished.
  8642. Now, in order that it may represent as unmovable the result of the act
  8643. which is being accomplished, the intellect must perceive, as also
  8644. unmovable, the surroundings in which this result is being framed. Our
  8645. activity is fitted into the material world. If matter appeared to us as
  8646. a perpetual flowing, we should assign no termination to any of our
  8647. actions. We should feel each of them dissolve as fast as it was
  8648. accomplished, and we should not anticipate an ever-fleeting future. In
  8649. order that our activity may leap from an _act_ to an _act_, it is
  8650. necessary that matter should pass from a _state_ to a _state_, for it is
  8651. only into a state of the material world that action can fit a result, so
  8652. as to be accomplished. But is it thus that matter presents itself?
  8653. _A priori_ we may presume that our perception manages to apprehend
  8654. matter with this bias. Sensory organs and motor organs are in fact
  8655. coördinated with each other. Now, the first symbolize our faculty of
  8656. perceiving, as the second our faculty of acting. The organism thus
  8657. evidences, in a visible and tangible form, the perfect accord of
  8658. perception and action. So if our activity always aims at a _result_ into
  8659. which it is momentarily fitted, our perception must retain of the
  8660. material world, at every moment, only a _state_ in which it is
  8661. provisionally placed. This is the most natural hypothesis. And it is
  8662. easy to see that experience confirms it.
  8663. From our first glance at the world, before we even make our _bodies_ in
  8664. it, we distinguish _qualities_. Color succeeds to color, sound to sound,
  8665. resistance to resistance, etc. Each of these qualities, taken
  8666. separately, is a state that seems to persist as such, immovable until
  8667. another replaces it. Yet each of these qualities resolves itself, on
  8668. analysis, into an enormous number of elementary movements. Whether we
  8669. see in it vibrations or whether we represent it in any other way, one
  8670. fact is certain, it is that every quality is change. In vain, moreover,
  8671. shall we seek beneath the change the thing which changes: it is always
  8672. provisionally, and in order to satisfy our imagination, that we attach
  8673. the movement to a mobile. The mobile flies for ever before the pursuit
  8674. of science, which is concerned with mobility alone. In the smallest
  8675. discernible fraction of a second, in the almost instantaneous perception
  8676. of a sensible quality, there may be trillions of oscillations which
  8677. repeat themselves. The permanence of a sensible quality consists in this
  8678. repetition of movements, as the persistence of life consists in a series
  8679. of palpitations. The primal function of perception is precisely to grasp
  8680. a series of elementary changes under the form of a quality or of a
  8681. simple state, by a work of condensation. The greater the power of acting
  8682. bestowed upon an animal species, the more numerous, probably, are the
  8683. elementary changes that its faculty of perceiving concentrates into one
  8684. of its instants. And the progress must be continuous, in nature, from
  8685. the beings that vibrate almost in unison with the oscillations of the
  8686. ether, up to those that embrace trillions of these oscillations in the
  8687. shortest of their simple perceptions. The first feel hardly anything but
  8688. movements; the others perceive quality. The first are almost caught up
  8689. in the running-gear of things; the others react, and the tension of
  8690. their faculty of acting is probably proportional to the concentration of
  8691. their faculty of perceiving. The progress goes on even in humanity
  8692. itself. A man is so much the more a "man of action" as he can embrace in
  8693. a glance a greater number of events: he who perceives successive events
  8694. one by one will allow himself to be led by them; he who grasps them as
  8695. a whole will dominate them. In short, the qualities of matter are so
  8696. many stable views that we take of its instability.
  8697. Now, in the continuity of sensible qualities we mark off the boundaries
  8698. of bodies. Each of these bodies really changes at every moment. In the
  8699. first place, it resolves itself into a group of qualities, and every
  8700. quality, as we said, consists of a succession of elementary movements.
  8701. But, even if we regard the quality as a stable state, the body is still
  8702. unstable in that it changes qualities without ceasing. The body
  8703. pre-eminently--that which we are most justified in isolating within the
  8704. continuity of matter, because it constitutes a relatively closed
  8705. system--is the living body; it is, moreover, for it that we cut out the
  8706. others within the whole. Now, life is an evolution. We concentrate a
  8707. period of this evolution in a stable view which we call a form, and,
  8708. when the change has become considerable enough to overcome the fortunate
  8709. inertia of our perception, we say that the body has changed its form.
  8710. But in reality the body is changing form at every moment; or rather,
  8711. there is no form, since form is immobile and the reality is movement.
  8712. What is real is the continual _change of_ form: _form is only a snapshot
  8713. view of a transition_. Therefore, here again, our perception manages to
  8714. solidify into discontinuous images the fluid continuity of the real.
  8715. When the successive images do not differ from each other too much, we
  8716. consider them all as the waxing and waning of a single _mean_ image, or
  8717. as the deformation of this image in different directions. And to this
  8718. mean we really allude when we speak of the _essence_ of a thing, or of
  8719. the thing itself.
  8720. Finally things, once constituted, show on the surface, by their changes
  8721. of situation, the profound changes that are being accomplished within
  8722. the Whole. We say then that they _act_ on one another. This action
  8723. appears to us, no doubt, in the form of movement. But from the mobility
  8724. of the movement we turn away as much as we can; what interests us is, as
  8725. we said above, the unmovable plan of the movement rather than the
  8726. movement itself. Is it a simple movement? We ask ourselves _where_ it is
  8727. going. It is by its direction, that is to say, by the position of its
  8728. provisional end, that we represent it at every moment. Is it a complex
  8729. movement? We would know above all _what_ is going on, _what_ the
  8730. movement is doing--in other words, the _result_ obtained or the
  8731. presiding _intention_. Examine closely what is in your mind when you
  8732. speak of an action in course of accomplishment. The idea of change is
  8733. there, I am willing to grant, but it is hidden in the penumbra. In the
  8734. full light is the motionless plan of the act supposed accomplished. It
  8735. is by this, and by this only, that the complex act is distinguished and
  8736. defined. We should be very much embarrassed if we had to imagine the
  8737. movements inherent in the actions of eating, drinking, fighting, etc. It
  8738. is enough for us to know, in a general and indefinite way, that all
  8739. these acts are movements. Once that side of the matter has been settled,
  8740. we simply seek to represent the _general plan_ of each of these complex
  8741. movements, that is to say the _motionless design_ that underlies them.
  8742. Here again knowledge bears on a state rather than on a change. It is
  8743. therefore the same with this third case as with the others. Whether the
  8744. movement be qualitative or evolutionary or extensive, the mind manages
  8745. to take stable views of the instability. And thence the mind derives, as
  8746. we have just shown, three kinds of representations: (1) qualities, (2)
  8747. forms of essences, (3) acts.
  8748. To these three ways of seeing correspond three categories of words:
  8749. _adjectives_, _substantives_, and _verbs_, which are the primordial
  8750. elements of language. Adjectives and substantives therefore symbolize
  8751. _states_. But the verb itself, if we keep to the clear part of the idea
  8752. it calls up, hardly expresses anything else.
  8753. * * * * *
  8754. Now, if we try to characterize more precisely our natural attitude
  8755. towards Becoming, this is what we find. Becoming is infinitely varied.
  8756. That which goes from yellow to green is not like that which goes from
  8757. green to blue: they are different _qualitative_ movements. That which
  8758. goes from flower to fruit is not like that which goes from larva to
  8759. nymph and from nymph to perfect insect: they are different
  8760. _evolutionary_ movements. The action of eating or of drinking is not
  8761. like the action of fighting: they are different _extensive_ movements.
  8762. And these three kinds of movement themselves--qualitative, evolutionary,
  8763. extensive--differ profoundly. The trick of our perception, like that of
  8764. our intelligence, like that of our language, consists in extracting from
  8765. these profoundly different becomings the single representation of
  8766. becoming _in general_, undefined becoming, a mere abstraction which by
  8767. itself says nothing and of which, indeed, it is very rarely that we
  8768. think. To this idea, always the same, and always obscure or unconscious,
  8769. we then join, in each particular case, one or several clear images that
  8770. represent _states_ and which serve to distinguish all becomings from
  8771. each other. It is this composition of a specified and definite state
  8772. with change general and undefined that we substitute for the specific
  8773. change. An infinite multiplicity of becomings variously colored, so to
  8774. speak, passes before our eyes: we manage so that we see only differences
  8775. of color, that is to say, differences of state, beneath which there is
  8776. supposed to flow, hidden from our view, a becoming always and everywhere
  8777. the same, invariably colorless.
  8778. Suppose we wish to portray on a screen a living picture, such as the
  8779. marching past of a regiment. There is one way in which it might first
  8780. occur to us to do it. That would be to cut out jointed figures
  8781. representing the soldiers, to give to each of them the movement of
  8782. marching, a movement varying from individual to individual although
  8783. common to the human species, and to throw the whole on the screen. We
  8784. should need to spend on this little game an enormous amount of work, and
  8785. even then we should obtain but a very poor result: how could it, at its
  8786. best, reproduce the suppleness and variety of life? Now, there is
  8787. another way of proceeding, more easy and at the same time more
  8788. effective. It is to take a series of snapshots of the passing regiment
  8789. and to throw these instantaneous views on the screen, so that they
  8790. replace each other very rapidly. This is what the cinematograph does.
  8791. With photographs, each of which represents the regiment in a fixed
  8792. attitude, it reconstitutes the mobility of the regiment marching. It is
  8793. true that if we had to do with photographs alone, however much we might
  8794. look at them, we should never see them animated: with immobility set
  8795. beside immobility, even endlessly, we could never make movement. In
  8796. order that the pictures may be animated, there must be movement
  8797. somewhere. The movement does indeed exist here; it is in the apparatus.
  8798. It is because the film of the cinematograph unrolls, bringing in turn
  8799. the different photographs of the scene to continue each other, that each
  8800. actor of the scene recovers his mobility; he strings all his successive
  8801. attitudes on the invisible movement of the film. The process then
  8802. consists in extracting from all the movements peculiar to all the
  8803. figures an impersonal movement abstract and simple, _movement in
  8804. general_, so to speak: we put this into the apparatus, and we
  8805. reconstitute the individuality of each particular movement by combining
  8806. this nameless movement with the personal attitudes. Such is the
  8807. contrivance of the cinematograph. And such is also that of our
  8808. knowledge. Instead of attaching ourselves to the inner becoming of
  8809. things, we place ourselves outside them in order to recompose their
  8810. becoming artificially. We take snapshots, as it were, of the passing
  8811. reality, and, as these are characteristic of the reality, we have only
  8812. to string them on a becoming, abstract, uniform and invisible, situated
  8813. at the back of the apparatus of knowledge, in order to imitate what
  8814. there is that is characteristic in this becoming itself. Perception,
  8815. intellection, language so proceed in general. Whether we would think
  8816. becoming, or express it, or even perceive it, we hardly do anything else
  8817. than set going a kind of cinematograph inside us. We may therefore sum
  8818. up what we have been saying in the conclusion that the _mechanism of our
  8819. ordinary knowledge is of a cinematographical kind_.
  8820. Of the altogether practical character of this operation there is no
  8821. possible doubt. Each of our acts aims at a certain insertion of our will
  8822. into the reality. There is, between our body and other bodies, an
  8823. arrangement like that of the pieces of glass that compose a
  8824. kaleidoscopic picture. Our activity goes from an arrangement to a
  8825. rearrangement, each time no doubt giving the kaleidoscope a new shake,
  8826. but not interesting itself in the shake, and seeing only the new
  8827. picture. Our knowledge of the operation of nature must be exactly
  8828. symmetrical, therefore, with the interest we take in our own operation.
  8829. In this sense we may say, if we are not abusing this kind of
  8830. illustration, that _the cinematographical character of our knowledge of
  8831. things is due to the kaleidoscopic character of our adaptation to them_.
  8832. The cinematographical method is therefore the only practical method,
  8833. since it consists in making the general character of knowledge form
  8834. itself on that of action, while expecting that the detail of each act
  8835. should depend in its turn on that of knowledge. In order that action may
  8836. always be enlightened, intelligence must always be present in it; but
  8837. intelligence, in order thus to accompany the progress of activity and
  8838. ensure its direction, must begin by adopting its rhythm. Action is
  8839. discontinuous, like every pulsation of life; discontinuous, therefore,
  8840. is knowledge. The mechanism of the faculty of knowing has been
  8841. constructed on this plan. Essentially practical, can it be of use, such
  8842. as it is, for speculation? Let us try with it to follow reality in its
  8843. windings, and see what will happen.
  8844. I take of the continuity of a particular becoming a series of views,
  8845. which I connect together by "becoming in general." But of course I
  8846. cannot stop there. What is not determinable is not representable: of
  8847. "becoming in general" I have only a verbal knowledge. As the letter _x_
  8848. designates a certain unknown quantity, whatever it may be, so my
  8849. "becoming in general," always the same, symbolizes here a certain
  8850. transition of which I have taken some snapshots; of the transition
  8851. itself it teaches me nothing. Let me then concentrate myself wholly on
  8852. the transition, and, between any two snapshots, endeavor to realize what
  8853. is going on. As I apply the same method, I obtain the same result; a
  8854. third view merely slips in between the two others. I may begin again as
  8855. often as I will, I may set views alongside of views for ever, I shall
  8856. obtain nothing else. The application of the cinematographical method
  8857. therefore leads to a perpetual recommencement, during which the mind,
  8858. never able to satisfy itself and never finding where to rest, persuades
  8859. itself, no doubt, that it imitates by its instability the very movement
  8860. of the real. But though, by straining itself to the point of giddiness,
  8861. it may end by giving itself the illusion of mobility, its operation has
  8862. not advanced it a step, since it remains as far as ever from its goal.
  8863. In order to advance with the moving reality, you must replace yourself
  8864. within it. Install yourself within change, and you will grasp at once
  8865. both change itself and the successive states in which _it might_ at any
  8866. instant be immobilized. But with these successive states, perceived from
  8867. without as real and no longer as potential immobilities, you will never
  8868. reconstitute movement. Call them _qualities_, _forms_, _positions_, or
  8869. _intentions_, as the case may be, multiply the number of them as you
  8870. will, let the interval between two consecutive states be infinitely
  8871. small: before the intervening movement you will always experience the
  8872. disappointment of the child who tries by clapping his hands together to
  8873. crush the smoke. The movement slips through the interval, because every
  8874. attempt to reconstitute change out of states implies the absurd
  8875. proposition, that movement is made of immobilities.
  8876. Philosophy perceived this as soon as it opened its eyes. The arguments
  8877. of Zeno of Elea, although formulated with a very different intention,
  8878. have no other meaning.
  8879. Take the flying arrow. At every moment, says Zeno, it is motionless, for
  8880. it cannot have time to move, that is, to occupy at least two successive
  8881. positions, unless at least two moments are allowed it. At a given
  8882. moment, therefore, it is at rest at a given point. Motionless in each
  8883. point of its course, it is motionless during all the time that it is
  8884. moving.
  8885. Yes, if we suppose that the arrow can ever _be_ in a point of its
  8886. course. Yes again, if the arrow, which is moving, ever coincides with a
  8887. position, which is motionless. But the arrow never _is_ in any point of
  8888. its course. The most we can say is that it might be there, in this
  8889. sense, that it passes there and might stop there. It is true that if it
  8890. did stop there, it would be at rest there, and at this point it is no
  8891. longer movement that we should have to do with. The truth is that if the
  8892. arrow leaves the point A to fall down at the point B, its movement AB is
  8893. as simple, as indecomposable, in so far as it is movement, as the
  8894. tension of the bow that shoots it. As the shrapnel, bursting before it
  8895. falls to the ground, covers the explosive zone with an indivisible
  8896. danger, so the arrow which goes from A to B displays with a single
  8897. stroke, although over a certain extent of duration, its indivisible
  8898. mobility. Suppose an elastic stretched from A to B, could you divide its
  8899. extension? The course of the arrow is this very extension; it is equally
  8900. simple and equally undivided. It is a single and unique bound. You fix a
  8901. point C in the interval passed, and say that at a certain moment the
  8902. arrow was in C. If it had been there, it would have been stopped there,
  8903. and you would no longer have had a flight from A to B, but _two_
  8904. flights, one from A to C and the other from C to B, with an interval of
  8905. rest. A single movement is entirely, by the hypothesis, a movement
  8906. between two stops; if there are intermediate stops, it is no longer a
  8907. single movement. At bottom, the illusion arises from this, that the
  8908. movement, _once effected_, has laid along its course a motionless
  8909. trajectory on which we can count as many immobilities as we will. From
  8910. this we conclude that the movement, _whilst being effected_, lays at
  8911. each instant beneath it a position with which it coincides. We do not
  8912. see that the trajectory is created in one stroke, although a certain
  8913. time is required for it; and that though we can divide at will the
  8914. trajectory once created, we cannot divide its creation, which is an act
  8915. in progress and not a thing. To suppose that the moving body _is_ at a
  8916. point of its course is to cut the course in two by a snip of the
  8917. scissors at this point, and to substitute two trajectories for the
  8918. single trajectory which we were first considering. It is to distinguish
  8919. two successive acts where, by the hypothesis, there is only one. In
  8920. short, it is to attribute to the course itself of the arrow everything
  8921. that can be said of the interval that the arrow has traversed, that is
  8922. to say, to admit _a priori_ the absurdity that movement coincides with
  8923. immobility.
  8924. We shall not dwell here on the three other arguments of Zeno. We have
  8925. examined them elsewhere. It is enough to point out that they all consist
  8926. in applying the movement to the line traversed, and supposing that what
  8927. is true of the line is true of the movement. The line, for example, may
  8928. be divided into as many parts as we wish, of any length that we wish,
  8929. and it is always the same line. From this we conclude that we have the
  8930. right to suppose the movement articulated as we wish, and that it is
  8931. always the same movement. We thus obtain a series of absurdities that
  8932. all express the same fundamental absurdity. But the possibility of
  8933. applying the movement _to_ the line traversed exists only for an
  8934. observer who keeping outside the movement and seeing at every instant
  8935. the possibility of a stop, tries to reconstruct the real movement with
  8936. these possible immobilities. The absurdity vanishes as soon as we adopt
  8937. by thought the continuity of the real movement, a continuity of which
  8938. every one of us is conscious whenever he lifts an arm or advances a
  8939. step. We feel then indeed that the line passed over between two stops is
  8940. described with a single indivisible stroke, and that we seek in vain to
  8941. practice on the movement, which traces the line, divisions
  8942. corresponding, each to each, with the divisions arbitrarily chosen of
  8943. the line once it has been traced. The line traversed by the moving body
  8944. lends itself to any kind of division, because it has no internal
  8945. organization. But all movement is articulated inwardly. It is either an
  8946. indivisible bound (which may occupy, nevertheless, a very long duration)
  8947. or a series of indivisible bounds. Take the articulations of this
  8948. movement into account, or give up speculating on its nature.
  8949. When Achilles pursues the tortoise, each of his steps must be treated as
  8950. indivisible, and so must each step of the tortoise. After a certain
  8951. number of steps, Achilles will have overtaken the tortoise. There is
  8952. nothing more simple. If you insist on dividing the two motions further,
  8953. distinguish both on the one side and on the other, in the course of
  8954. Achilles and in that of the tortoise, the _sub-multiples_ of the steps
  8955. of each of them; but respect the natural articulations of the two
  8956. courses. As long as you respect them, no difficulty will arise, because
  8957. you will follow the indications of experience. But Zeno's device is to
  8958. reconstruct the movement of Achilles according to a law arbitrarily
  8959. chosen. Achilles with a first step is supposed to arrive at the point
  8960. where the tortoise was, with a second step at the point which it has
  8961. moved to while he was making the first, and so on. In this case,
  8962. Achilles would always have a new step to take. But obviously, to
  8963. overtake the tortoise, he goes about it in quite another way. The
  8964. movement considered by Zeno would only be the equivalent of the movement
  8965. of Achilles if we could treat the movement as we treat the interval
  8966. passed through, decomposable and recomposable at will. Once you
  8967. subscribe to this first absurdity, all the others follow.[99]
  8968. Nothing would be easier, now, than to extend Zeno's argument to
  8969. qualitative becoming and to evolutionary becoming. We should find the
  8970. same contradictions in these. That the child can become a youth, ripen
  8971. to maturity and decline to old age, we understand when we consider that
  8972. vital evolution is here the reality itself. Infancy, adolescence,
  8973. maturity, old age, are mere views of the mind, _possible stops_ imagined
  8974. by us, from without, along the continuity of a progress. On the
  8975. contrary, let childhood, adolescence, maturity and old age be given as
  8976. integral parts of the evolution, they become _real stops_, and we can no
  8977. longer conceive how evolution is possible, for rests placed beside rests
  8978. will never be equivalent to a movement. How, with what is made, can we
  8979. reconstitute what is being made? How, for instance, from childhood once
  8980. posited as a _thing_, shall we pass to adolescence, when, by the
  8981. hypothesis, childhood only is given? If we look at it closely, we shall
  8982. see that our habitual manner of speaking, which is fashioned after our
  8983. habitual manner of thinking, leads us to actual logical
  8984. dead-locks--dead-locks to which we allow ourselves to be led without
  8985. anxiety, because we feel confusedly that we can always get out of them
  8986. if we like: all that we have to do, in fact, is to give up the
  8987. cinematographical habits of our intellect. When we say "The child
  8988. becomes a man," let us take care not to fathom too deeply the literal
  8989. meaning of the expression, or we shall find that, when we posit the
  8990. subject "child," the attribute "man" does not yet apply to it, and
  8991. that, when we express the attribute "man," it applies no more to the
  8992. subject "child." The reality, which is the _transition_ from childhood
  8993. to manhood, has slipped between our fingers. We have only the imaginary
  8994. stops "child" and "man," and we are very near to saying that one of
  8995. these stops _is_ the other, just as the arrow of Zeno _is_, according to
  8996. that philosopher, at all the points of the course. The truth is that if
  8997. language here were molded on reality, we should not say "The child
  8998. becomes the man," but "There is becoming from the child to the man." In
  8999. the first proposition, "becomes" is a verb of indeterminate meaning,
  9000. intended to mask the absurdity into which we fall when we attribute the
  9001. state "man" to the subject "child." It behaves in much the same way as
  9002. the movement, always the same, of the cinematographical film, a movement
  9003. hidden in the apparatus and whose function it is to superpose the
  9004. successive pictures on one another in order to imitate the movement of
  9005. the real object. In the second proposition, "becoming" is a subject. It
  9006. comes to the front. It is the reality itself; childhood and manhood are
  9007. then only possible stops, mere views of the mind; we now have to do with
  9008. the objective movement itself, and no longer with its cinematographical
  9009. imitation. But the first manner of expression is alone conformable to
  9010. our habits of language. We must, in order to adopt the second, escape
  9011. from the cinematographical mechanism of thought.
  9012. We must make complete abstraction of this mechanism, if we wish to get
  9013. rid at one stroke of the theoretical absurdities that the question of
  9014. movement raises. All is obscure, all is contradictory when we try, with
  9015. states, to build up a transition. The obscurity is cleared up, the
  9016. contradiction vanishes, as soon as we place ourselves along the
  9017. transition, in order to distinguish states in it by making cross cuts
  9018. therein in thought. The reason is that there is _more_ in the transition
  9019. than the series of states, that is to say, the possible cuts--_more_ in
  9020. the movement than the series of positions, that is to say, the possible
  9021. stops. Only, the first way of looking at things is conformable to the
  9022. processes of the human mind; the second requires, on the contrary, that
  9023. we reverse the bent of our intellectual habits. No wonder, then, if
  9024. philosophy at first recoiled before such an effort. The Greeks trusted
  9025. to nature, trusted the natural propensity of the mind, trusted language
  9026. above all, in so far as it naturally externalizes thought. Rather than
  9027. lay blame on the attitude of thought and language toward the course of
  9028. things, they preferred to pronounce the course of things itself to be
  9029. wrong.
  9030. Such, indeed, was the sentence passed by the philosophers of the Eleatic
  9031. school. And they passed it without any reservation whatever. As becoming
  9032. shocks the habits of thought and fits ill into the molds of language,
  9033. they declared it unreal. In spatial movement and in change in general
  9034. they saw only pure illusion. This conclusion could be softened down
  9035. without changing the premisses, by saying that the reality changes, but
  9036. that it _ought not_ to change. Experience confronts us with becoming:
  9037. that is _sensible_ reality. But the _intelligible_ reality, that which
  9038. _ought_ to be, is more real still, and that reality does not change.
  9039. Beneath the qualitative becoming, beneath the evolutionary becoming,
  9040. beneath the extensive becoming, the mind must seek that which defies
  9041. change, the definable quality, the form or essence, the end. Such was
  9042. the fundamental principle of the philosophy which developed throughout
  9043. the classic age, the philosophy of Forms, or, to use a term more akin to
  9044. the Greek, the philosophy of Ideas.
  9045. The word [Greek: eidos], which we translate here by "Idea," has, in
  9046. fact, this threefold meaning. It denotes (1) the quality, (2) the form
  9047. or essence, (3) the end or _design_ (in the sense of _intention_) of the
  9048. act being performed, that is to say, at bottom, the _design_ (in the
  9049. sense of _drawing_) of the act supposed accomplished. _These three
  9050. aspects are those of the adjective, substantive and verb, and correspond
  9051. to the three essential categories of language._ After the explanations
  9052. we have given above, we might, and perhaps we ought to, translate
  9053. [Greek: eidos] by "view" or rather by "moment." For [Greek: eidos] is
  9054. the stable view taken of the instability of things: the _quality_, which
  9055. is a moment of becoming; the _form_, which is a moment of evolution; the
  9056. _essence_, which is the mean form above and below which the other forms
  9057. are arranged as alterations of the mean; finally, the intention or
  9058. _mental design_ which presides over the action being accomplished, and
  9059. which is nothing else, we said, than the _material design_, traced out
  9060. and contemplated beforehand, of the action accomplished. To reduce
  9061. things to Ideas is therefore to resolve becoming into its principal
  9062. moments, each of these being, moreover, by the hypothesis, screened from
  9063. the laws of time and, as it were, plucked out of eternity. That is to
  9064. say that we end in the philosophy of Ideas when we apply the
  9065. cinematographical mechanism of the intellect to the analysis of the
  9066. real.
  9067. But, when we put immutable Ideas at the base of the moving reality, a
  9068. whole physics, a whole cosmology, a whole theology follows necessarily.
  9069. We must insist on the point. Not that we mean to summarize in a few
  9070. pages a philosophy so complex and so comprehensive as that of the
  9071. Greeks. But, since we have described the cinematographical mechanism of
  9072. the intellect, it is important that we should show to what idea of
  9073. reality the play of this mechanism leads. It is the very idea, we
  9074. believe, that we find in the ancient philosophy. The main lines of the
  9075. doctrine that was developed from Plato to Plotinus, passing through
  9076. Aristotle (and even, in a certain measure, through the Stoics), have
  9077. nothing accidental, nothing contingent, nothing that must be regarded as
  9078. a philosopher's fancy. They indicate the vision that a systematic
  9079. intellect obtains of the universal becoming when regarding it by means
  9080. of snapshots, taken at intervals, of its flowing. So that, even to-day,
  9081. we shall philosophize in the manner of the Greeks, we shall rediscover,
  9082. without needing to know them, such and such of their general
  9083. conclusions, in the exact proportion that we trust in the
  9084. cinematographical instinct of our thought.
  9085. * * * * *
  9086. We said there is _more_ in a movement than in the successive positions
  9087. attributed to the moving object, _more_ in a becoming than in the forms
  9088. passed through in turn, _more_ in the evolution of form than the forms
  9089. assumed one after another. Philosophy can therefore derive terms of the
  9090. second kind from those of the first, but not the first from the second:
  9091. from the first terms speculation must take its start. But the intellect
  9092. reverses the order of the two groups; and, on this point, ancient
  9093. philosophy proceeds as the intellect does. It installs itself in the
  9094. immutable, it posits only Ideas. Yet becoming exists: it is a fact. How,
  9095. then, having posited immutability alone, shall we make change come forth
  9096. from it? Not by the addition of anything, for, by the hypothesis, there
  9097. exists nothing positive outside Ideas. It must therefore be by a
  9098. diminution. So at the base of ancient philosophy lies necessarily this
  9099. postulate: that there is more in the motionless than in the moving, and
  9100. that we pass from immutability to becoming by way of diminution or
  9101. attenuation.
  9102. It is therefore something negative, or zero at most, that must be added
  9103. to Ideas to obtain change. In that consists the Platonic "non-being,"
  9104. the Aristotelian "matter"--a metaphysical zero which, joined to the
  9105. Idea, like the arithmetical zero to unity, multiplies it in space and
  9106. time. By it the motionless and simple Idea is refracted into a movement
  9107. spread out indefinitely. In right, there ought to be nothing but
  9108. immutable Ideas, immutably fitted to each other. In fact, matter comes
  9109. to add to them its void, and thereby lets loose the universal becoming.
  9110. It is an elusive nothing, that creeps between the Ideas and creates
  9111. endless agitation, eternal disquiet, like a suspicion insinuated between
  9112. two loving hearts. Degrade the immutable Ideas: you obtain, by that
  9113. alone, the perpetual flux of things. The Ideas or Forms are the whole of
  9114. intelligible reality, that is to say, of truth, in that they represent,
  9115. all together, the theoretical equilibrium of Being. As to sensible
  9116. reality, it is a perpetual oscillation from one side to the other of
  9117. this point of equilibrium.
  9118. Hence, throughout the whole philosophy of Ideas there is a certain
  9119. conception of duration, as also of the relation of time to eternity. He
  9120. who installs himself in becoming sees in duration the very life of
  9121. things, the fundamental reality. The Forms, which the mind isolates and
  9122. stores up in concepts, are then only snapshots of the changing reality.
  9123. They are moments gathered along the course of time; and, just because we
  9124. have cut the thread that binds them to time, they no longer endure. They
  9125. tend to withdraw into their own definition, that is to say, into the
  9126. artificial reconstruction and symbolical expression which is their
  9127. intellectual equivalent. They enter into eternity, if you will; but what
  9128. is eternal in them is just what is unreal. On the contrary, if we treat
  9129. becoming by the cinematographical method, the Forms are no longer
  9130. snapshots taken of the change, they are its constitutive elements, they
  9131. represent all that is positive in Becoming. Eternity no longer hovers
  9132. over time, as an abstraction; it underlies time, as a reality. Such is
  9133. exactly, on this point, the attitude of the philosophy of Forms or
  9134. Ideas. It establishes between eternity and time the same relation as
  9135. between a piece of gold and the small change--change so small that
  9136. payment goes on for ever without the debt being paid off. The debt could
  9137. be paid at once with the piece of gold. It is this that Plato expresses
  9138. in his magnificent language when he says that God, unable to make the
  9139. world eternal, gave it Time, "a moving image of eternity."[100]
  9140. Hence also arises a certain conception of extension, which is at the
  9141. base of the philosophy of Ideas, although it has not been so explicitly
  9142. brought out. Let us imagine a mind placed alongside becoming, and
  9143. adopting its movement. Each successive state, each quality, each form,
  9144. in short, will be seen by it as a mere cut made by thought in the
  9145. universal becoming. It will be found that form is essentially extended,
  9146. inseparable as it is from the extensity of the becoming which has
  9147. materialized it in the course of its flow. Every form thus occupies
  9148. space, as it occupies time. But the philosophy of Ideas follows the
  9149. inverse direction. It starts from the Form; it sees in the Form the very
  9150. essence of reality. It does not take Form as a snapshot of becoming; it
  9151. posits Forms in the eternal; of this motionless eternity, then, duration
  9152. and becoming are supposed to be only the degradation. Form thus posited,
  9153. independent of time, is then no longer what is found in a perception; it
  9154. is a _concept_. And, as a reality of the conceptual order occupies no
  9155. more of extension than it does of duration, the Forms must be stationed
  9156. outside space as well as above time. Space and time have therefore
  9157. necessarily, in ancient philosophy, the same origin and the same value.
  9158. The same diminution of being is expressed both by extension in space and
  9159. detention in time. Both of these are but the distance between what is
  9160. and what ought to be. From the standpoint of ancient philosophy, space
  9161. and time can be nothing but the field that an incomplete reality, or
  9162. rather a reality that has gone astray from itself, needs in order to run
  9163. in quest of itself. Only it must be admitted that the field is created
  9164. as the hunting progresses, and that the hunting in some way deposits the
  9165. field beneath it. Move an imaginary pendulum, a mere mathematical point,
  9166. from its position of equilibrium: a perpetual oscillation is started,
  9167. along which points are placed next to points, and moments succeed
  9168. moments. The space and time which thus arise have no more "positivity"
  9169. than the movement itself. They represent the remoteness of the position
  9170. artificially given to the pendulum from its normal position, _what it
  9171. lacks_ in order to regain its natural stability. Bring it back to its
  9172. normal position: space, time and motion shrink to a mathematical point.
  9173. Just so, human reasonings are drawn out into an endless chain, but are
  9174. at once swallowed up in the truth seized by intuition, for their
  9175. extension in space and time is only the distance, so to speak, between
  9176. thought and truth.[101] So of extension and duration in relation to pure
  9177. Forms or Ideas. The sensible forms are before us, ever about to recover
  9178. their ideality, ever prevented by the matter they bear in them, that is
  9179. to say, by their inner void, by the interval between what they are and
  9180. what they ought to be. They are for ever on the point of recovering
  9181. themselves, for ever occupied in losing themselves. An inflexible law
  9182. condemns them, like the rock of Sisyphus, to fall back when they are
  9183. almost touching the summit, and this law, which has projected them into
  9184. space and time, is nothing other than the very constancy of their
  9185. original insufficiency. The alternations of generation and decay, the
  9186. evolutions ever beginning over and over again, the infinite repetition
  9187. of the cycles of celestial spheres--this all represents merely a certain
  9188. fundamental deficit, in which materiality consists. Fill up this
  9189. deficit: at once you suppress space and time, that is to say, the
  9190. endlessly renewed oscillations around a stable equilibrium always aimed
  9191. at, never reached. Things re-enter into each other. What was extended in
  9192. space is contracted into pure Form. And past, present, and future shrink
  9193. into a single moment, which is eternity.
  9194. This amounts to saying that physics is but logic spoiled. In this
  9195. proposition the whole philosophy of Ideas is summarized. And in it also
  9196. is the hidden principle of the philosophy that is innate in our
  9197. understanding. If immutability is more than becoming, form is more than
  9198. change, and it is by a veritable fall that the logical system of Ideas,
  9199. rationally subordinated and coördinated among themselves, is scattered
  9200. into a physical series of objects and events accidentally placed one
  9201. after another. The generative idea of a poem is developed in thousands
  9202. of imaginations which are materialized in phrases that spread themselves
  9203. out in words. And the more we descend from the motionless idea, wound on
  9204. itself, to the words that unwind it, the more room is left for
  9205. contingency and choice. Other metaphors, expressed by other words, might
  9206. have arisen; an image is called up by an image, a word by a word. All
  9207. these words run now one after another, seeking in vain, by themselves,
  9208. to give back the simplicity of the generative idea. Our ear only hears
  9209. the words: it therefore perceives only accidents. But our mind, by
  9210. successive bounds, leaps from the words to the images, from the images
  9211. to the original idea, and so gets back, from the perception of
  9212. words--accidents called up by accidents--to the conception of the Idea
  9213. that posits its own being. So the philosopher proceeds, confronted with
  9214. the universe. Experience makes to pass before his eyes phenomena which
  9215. run, they also, one behind another in an accidental order determined by
  9216. circumstances of time and place. This physical order--a degeneration of
  9217. the logical order--is nothing else but the fall of the logical into
  9218. space and time. But the philosopher, ascending again from the percept to
  9219. the concept, sees condensed into the logical all the positive reality
  9220. that the physical possesses. His intellect, doing away with the
  9221. materiality that lessens being, grasps being itself in the immutable
  9222. system of Ideas. Thus Science is obtained, which appears to us, complete
  9223. and ready-made, as soon as we put back our intellect into its true
  9224. place, correcting the deviation that separated it from the intelligible.
  9225. Science is not, then, a human construction. It is prior to our
  9226. intellect, independent of it, veritably the generator of Things.
  9227. And indeed, if we hold the Forms to be simply snapshots taken by the
  9228. mind of the continuity of becoming, they must be relative to the mind
  9229. that thinks them, they can have no independent existence. At most we
  9230. might say that each of these Ideas is an _ideal_. But it is in the
  9231. opposite hypothesis that we are placing ourselves. Ideas must then exist
  9232. by themselves. Ancient philosophy could not escape this conclusion.
  9233. Plato formulated it, and in vain did Aristotle strive to avoid it. Since
  9234. movement arises from the degradation of the immutable, there could be no
  9235. movement, consequently no sensible world, if there were not, somewhere,
  9236. immutability realized. So, having begun by refusing to Ideas an
  9237. independent existence, and finding himself nevertheless unable to
  9238. deprive them of it, Aristotle pressed them into each other, rolled them
  9239. up into a ball, and set above the physical world a Form that was thus
  9240. found to be the Form of Forms, the Idea of Ideas, or, to use his own
  9241. words, the Thought of Thought. Such is the God of Aristotle--necessarily
  9242. immutable and apart from what is happening in the world, since he is
  9243. only the synthesis of all concepts in a single concept. It is true that
  9244. no one of the manifold concepts could exist apart, such as it is in the
  9245. divine unity: in vain should we look for the ideas of Plato within the
  9246. God of Aristotle. But if only we imagine the God of Aristotle in a sort
  9247. of refraction of himself, or simply inclining toward the world, at once
  9248. the Platonic Ideas are seen to pour themselves out of him, as if they
  9249. were involved in the unity of his essence: so rays stream out from the
  9250. sun, which nevertheless did not contain them. It is probably this
  9251. _possibility of an outpouring_ of Platonic Ideas from the Aristotelian
  9252. God that is meant, in the philosophy of Aristotle, by the active
  9253. intellect, the [Greek: nous] that has been called [Greek:
  9254. poiêtikos]--that is, by what is essential and yet unconscious in human
  9255. intelligence. The [Greek: nous poiêtikos] is Science entire, posited all
  9256. at once, which the conscious, discursive intellect is condemned to
  9257. reconstruct with difficulty, bit by bit. There is then within us, or
  9258. rather behind us, a possible vision of God, as the Alexandrians said, a
  9259. vision always virtual, never actually realized by the conscious
  9260. intellect. In this intuition we should see God expand in Ideas. This it
  9261. is that "does everything,"[102] playing in relation to the discursive
  9262. intellect, which moves in time, the same rôle as the motionless Mover
  9263. himself plays in relation to the movement of the heavens and the course
  9264. of things.
  9265. There is, then, immanent in the philosophy of Ideas, a particular
  9266. conception of causality, which it is important to bring into full
  9267. light, because it is that which each of us will reach when, in order to
  9268. ascend to the origin of things, he follows to the end the natural
  9269. movement of the intellect. True, the ancient philosophers never
  9270. formulated it explicitly. They confined themselves to drawing the
  9271. consequences of it, and, in general, they have marked but points of view
  9272. of it rather than presented it itself. Sometimes, indeed, they speak of
  9273. an _attraction_, sometimes of an _impulsion_ exercised by the prime
  9274. mover on the whole of the world. Both views are found in Aristotle, who
  9275. shows us in the movement of the universe an aspiration of things toward
  9276. the divine perfection, and consequently an ascent toward God, while he
  9277. describes it elsewhere as the effect of a contact of God with the first
  9278. sphere and as descending, consequently, from God to things. The
  9279. Alexandrians, we think, do no more than follow this double indication
  9280. when they speak of _procession_ and _conversion_. Everything is derived
  9281. from the first principle, and everything aspires to return to it. But
  9282. these two conceptions of the divine causality can only be identified
  9283. together if we bring them, both the one and the other, back to a third,
  9284. which we hold to be fundamental, and which alone will enable us to
  9285. understand, not only why, in what sense, things move in space and time,
  9286. but also why there is space and time, why there is movement, why there
  9287. are things.
  9288. This conception, which more and more shows through the reasonings of the
  9289. Greek philosophers as we go from Plato to Plotinus, we may formulate
  9290. thus: _The affirmation of a reality implies the simultaneous affirmation
  9291. of all the degrees of reality intermediate between it and nothing._ The
  9292. principle is evident in the case of number: we cannot affirm the number
  9293. 10 without thereby affirming the existence of the numbers 9, 8, 7, ...,
  9294. etc.--in short, of the whole interval between 10 and zero. But here our
  9295. mind passes naturally from the sphere of quantity to that of quality.
  9296. It seems to us that, a certain perfection being given, the whole
  9297. continuity of degradations is given also between this perfection, on the
  9298. one hand, and the nought, on the other hand, that we think we conceive.
  9299. Let us then posit the God of Aristotle, thought of thought--that is,
  9300. thought _making a circle_, transforming itself from subject to object
  9301. and from object to subject by an instantaneous, or rather an eternal,
  9302. circular process: as, on the other hand, the nought appears to posit
  9303. itself, and as, the two extremities being given, the interval between
  9304. them is equally given, it follows that all the descending degrees of
  9305. being, from the divine perfection down to the "absolute nothing," are
  9306. realized automatically, so to speak, when we have posited God.
  9307. Let us then run through this interval from top to bottom. First of all,
  9308. the slightest diminution of the first principle will be enough to
  9309. precipitate Being into space and time; but duration and extension, which
  9310. represent this first diminution, will be as near as possible to the
  9311. divine inextension and eternity. We must therefore picture to ourselves
  9312. this first degradation of the divine principle as a sphere turning on
  9313. itself, imitating, by the perpetuity of its circular movement, the
  9314. eternity of the circle of the divine thought; creating, moreover, its
  9315. own place, and thereby place in general,[103] since it includes without
  9316. being included and moves without stirring from the spot; creating also
  9317. its own duration, and thereby duration in general, since its movement is
  9318. the measure of all motion.[104] Then, by degrees, we shall see the
  9319. perfection decrease, more and more, down to our sublunary world, in
  9320. which the cycle of birth, growth and decay imitates and mars the
  9321. original circle for the last time. So understood, the causal relation
  9322. between God and the world is seen as an attraction when regarded from
  9323. below, as an impulsion or a contact when regarded from above, since the
  9324. first heaven, with its circular movement, is an imitation of God and all
  9325. imitation is the reception of a form. Therefore, we perceive God as
  9326. efficient cause or as final cause, according to the point of view. And
  9327. yet neither of these two relations is the ultimate causal relation. The
  9328. true relation is that which is found between the two members of an
  9329. equation, when the first member is a single term and the second a sum of
  9330. an endless number of terms. It is, we may say, the relation of the
  9331. gold-piece to the small change, if we suppose the change to offer itself
  9332. automatically as soon as the gold piece is presented. Only thus can we
  9333. understand why Aristotle has demonstrated the necessity of a first
  9334. motionless mover, not by founding it on the assertion that the movement
  9335. of things must have had a beginning, but, on the contrary, by affirming
  9336. that this movement could not have begun and can never come to an end. If
  9337. movement exists, or, in other words, if the small change is being
  9338. counted, the gold piece is to be found somewhere. And if the counting
  9339. goes on for ever, having never begun, the single term that is eminently
  9340. equivalent to it must be eternal. A perpetuity of mobility is possible
  9341. only if it is backed by an eternity of immutability, which it unwinds in
  9342. a chain without beginning or end.
  9343. Such is the last word of the Greek philosophy. We have not attempted to
  9344. reconstruct it _a priori_. It has manifold origins. It is connected by
  9345. many invisible threads to the soul of ancient Greece. Vain, therefore,
  9346. the effort to deduce it from a simple principle.[105] But if everything
  9347. that has come from poetry, religion, social life and a still rudimentary
  9348. physics and biology be removed from it, if we take away all the light
  9349. material that may have been used in the construction of the stately
  9350. building, a solid framework remains, and this framework marks out the
  9351. main lines of a metaphysic which is, we believe, the natural metaphysic
  9352. of the human intellect. We come to a philosophy of this kind, indeed,
  9353. whenever we follow to the end, the cinematographical tendency of
  9354. perception and thought. Our perception and thought begin by substituting
  9355. for the continuity of evolutionary change a series of unchangeable forms
  9356. which are turn by turn, "caught on the wing," like the rings at a
  9357. merry-go-round, which the children unhook with their little stick as
  9358. they are passing. Now, how can the forms be passing, and on what "stick"
  9359. are they strung? As the stable forms have been obtained by extracting
  9360. from change everything that is definite, there is nothing left, to
  9361. characterize the instability on which the forms are laid, but a negative
  9362. attribute, which must be indetermination itself. Such is the first
  9363. proceeding of our thought: it dissociates each change into two
  9364. elements--the one stable, definable for each particular case, to wit,
  9365. the Form; the other indefinable and always the same, Change in general.
  9366. And such, also, is the essential operation of language. Forms are all
  9367. that it is capable of expressing. It is reduced to taking as understood
  9368. or is limited to _suggesting_ a mobility which, just because it is
  9369. always unexpressed, is thought to remain in all cases the same.--Then
  9370. comes in a philosophy that holds the dissociation thus effected by
  9371. thought and language to be legitimate. What can it do, except objectify
  9372. the distinction with more force, push it to its extreme consequences,
  9373. reduce it into a system? It will therefore construct the real, on the
  9374. one hand, with definite Forms or immutable elements, and, on the other,
  9375. with a principle of mobility which, being the negation of the form,
  9376. will, by the hypothesis, escape all definition and be the purely
  9377. indeterminate. The more it directs its attention to the forms delineated
  9378. by thought and expressed by language, the more it will see them rise
  9379. above the sensible and become subtilized into pure concepts, capable of
  9380. entering one within the other, and even of being at last massed together
  9381. into a single concept, the synthesis of all reality, the achievement of
  9382. all perfection. The more, on the contrary, it descends toward the
  9383. invisible source of the universal mobility, the more it will feel this
  9384. mobility sink beneath it and at the same time become void, vanish into
  9385. what it will call the "non-being." Finally, it will have on the one hand
  9386. the system of ideas, logically coördinated together or concentrated into
  9387. one only, on the other a quasi-nought, the Platonic "non-being" or the
  9388. Aristotelian "matter."--But, having cut your cloth, you must sew it.
  9389. With supra-sensible Ideas and an infra-sensible non-being, you now have
  9390. to reconstruct the sensible world. You can do so only if you postulate a
  9391. kind of metaphysical necessity in virtue of which the confronting of
  9392. this All with this Zero _is equivalent_ to the affirmation of all the
  9393. degrees of reality that measure the interval between them--just as an
  9394. undivided number, when regarded as a difference between itself and zero,
  9395. is revealed as a certain sum of units, and with its own affirmation
  9396. affirms all the lower numbers. That is the natural postulate. It is that
  9397. also that we perceive as the base of the Greek philosophy. In order then
  9398. to explain the specific characters of each of these degrees of
  9399. intermediate reality, nothing more is necessary than to measure the
  9400. distance that separates it from the integral reality. Each lower degree
  9401. consists in a diminution of the higher, and the _sensible_ newness that
  9402. we perceive in it is resolved, from the point of view of the
  9403. _intelligible_, into a new quantity of negation which is superadded to
  9404. it. The smallest possible quantity of negation, that which is found
  9405. already in the highest forms of sensible reality, and consequently _a
  9406. fortiori_ in the lower forms, is that which is expressed by the most
  9407. general attributes of sensible reality, extension and duration. By
  9408. increasing degradations we will obtain attributes more and more special.
  9409. Here the philosopher's fancy will have free scope, for it is by an
  9410. arbitrary decree, or at least a debatable one, that a particular aspect
  9411. of the sensible world will be equated with a particular diminution of
  9412. being. We shall not necessarily end, as Aristotle did, in a world
  9413. consisting of concentric spheres turning on themselves. But we shall be
  9414. led to an analogous cosmology--I mean, to a construction whose pieces,
  9415. though all different, will have none the less the same relations between
  9416. them. And this cosmology will be ruled by the same principle. The
  9417. physical will be defined by the logical. Beneath the changing phenomena
  9418. will appear to us, by transparence, a closed system of concepts
  9419. subordinated to and coördinated with each other. Science, understood as
  9420. the system of concepts, will be more real than the sensible reality. It
  9421. will be prior to human knowledge, which is only able to spell it letter
  9422. by letter; prior also to things, which awkwardly try to imitate it. It
  9423. would only have to be diverted an instant from itself in order to step
  9424. out of its eternity and thereby coincide with all this knowledge and all
  9425. these things. Its immutability is therefore, indeed, the cause of the
  9426. universal becoming.
  9427. Such was the point of view of ancient philosophy in regard to change
  9428. and duration. That modern philosophy has repeatedly, but especially in
  9429. its beginnings, had the wish to depart from it, seems to us
  9430. unquestionable. But an irresistible attraction brings the intellect back
  9431. to its natural movement, and the metaphysic of the moderns to the
  9432. general conclusions of the Greek metaphysic. We must try to make this
  9433. point clear, in order to show by what invisible threads our mechanistic
  9434. philosophy remains bound to the ancient philosophy of Ideas, and how
  9435. also it responds to the requirements, above all practical, of our
  9436. understanding.
  9437. * * * * *
  9438. Modern, like ancient, science proceeds according to the
  9439. cinematographical method. It cannot do otherwise; all science is subject
  9440. to this law. For it is of the essence of science to handle _signs_,
  9441. which it substitutes for the objects themselves. These signs undoubtedly
  9442. differ from those of language by their greater precision and their
  9443. higher efficacy; they are none the less tied down to the general
  9444. condition of the sign, which is to denote a fixed aspect of the reality
  9445. under an arrested form. In order to think movement, a constantly renewed
  9446. effort of the mind is necessary. Signs are made to dispense us with this
  9447. effort by substituting, for the moving continuity of things, an
  9448. artificial reconstruction which is its equivalent in practice and has
  9449. the advantage of being easily handled. But let us leave aside the means
  9450. and consider only the end. What is the essential object of science? It
  9451. is to enlarge our influence over things. Science may be speculative in
  9452. its form, disinterested in its immediate ends; in other words we may
  9453. give it as long a credit as it wants. But, however long the day of
  9454. reckoning may be put off, some time or other the payment must be made.
  9455. It is always then, in short, practical utility that science has in view.
  9456. Even when it launches into theory, it is bound to adapt its behavior to
  9457. the general form of practice. However high it may rise, it must be ready
  9458. to fall back into the field of action, and at once to get on its feet.
  9459. This would not be possible for it, if its rhythm differed absolutely
  9460. from that of action itself. Now action, we have said, proceeds by leaps.
  9461. To act is to re-adapt oneself. To know, that is to say, to foresee in
  9462. order to act, is then to go from situation to situation, from
  9463. arrangement to rearrangement. Science may consider rearrangements that
  9464. come closer and closer to each other; it may thus increase the number of
  9465. moments that it isolates, but it always isolates moments. As to what
  9466. happens in the interval between the moments, science is no more
  9467. concerned with that than are our common intelligence, our senses and our
  9468. language: it does not bear on the interval, but only on the extremities.
  9469. So the cinematographical method forces itself upon our science, as it
  9470. did already on that of the ancients.
  9471. Wherein, then, is the difference between the two sciences? We indicated
  9472. it when we said that the ancients reduced the physical order to the
  9473. vital order, that is to say, laws to genera, while the moderns try to
  9474. resolve genera into laws. But we have to look at it in another aspect,
  9475. which, moreover, is only a transposition, of the first. Wherein consists
  9476. the difference of attitude of the two sciences toward change? We may
  9477. formulate it by saying that _ancient science thinks it knows its object
  9478. sufficiently when it has noted of it some privileged moments, whereas
  9479. modern science considers the object at any moment whatever_.
  9480. The forms or ideas of Plato or of Aristotle correspond to privileged or
  9481. salient moments in the history of things--those, in general, that have
  9482. been fixed by language. They are supposed, like the childhood or the old
  9483. age of a living being, to characterize a period of which they express
  9484. the quintessence, all the rest of this period being filled by the
  9485. passage, of no interest in itself, from one form to another form. Take,
  9486. for instance, a falling body. It was thought that we got near enough to
  9487. the fact when we characterized it as a whole: it was a movement
  9488. _downward_; it was the tendency toward a _centre_; it was the _natural_
  9489. movement of a body which, separated from the earth to which it belonged,
  9490. was now going to find its place again. They noted, then, the final term
  9491. or culminating point ([Greek: telos, akmê]) and set it up as the
  9492. essential moment: this moment, that language has retained in order to
  9493. express the whole of the fact, sufficed also for science to characterize
  9494. it. In the physics of Aristotle, it is by the concepts "high" and "low,"
  9495. spontaneous displacement and forced displacement, own place and strange
  9496. place, that the movement of a body shot into space or falling freely is
  9497. defined. But Galileo thought there was no essential moment, no
  9498. privileged instant. To study the falling body is to consider it at it
  9499. matters not what moment in its course. The true science of gravity is
  9500. that which will determine, for any moment of time whatever, the position
  9501. of the body in space. For this, indeed, signs far more precise than
  9502. those of language are required.
  9503. We may say, then, that our physics differs from that of the ancients
  9504. chiefly in the indefinite breaking up of time. For the ancients, time
  9505. comprises as many undivided periods as our natural perception and our
  9506. language cut out in it successive facts, each presenting a kind of
  9507. individuality. For that reason, each of these facts admits, in their
  9508. view, of only a _total_ definition or description. If, in describing it,
  9509. we are led to distinguish phases in it, we have several facts instead of
  9510. a single one, several undivided periods instead of a single period; but
  9511. time is always supposed to be divided into determinate periods, and the
  9512. mode of division to be forced on the mind by apparent crises of the
  9513. real, comparable to that of puberty, by the apparent release of a new
  9514. form.--For a Kepler or a Galileo, on the contrary, time is not divided
  9515. objectively in one way or another by the matter that fills it. It has no
  9516. natural articulations. We can, we ought to, divide it as we please. All
  9517. moments count. None of them has the right to set itself up as a moment
  9518. that represents or dominates the others. And, consequently, we know a
  9519. change only when we are able to determine what it is about at any one of
  9520. its moments.
  9521. The difference is profound. In fact, in a certain aspect it is radical.
  9522. But, from the point of view from which we are regarding it, it is a
  9523. difference of degree rather than of kind. The human mind has passed from
  9524. the first kind of knowledge to the second through gradual perfecting,
  9525. simply by seeking a higher precision. There is the same relation between
  9526. these two sciences as between the noting of the phases of a movement by
  9527. the eye and the much more complete recording of these phases by
  9528. instantaneous photography. It is the same cinematographical mechanism in
  9529. both cases, but it reaches a precision in the second that it cannot have
  9530. in the first. Of the gallop of a horse our eye perceives chiefly a
  9531. characteristic, essential or rather schematic attitude, a form that
  9532. appears to radiate over a whole period and so fill up a time of gallop.
  9533. It is this attitude that sculpture has fixed on the frieze of the
  9534. Parthenon. But instantaneous photography isolates any moment; it puts
  9535. them all in the same rank, and thus the gallop of a horse spreads out
  9536. for it into as many successive attitudes as it wishes, instead of
  9537. massing itself into a single attitude, which is supposed to flash out in
  9538. a privileged moment and to illuminate a whole period.
  9539. From this original difference flow all the others. A science that
  9540. considers, one after the other, undivided periods of duration, sees
  9541. nothing but phases succeeding phases, forms replacing forms; it is
  9542. content with a _qualitative_ description of objects, which it likens to
  9543. organized beings. But when we seek to know what happens within one of
  9544. these periods, at any moment of time, we are aiming at something
  9545. entirely different. The changes which are produced from one moment to
  9546. another are no longer, by the hypothesis, changes of quality; they are
  9547. _quantitative_ variations, it may be of the phenomenon itself, it may be
  9548. of its elementary parts. We were right then to say that modern science
  9549. is distinguishable from the ancient in that it applies to magnitudes and
  9550. proposes first and foremost to measure them. The ancients did indeed try
  9551. experiments, and on the other hand Kepler tried no experiment, in the
  9552. proper sense of the word, in order to discover a law which is the very
  9553. type of scientific knowledge as we understand it. What distinguishes
  9554. modern science is not that it is experimental, but that it experiments
  9555. and, more generally, works only with a view to measure.
  9556. For that reason it is right, again, to say that ancient science applied
  9557. to _concepts_, while modern science seeks _laws_--constant relations
  9558. between variable magnitudes. The concept of circularity was sufficient
  9559. to Aristotle to define the movement of the heavenly bodies. But, even
  9560. with the more accurate concept of elliptical form, Kepler did not think
  9561. he had accounted for the movement of planets. He had to get a law, that
  9562. is to say, a constant relation between the quantitative variations of
  9563. two or several elements of the planetary movement.
  9564. Yet these are only consequences--differences that follow from the
  9565. fundamental difference. It did happen to the ancients accidentally to
  9566. experiment with a view to measuring, as also to discover a law
  9567. expressing a constant relation between magnitudes. The principle of
  9568. Archimedes is a true experimental law. It takes into account three
  9569. variable magnitudes: the volume of a body, the density of the liquid in
  9570. which the body is immersed, the vertical pressure that is being exerted.
  9571. And it states indeed that one of these three terms is a function of the
  9572. other two.
  9573. The essential, original difference must therefore be sought elsewhere.
  9574. It is the same that we noticed first. The science of the ancients is
  9575. static. Either it considers in block the change that it studies, or, if
  9576. it divides the change into periods, it makes of each of these periods a
  9577. block in its turn: which amounts to saying that it takes no account of
  9578. time. But modern science has been built up around the discoveries of
  9579. Galileo and of Kepler, which immediately furnished it with a model. Now,
  9580. what do the laws of Kepler say? They lay down a relation between the
  9581. areas described by the heliocentric radius-vector of a planet and the
  9582. _time_ employed in describing them, a relation between the longer axis
  9583. of the orbit and the _time_ taken up by the course. And what was the
  9584. principle discovered by Galileo? A law which connected the space
  9585. traversed by a falling body with the _time_ occupied by the fall.
  9586. Furthermore, in what did the first of the great transformations of
  9587. geometry in modern times consist, if not in introducing--in a veiled
  9588. form, it is true--time and movement even in the consideration of
  9589. figures? For the ancients, geometry was a purely static science. Figures
  9590. were given to it at once, completely finished, like the Platonic Ideas.
  9591. But the essence of the Cartesian geometry (although Descartes did not
  9592. give it this form) was to regard every plane curve as described by the
  9593. movement of a point on a movable straight line which is displaced,
  9594. parallel to itself, along the axis of the abscissae--the displacement of
  9595. the movable straight line being supposed to be uniform and the abscissa
  9596. thus becoming representative of the time. The curve is then defined if
  9597. we can state the relation connecting the space traversed on the movable
  9598. straight line to the time employed in traversing it, that is, if we are
  9599. able to indicate the position of the movable point, on the straight line
  9600. which it traverses, at any moment whatever of its course. This relation
  9601. is just what we call the equation of the curve. To substitute an
  9602. equation for a figure consists, therefore, in seeing the actual position
  9603. of the moving points in the tracing of the curve at any moment whatever,
  9604. instead of regarding this tracing all at once, gathered up in the unique
  9605. moment when the curve has reached its finished state.
  9606. Such, then, was the directing idea of the reform by which both the
  9607. science of nature and mathematics, which serves as its instrument, were
  9608. renewed. Modern science is the daughter of astronomy; it has come down
  9609. from heaven to earth along the inclined plane of Galileo, for it is
  9610. through Galileo that Newton and his successors are connected with
  9611. Kepler. Now, how did the astronomical problem present itself to Kepler?
  9612. The question was, knowing the respective positions of the planets at a
  9613. given moment, how to calculate their positions at any other moment. So
  9614. the same question presented itself, henceforth, for every material
  9615. system. Each material point became a rudimentary planet, and the main
  9616. question, the ideal problem whose solution would yield the key to all
  9617. the others was, the positions of these elements at a particular moment
  9618. being given, how to determine their relative positions at any moment. No
  9619. doubt the problem cannot be put in these precise terms except in very
  9620. simple cases, for a schematized reality; for we never know the
  9621. respective positions of the real elements of matter, supposing there are
  9622. real elements; and, even if we knew them at a given moment, the
  9623. calculation of their positions at another moment would generally require
  9624. a mathematical effort surpassing human powers. But it is enough for us
  9625. to know that these elements might be known, that their present
  9626. positions might be noted, and that a superhuman intellect might, by
  9627. submitting these data to mathematical operations, determine the
  9628. positions of the elements at any other moment of time. This conviction
  9629. is at the bottom of the questions we put to ourselves on the subject of
  9630. nature, and of the methods we employ to solve them. That is why every
  9631. law in static form seems to us as a provisional instalment or as a
  9632. particular view of a dynamic law which alone would give us whole and
  9633. definitive knowledge.
  9634. Let us conclude, then, that our science is not only distinguished from
  9635. ancient science in this, that it seeks laws, nor even in this, that its
  9636. laws set forth relations between magnitudes: we must add that the
  9637. magnitude to which we wish to be able to relate all others is time, and
  9638. that _modern science must be defined pre-eminently by its aspiration to
  9639. take time as an independent variable_. But with what time has it to do?
  9640. We have said before, and we cannot repeat too often, that the science of
  9641. matter proceeds like ordinary knowledge. It perfects this knowledge,
  9642. increases its precision and its scope, but it works in the same
  9643. direction and puts the same mechanism into play. If, therefore, ordinary
  9644. knowledge, by reason of the cinematographical mechanism to which it is
  9645. subjected, forbears to follow becoming in so far as becoming is moving,
  9646. the science of matter renounces it equally. No doubt, it distinguishes
  9647. as great a number of moments as we wish in the interval of time it
  9648. considers. However small the intervals may be at which it stops, it
  9649. authorizes us to divide them again if necessary. In contrast with
  9650. ancient science, which stopped at certain so-called essential moments,
  9651. it is occupied indifferently with any moment whatever. But it always
  9652. considers moments, always virtual stopping-places, always, in short,
  9653. immobilities. Which amounts to saying that real time, regarded as a
  9654. flux, or, in other words, as the very mobility of being, escapes the
  9655. hold of scientific knowledge. We have already tried to establish this
  9656. point in a former work. We alluded to it again in the first chapter of
  9657. this book. But it is necessary to revert to it once more, in order to
  9658. clear up misunderstandings.
  9659. When positive science speaks of time, what it refers to is the movement
  9660. of a certain mobile T on its trajectory. This movement has been chosen
  9661. by it as representative of time, and it is, by definition, uniform. Let
  9662. us call T_{1}, T_{2}, T_{3}, ... etc., points which divide the trajectory
  9663. of the mobile into equal parts from its origin T_0. We shall say that 1, 2,
  9664. 3, ... units of time have flowed past, when the mobile is at the points
  9665. T_{1}, T_{2}, T_{3}, ... of the line it traverses. Accordingly, to consider
  9666. the state of the universe at the end of a certain time _t_, is to
  9667. examine where it will be when T is at the point T_t of its course. But
  9668. of the _flux_ itself of time, still less of its effect on consciousness,
  9669. there is here no question; for there enter into the calculation only the
  9670. points T_{1}, T_{2}, T_{3}, ... taken on the flux, never the flux itself.
  9671. We may narrow the time considered as much as we will, that is, break up at
  9672. will the interval between two consecutive divisions T_{n} and T_{n-|-1};
  9673. but it is always with points, and with points only, that we are dealing.
  9674. What we retain of the movement of the mobile T are positions taken on
  9675. its trajectory. What we retain of all the other points of the universe
  9676. are their positions on their respective trajectories. To each _virtual
  9677. stop_ of the moving body T at the points of division T_{1}, T_{2}, T_{3},
  9678. ... we make correspond a _virtual stop_ of all the other mobiles at the
  9679. points where they are passing. And when we say that a movement or any
  9680. other change has occupied a time _t_, we mean by it that we have noted a
  9681. number _t_ of correspondences of this kind. We have therefore counted
  9682. simultaneities; we have not concerned ourselves with the flux that goes
  9683. from one to another. The proof of this is that I can, at discretion,
  9684. vary the rapidity of the flux of the universe in regard to a
  9685. consciousness that is independent of it and that would perceive the
  9686. variation by the quite qualitative _feeling_ that it would have of it:
  9687. whatever the variation had been, since the movement of T would
  9688. participate in this variation, I should have nothing to change in my
  9689. equations nor in the numbers that figure in them.
  9690. Let us go further. Suppose that the rapidity of the flux becomes
  9691. infinite. Imagine, as we said in the first pages of this book, that the
  9692. trajectory of the mobile T is given at once, and that the whole history,
  9693. past, present and future, of the material universe is spread out
  9694. instantaneously in space. The same mathematical correspondences will
  9695. subsist between the moments of the history of the world unfolded like a
  9696. fan, so to speak, and the divisions T_{1}, T_{2}, T_{3}, ... of the line
  9697. which will be called, by definition, "the course of time." In the eyes of
  9698. science nothing will have changed. But if, time thus spreading itself
  9699. out in space and succession becoming juxtaposition, science has nothing
  9700. to change in what it tells us, we must conclude that, in what it tells
  9701. us, it takes account neither of _succession_ in what of it is specific
  9702. nor of _time_ in what there is in it that is fluent. It has no sign to
  9703. express what strikes our consciousness in succession and duration. It no
  9704. more applies to becoming, so far as that is moving, than the bridges
  9705. thrown here and there across the stream follow the water that flows
  9706. under their arches.
  9707. Yet succession exists; I am conscious of it; it is a fact. When a
  9708. physical process is going on before my eyes, my perception and my
  9709. inclination have nothing to do with accelerating or retarding it. What
  9710. is important to the physicist is the _number_ of units of duration the
  9711. process fills; he does not concern himself about the units themselves
  9712. and that is why the successive states of the world might be spread out
  9713. all at once in space without his having to change anything in his
  9714. science or to cease talking about time. But for us, conscious beings, it
  9715. is the units that matter, for we do not count extremities of intervals,
  9716. we feel and live the intervals themselves. Now, we are conscious of
  9717. these intervals as of _definite_ intervals. Let me come back again to
  9718. the sugar in my glass of water:[106] why must I wait for it to melt?
  9719. While the duration of the phenomenon is _relative_ for the physicist,
  9720. since it is reduced to a certain number of units of time and the units
  9721. themselves are indifferent, this duration is an _absolute_ for my
  9722. consciousness, for it coincides with a certain degree of impatience
  9723. which is rigorously determined. Whence comes this determination? What is
  9724. it that obliges me to wait, and to wait for a certain length of
  9725. psychical duration which is forced upon me, over which I have no power?
  9726. If succession, in so far as distinct from mere juxtaposition, has no
  9727. real efficacy, if time is not a kind of force, why does the universe
  9728. unfold its successive states with a velocity which, in regard to my
  9729. consciousness, is a veritable absolute? Why with this particular
  9730. velocity rather than any other? Why not with an infinite velocity? Why,
  9731. in other words, is not everything given at once, as on the film of the
  9732. cinematograph? The more I consider this point, the more it seems to me
  9733. that, if the future is bound to _succeed_ the present instead of being
  9734. given alongside of it, it is because the future is not altogether
  9735. determined at the present moment, and that if the time taken up by this
  9736. succession is something other than a number, if it has for the
  9737. consciousness that is installed in it absolute value and reality, it is
  9738. because there is unceasingly being created in it, not indeed in any such
  9739. artificially isolated system as a glass of sugared water, but in the
  9740. concrete whole of which every such system forms part, something
  9741. unforeseeable and new. This duration may not be the fact of matter
  9742. itself, but that of the life which reascends the course of matter; the
  9743. two movements are none the less mutually dependent upon each other. _The
  9744. duration of the universe must therefore be one with the latitude of
  9745. creation which can find place in it._
  9746. When a child plays at reconstructing a picture by putting together the
  9747. separate pieces in a puzzle game, the more he practices, the more and
  9748. more quickly he succeeds. The reconstruction was, moreover,
  9749. instantaneous, the child found it ready-made, when he opened the box on
  9750. leaving the shop. The operation, therefore, does not require a definite
  9751. time, and indeed, theoretically, it does not require any time. That is
  9752. because the result is given. It is because the picture is already
  9753. created, and because to obtain it requires only a work of recomposing
  9754. and rearranging--a work that can be supposed going faster and faster,
  9755. and even infinitely fast, up to the point of being instantaneous. But,
  9756. to the artist who creates a picture by drawing it from the depths of his
  9757. soul, time is no longer an accessory; it is not an interval that may be
  9758. lengthened or shortened without the content being altered. The duration
  9759. of his work is part and parcel of his work. To contract or to dilate it
  9760. would be to modify both the psychical evolution that fills it and the
  9761. invention which is its goal. The time taken up by the invention, is one
  9762. with the invention itself. It is the progress of a thought which is
  9763. changing in the degree and measure that it is taking form. It is a vital
  9764. process, something like the ripening of an idea.
  9765. The painter is before his canvas, the colors are on the palette, the
  9766. model is sitting--all this we see, and also we know the painter's
  9767. style: do we foresee what will appear on the canvas? We possess the
  9768. elements of the problem; we know in an abstract way, how it will be
  9769. solved, for the portrait will surely resemble the model and will surely
  9770. resemble also the artist; but the concrete solution brings with it that
  9771. unforeseeable nothing which is everything in a work of art. And it is
  9772. this nothing that takes time. Nought as matter, it creates itself as
  9773. form. The sprouting and flowering of this form are stretched out on an
  9774. unshrinkable duration, which is one with their essence. So of the works
  9775. of nature. Their novelty arises from an internal impetus which is
  9776. progress or succession, which confers on succession a peculiar virtue or
  9777. which owes to succession the whole of its virtue--which, at any rate,
  9778. makes succession, or _continuity of interpenetration_ in time,
  9779. irreducible to a mere instantaneous juxtaposition in space. This is why
  9780. the idea of reading in a present state of the material universe the
  9781. future of living forms, and of unfolding now their history yet to come,
  9782. involves a veritable absurdity. But this absurdity is difficult to bring
  9783. out, because our memory is accustomed to place alongside of each other,
  9784. in an ideal space, the terms it perceives in turn, because it always
  9785. represents _past_ succession in the form of juxtaposition. It is able to
  9786. do so, indeed, just because the past belongs to that which is already
  9787. invented, to the dead, and no longer to creation and to life. Then, as
  9788. the succession to come will end by being a succession past, we persuade
  9789. ourselves that the duration to come admits of the same treatment as past
  9790. duration, that it is, even now, unrollable, that the future is there,
  9791. rolled up, already painted on the canvas. An illusion, no doubt, but an
  9792. illusion that is natural, ineradicable, and that will last as long as
  9793. the human mind!
  9794. _Time is invention or it is nothing at all._ But of time-invention
  9795. physics can take no account, restricted as it is to the
  9796. cinematographical method. It is limited to counting simultaneities
  9797. between the events that make up this time and the positions of the
  9798. mobile T on its trajectory. It detaches these events from the whole,
  9799. which at every moment puts on a new form and which communicates to them
  9800. something of its novelty. It considers them in the abstract, such as
  9801. they would be outside of the living whole, that is to say, in a time
  9802. unrolled in space. It retains only the events or systems of events that
  9803. can be thus isolated without being made to undergo too profound a
  9804. deformation, because only these lend themselves to the application of
  9805. its method. Our physics dates from the day when it was known how to
  9806. isolate such systems. To sum up, _while modern physics is distinguished
  9807. from ancient physics by the fact that it considers any moment of time
  9808. whatever, it rests altogether on a substitution of time-length for
  9809. time-invention_.
  9810. It seems then that, parallel to this physics, a second kind of knowledge
  9811. ought to have grown up, which could have retained what physics allowed
  9812. to escape. On the flux itself of duration science neither would nor
  9813. could lay hold, bound as it was to the cinematographical method. This
  9814. second kind of knowledge would have set the cinematographical method
  9815. aside. It would have called upon the mind to renounce its most cherished
  9816. habits. It is within becoming that it would have transported us by an
  9817. effort of sympathy. We should no longer be asking where a moving body
  9818. will be, what shape a system will take, through what state a change will
  9819. pass at a given moment: the moments of time, which are only arrests of
  9820. our attention, would no longer exist; it is the flow of time, it is the
  9821. very flux of the real that we should be trying to follow. The first kind
  9822. of knowledge has the advantage of enabling us to foresee the future and
  9823. of making us in some measure masters of events; in return, it retains
  9824. of the moving reality only eventual immobilities, that is to say, views
  9825. taken of it by our mind. It symbolizes the real and transposes it into
  9826. the human rather than expresses it. The other knowledge, if it is
  9827. possible, is practically useless, it will not extend our empire over
  9828. nature, it will even go against certain natural aspirations of the
  9829. intellect; but, if it succeeds, it is reality itself that it will hold
  9830. in a firm and final embrace. Not only may we thus complete the intellect
  9831. and its knowledge of matter by accustoming it to install itself within
  9832. the moving, but by developing also another faculty, complementary to the
  9833. intellect, we may open a perspective on the other half of the real. For,
  9834. as soon as we are confronted with true duration, we see that it means
  9835. creation, and that if that which is being unmade endures, it can only be
  9836. because it is inseparably bound to what is making itself. Thus will
  9837. appear the necessity of a continual growth of the universe, I should say
  9838. of a _life_ of the real. And thus will be seen in a new light the life
  9839. which we find on the surface of our planet, a life directed the same way
  9840. as that of the universe, and inverse of materiality. To intellect, in
  9841. short, there will be added intuition.
  9842. The more we reflect on it, the more we shall find that this conception
  9843. of metaphysics is that which modern science suggests.
  9844. For the ancients, indeed, time is theoretically negligible, because the
  9845. duration of a thing only manifests the degradation of its essence: it is
  9846. with this motionless essence that science has to deal. Change being only
  9847. the effort of a form toward its own realization, the realization is all
  9848. that it concerns us to know. No doubt the realization is never complete:
  9849. it is this that ancient philosophy expresses by saying that we do not
  9850. perceive form without matter. But if we consider the changing object at
  9851. a certain essential moment, at its apogee, we may say that there it
  9852. just touches its intelligible form. This intelligible form, this ideal
  9853. and, so to speak, limiting form, our science seizes upon. And possessing
  9854. in this the gold-piece, it holds eminently the small money which we call
  9855. becoming or change. This change is less than being. The knowledge that
  9856. would take it for object, supposing such knowledge were possible, would
  9857. be less than science.
  9858. But, for a science that places all the moments of time in the same rank,
  9859. that admits no essential moment, no culminating point, no apogee, change
  9860. is no longer a diminution of essence, duration is not a dilution of
  9861. eternity. The flux of time is the reality itself, and the things which
  9862. we study are the things which flow. It is true that of this flowing
  9863. reality we are limited to taking instantaneous views. But, just because
  9864. of this, scientific knowledge must appeal to another knowledge to
  9865. complete it. While the ancient conception of scientific knowledge ended
  9866. in making time a degradation, and change the diminution of a form given
  9867. from all eternity--on the contrary, by following the new conception to
  9868. the end, we should come to see in time a progressive growth of the
  9869. absolute, and in the evolution of things a continual invention of forms
  9870. ever new.
  9871. It is true that it would be to break with the metaphysics of the
  9872. ancients. They saw only one way of knowing definitely. Their science
  9873. consisted in a scattered and fragmentary metaphysics, their metaphysics
  9874. in a concentrated and systematic science. Their science and metaphysics
  9875. were, at most, two species of one and the same genus. In our hypothesis,
  9876. on the contrary, science and metaphysics are two opposed although
  9877. complementary ways of knowing, the first retaining only moments, that is
  9878. to say, that which does not endure, the second bearing on duration
  9879. itself. Now, it was natural to hesitate between so novel a conception
  9880. of metaphysics and the traditional conception. The temptation must have
  9881. been strong to repeat with the new science what had been tried on the
  9882. old, to suppose our scientific knowledge of nature completed at once, to
  9883. unify it entirely, and to give to this unification, as the Greeks had
  9884. already done, the name of metaphysics. So, beside the new way that
  9885. philosophy might have prepared, the old remained open, that indeed which
  9886. physics trod. And, as physics retained of time only what could as well
  9887. be spread out all at once in space, the metaphysics that chose the same
  9888. direction had necessarily to proceed as if time created and annihilated
  9889. nothing, as if duration had no efficacy. Bound, like the physics of the
  9890. moderns and the metaphysics of the ancients, to the cinematographical
  9891. method, it ended with the conclusion, implicitly admitted at the start
  9892. and immanent in the method itself: _All is given._
  9893. That metaphysics hesitated at first between the two paths seems to us
  9894. unquestionable. The indecision is visible in Cartesianism. On the one
  9895. hand, Descartes affirms universal mechanism: from this point of view
  9896. movement would be relative,[107] and, as time has just as much reality
  9897. as movement, it would follow that past, present and future are given
  9898. from all eternity. But, on the other hand (and that is why the
  9899. philosopher has not gone to these extreme consequences), Descartes
  9900. believes in the free will of man. He superposes on the determinism of
  9901. physical phenomena the indeterminism of human actions, and,
  9902. consequently, on time-length a time in which there is invention,
  9903. creation, true succession. This duration he supports on a God who is
  9904. unceasingly renewing the creative act, and who, being thus tangent to
  9905. time and becoming, sustains them, communicates to them necessarily
  9906. something of his absolute reality. When he places himself at this
  9907. second point of view, Descartes speaks of movement, even spatial, as of
  9908. an absolute.[108]
  9909. He therefore entered both roads one after the other, having resolved to
  9910. follow neither of them to the end. The first would have led him to the
  9911. denial of free will in man and of real will in God. It was the
  9912. suppression of all efficient duration, the likening of the universe to a
  9913. thing given, which a superhuman intelligence would embrace at once in a
  9914. moment or in eternity. In following the second, on the contrary, he
  9915. would have been led to all the consequences which the intuition of true
  9916. duration implies. Creation would have appeared not simply as
  9917. _continued_, but also as _continuous_. The universe, regarded as a
  9918. whole, would really evolve. The future would no longer be determinable
  9919. by the present; at most we might say that, once realized, it can be
  9920. found again in its antecedents, as the sounds of a new language can be
  9921. expressed with the letters of an old alphabet if we agree to enlarge the
  9922. value of the letters and to attribute to them, retro-actively, sounds
  9923. which no combination of the old sounds could have produced beforehand.
  9924. Finally, the mechanistic explanation might have remained universal in
  9925. this, that it can indeed be extended to as many systems as we choose to
  9926. cut out in the continuity of the universe; but mechanism would then have
  9927. become a _method_ rather than a _doctrine_. It would have expressed the
  9928. fact that science must proceed after the cinematographical manner, that
  9929. the function of science is to scan the rhythm of the flow of things and
  9930. not to fit itself into that flow.--Such were the two opposite
  9931. conceptions of metaphysics which were offered to philosophy.
  9932. It chose the first. The reason of this choice is undoubtedly the mind's
  9933. tendency to follow the cinematographical method, a method so natural to
  9934. our intellect, and so well adjusted also to the requirements of our
  9935. science, that we must feel doubly sure of its speculative impotence to
  9936. renounce it in metaphysics. But ancient philosophy also influenced the
  9937. choice. Artists for ever admirable, the Greeks created a type of
  9938. supra-sensible truth, as of sensible beauty, whose attraction is hard to
  9939. resist. As soon as we incline to make metaphysics a systematization of
  9940. science, we glide in the direction of Plato and of Aristotle. And, once
  9941. in the zone of attraction in which the Greek philosophers moved, we are
  9942. drawn along in their orbit.
  9943. Such was the case with Leibniz, as also with Spinoza. We are not blind
  9944. to the treasures of originality their doctrines contain. Spinoza and
  9945. Leibniz have poured into them the whole content of their souls, rich
  9946. with the inventions of their genius and the acquisitions of modern
  9947. thought. And there are in each of them, especially in Spinoza, flashes
  9948. of intuition that break through the system. But if we leave out of the
  9949. two doctrines what breathes life into them, if we retain the skeleton
  9950. only, we have before us the very picture of Platonism and
  9951. Aristotelianism seen through Cartesian mechanism. They present to us a
  9952. systematization of the new physics, constructed on the model of the
  9953. ancient metaphysics.
  9954. What, indeed, could the unification of physics be? The inspiring idea of
  9955. that science was to isolate, within the universe, systems of material
  9956. points such that, the position of each of these points being known at a
  9957. given moment, we could then calculate it for any moment whatever. As,
  9958. moreover, the systems thus defined were the only ones on which the new
  9959. science had hold, and as it could not be known beforehand whether a
  9960. system satisfied or did not satisfy the desired condition, it was useful
  9961. to proceed always and everywhere _as if_ the condition was realized.
  9962. There was in this a methodological rule, a very natural rule--so
  9963. natural, indeed, that it was not even necessary to formulate it. For
  9964. simple common sense tells us that when we are possessed of an effective
  9965. instrument of research, and are ignorant of the limits of its
  9966. applicability, we should act as if its applicability were unlimited;
  9967. there will always be time to abate it. But the temptation must have been
  9968. great for the philosopher to hypostatize this hope, or rather this
  9969. impetus, of the new science, and to convert a general rule of method
  9970. into a fundamental law of things. So he transported himself at once to
  9971. the limit; he supposed physics to have become complete and to embrace
  9972. the whole of the sensible world. The universe became a system of points,
  9973. the position of which was rigorously determined at each instant by
  9974. relation to the preceding instant and theoretically calculable for any
  9975. moment whatever. The result, in short, was universal mechanism. But it
  9976. was not enough to formulate this mechanism; what was required was to
  9977. found it, to give the reason for it and prove its necessity. And the
  9978. essential affirmation of mechanism being that of a reciprocal
  9979. mathematical dependence of all the points of the universe, as also of
  9980. all the moments of the universe, the reason of mechanism had to be
  9981. discovered in the unity of a principle into which could be contracted
  9982. all that is juxtaposed in space and successive in time. Hence, the whole
  9983. of the real was supposed to be given at once. The reciprocal
  9984. determination of the juxtaposed appearances in space was explained by
  9985. the indivisibility of true being, and the inflexible determinism of
  9986. successive phenomena in time simply expressed that the whole of being is
  9987. given in the eternal.
  9988. The new philosophy was going, then, to be a recommencement, or rather a
  9989. transposition, of the old. The ancient philosophy had taken each of the
  9990. _concepts_ into which a becoming is concentrated or which mark its
  9991. apogee: it supposed them all known, and gathered them up into a single
  9992. concept, form of forms, idea of ideas, like the God of Aristotle. The
  9993. new philosophy was going to take each of the _laws_ which condition a
  9994. becoming in relation to others and which are as the permanent substratum
  9995. of phenomena: it would suppose them all known, and would gather them up
  9996. into a unity which also would express them eminently, but which, like
  9997. the God of Aristotle and for the same reasons, must remain immutably
  9998. shut up in itself.
  9999. True, this return to the ancient philosophy was not without great
  10000. difficulties. When a Plato, an Aristotle, or a Plotinus melt all the
  10001. concepts of their science into a single one, in so doing they embrace
  10002. the whole of the real, for concepts are supposed to represent the things
  10003. themselves, and to possess at least as much positive content. But a law,
  10004. in general, expresses only a relation, and physical laws in particular
  10005. express only _quantitative_ relations between concrete things. So that
  10006. if a modern philosopher works with the laws of the new science as the
  10007. Greek philosopher did with the concepts of the ancient science, if he
  10008. makes all the conclusions of a physics supposed omniscient converge on a
  10009. single point, he neglects what is concrete in the phenomena--the
  10010. qualities perceived, the perceptions themselves. His synthesis
  10011. comprises, it seems, only a fraction of reality. In fact, the first
  10012. result of the new science was to cut the real into two halves, quantity
  10013. and quality, the former being credited to the account of _bodies_ and
  10014. the latter to the account of _souls_. The ancients had raised no such
  10015. barriers either between quality and quantity or between soul and body.
  10016. For them, the mathematical concepts were concepts like the others,
  10017. related to the others and fitting quite naturally into the hierarchy of
  10018. the Ideas. Neither was the body then defined by geometrical extension,
  10019. nor the soul by consciousness. If the [Greek: psychê] of Aristotle, the
  10020. entelechy of a living body, is less spiritual than our "soul," it is
  10021. because his [Greek: oôma], already impregnated with the Idea, is less
  10022. corporeal than our "body." The scission was not yet irremediable between
  10023. the two terms. It has become so, and thence a metaphysic that aims at an
  10024. abstract unity must resign itself either to comprehend in its synthesis
  10025. only one half of the real, or to take advantage of the absolute
  10026. heterogeneity of the two halves in order to consider one as a
  10027. translation of the other. Different phrases will express different
  10028. things if they belong to the same language, that is to say, if there is
  10029. a certain relationship of sound between them. But if they belong to two
  10030. different languages, they might, just because of their radical diversity
  10031. of sound, express the same thing. So of quality and quantity, of soul
  10032. and body. It is for having cut all connection between the two terms that
  10033. philosophers have been led to establish between them a rigorous
  10034. parallelism, of which the ancients had not dreamed, to regard them as
  10035. translations and not as inversions of each other; in short, to posit a
  10036. fundamental identity as a substratum to their duality. The synthesis to
  10037. which they rose thus became capable of embracing everything. A divine
  10038. mechanism made the phenomena of thought to correspond to those of
  10039. extension, each to each, qualities to quantities, souls to bodies.
  10040. It is this parallelism that we find both in Leibniz and in Spinoza--in
  10041. different forms, it is true, because of the unequal importance which
  10042. they attach to extension. With Spinoza, the two terms Thought and
  10043. Extension are placed, in principle at least, in the same rank. They are,
  10044. therefore, two translations of one and the same original, or, as Spinoza
  10045. says, two attributes of one and the same substance, which we must call
  10046. God. And these two translations, as also an infinity of others into
  10047. languages which we know not, are called up and even forced into
  10048. existence by the original, just as the essence of the circle is
  10049. translated automatically, so to speak, both by a figure and by an
  10050. equation. For Leibniz, on the contrary, extension is indeed still a
  10051. translation, but it is thought that is the original, and thought might
  10052. dispense with translation, the translation being made only for us. In
  10053. positing God, we necessarily posit also all the possible views of God,
  10054. that is to say, the monads. But we can always imagine that a view has
  10055. been taken from a point of view, and it is natural for an imperfect mind
  10056. like ours to class views, qualitatively different, according to the
  10057. order and position of points of view, qualitatively identical, from
  10058. which the views might have been taken. In reality the points of view do
  10059. not exist, for there are only views, each given in an indivisible block
  10060. and representing in its own way the whole of reality, which is God. But
  10061. we need to express the plurality of the views, that are _unlike_ each
  10062. other, by the multiplicity of the points of view that are _exterior_ to
  10063. each other; and we also need to symbolize the more or less close
  10064. relationship between the views by the relative situation of the points
  10065. of view to one another, their nearness or their distance, that is to
  10066. say, by a magnitude. That is what Leibniz means when he says that space
  10067. is the order of coexistents, that the perception of extension is a
  10068. confused perception (that is to say, a perception relative to an
  10069. imperfect mind), and that nothing exists but monads, expressing thereby
  10070. that the real Whole has no parts, but is repeated to infinity, each time
  10071. integrally (though diversely) within itself, and that all these
  10072. repetitions are complementary to each other. In just the same way, the
  10073. visible relief of an object is equivalent to the whole set of
  10074. stereoscopic views taken of it from all points, so that, instead of
  10075. seeing in the relief a juxtaposition of solid parts, we might quite as
  10076. well look upon it as made of the _reciprocal complementarity_ of these
  10077. whole views, each given in block, each indivisible, each different from
  10078. all the others and yet representative of the same thing. The Whole, that
  10079. is to say, God, is this very relief for Leibniz, and the monads are
  10080. these complementary plane views; for that reason he defines God as "the
  10081. substance that has no point of view," or, again, as "the universal
  10082. harmony," that is to say, the reciprocal complementarity of monads. In
  10083. short, Leibniz differs from Spinoza in this, that he looks upon the
  10084. universal mechanism as an aspect which reality takes for us, whereas,
  10085. Spinoza makes of it an aspect which reality takes for itself.
  10086. It is true that, after having concentrated in God the whole of the real,
  10087. it became difficult for them to pass from God to things, from eternity
  10088. to time. The difficulty was even much greater for these philosophers
  10089. than an Aristotle or a Plotinus. The God of Aristotle, indeed, had been
  10090. obtained by the compression and reciprocal compenetration of the Ideas
  10091. that represent, in their finished state or in their culminating point,
  10092. the changing things of the world. He was, therefore, transcendent to the
  10093. world, and the duration of things was juxtaposed to His eternity, of
  10094. which it was only a weakening. But in the principle to which we are led
  10095. by the consideration of universal mechanism, and which must serve as its
  10096. substratum, it is not concepts or _things_, but laws or _relations_ that
  10097. are condensed. Now, a relation does not exist separately. A law connects
  10098. changing terms and is immanent in what it governs. The principle in
  10099. which all these relations are ultimately summed up, and which is the
  10100. basis of the unity of nature, cannot, therefore, be transcendent to
  10101. sensible reality; it is immanent in it, and we must suppose that it is
  10102. at once both in and out of time, gathered up in the unity of its
  10103. substance and yet condemned to wind it off in an endless chain. Rather
  10104. than formulate so appalling a contradiction, the philosophers were
  10105. necessarily led to sacrifice the weaker of the two terms, and to regard
  10106. the temporal aspect of things as a mere illusion. Leibniz says so in
  10107. explicit terms, for he makes of time, as of space, a confused
  10108. perception. While the multiplicity of his monads expresses only the
  10109. diversity of views taken of the whole, the history of an isolated monad
  10110. seems to be hardly anything else than the manifold views that it can
  10111. take of its own substance: so that time would consist in all the points
  10112. of view that each monad can assume towards itself, as space consists in
  10113. all the points of view that all monads can assume towards God. But the
  10114. thought of Spinoza is much less clear, and this philosopher seems to
  10115. have sought to establish, between eternity and that which has duration,
  10116. the same difference as Aristotle made between essence and accidents: a
  10117. most difficult undertaking, for the [Greek: ylê] of Aristotle was no
  10118. longer there to measure the distance and explain the passage from the
  10119. essential to the accidental, Descartes having eliminated it for ever.
  10120. However that may be, the deeper we go into the Spinozistic conception of
  10121. the "inadequate," as related to the "adequate," the more we feel
  10122. ourselves moving in the direction of Aristotelianism--just as the
  10123. Leibnizian monads, in proportion as they mark themselves out the more
  10124. clearly, tend to approximate to the Intelligibles of Plotinus.[109] The
  10125. natural trend of these two philosophies brings them back to the
  10126. conclusions of the ancient philosophy.
  10127. To sum up, the resemblances of this new metaphysic to that of the
  10128. ancients arise from the fact that both suppose ready-made--the former
  10129. above the sensible, the latter within the sensible--a science one and
  10130. complete, with which any reality that the sensible may contain is
  10131. believed to coincide. _For both, reality as well as truth are integrally
  10132. given in eternity._ Both are opposed to the idea of a reality that
  10133. creates itself gradually, that is, at bottom, to an absolute duration.
  10134. * * * * *
  10135. Now, it might easily be shown that the conclusions of this metaphysic,
  10136. springing from science, have rebounded upon science itself, as it were,
  10137. by ricochet. They penetrate the whole of our so-called empiricism.
  10138. Physics and chemistry study only inert matter; biology, when it treats
  10139. the living being physically and chemically, considers only the inert
  10140. side of the living: hence the mechanistic explanations, in spite of
  10141. their development, include only a small part of the real. To suppose _a
  10142. priori_ that the whole of the real is resolvable into elements of this
  10143. kind, or at least that mechanism can give a complete translation of what
  10144. happens in the world, is to pronounce for a certain metaphysic--the very
  10145. metaphysic of which Spinoza and Leibniz have laid down the principles
  10146. and drawn the consequences. Certainly, the psycho-physiologist who
  10147. affirms the exact equivalence of the cerebral and the psychical state,
  10148. who imagines the possibility, for some superhuman intellect, of reading
  10149. in the brain what is going on in consciousness, believes himself very
  10150. far from the metaphysicians of the seventeenth century, and very near to
  10151. experience. Yet experience pure and simple tells us nothing of the kind.
  10152. It shows us the interdependence of the mental and the physical, the
  10153. necessity of a certain cerebral substratum for the psychical
  10154. state--nothing more. From the fact that two things are mutually
  10155. dependent, it does not follow that they are equivalent. Because a
  10156. certain screw is necessary to a certain machine, because the machine
  10157. works when the screw is there and stops when the screw is taken away, we
  10158. do not say that the screw is the equivalent of the machine. For
  10159. correspondence to be equivalence, it would be necessary that to any part
  10160. of the machine a definite part of the screw should correspond--as in a
  10161. literal translation in which each chapter renders a chapter, each
  10162. sentence a sentence, each word a word. Now, the relation of the brain to
  10163. consciousness seems to be entirely different. Not only does the
  10164. hypothesis of an equivalence between the psychical state and the
  10165. cerebral state imply a downright absurdity, as we have tried to prove in
  10166. a former essay,[110] but the facts, examined without prejudice,
  10167. certainly seem to indicate that the relation of the psychical to the
  10168. physical is just that of the machine to the screw. To speak of an
  10169. equivalence between the two is simply to curtail, and make almost
  10170. unintelligible, the Spinozistic or Leibnizian metaphysic. It is to
  10171. accept this philosophy, such as it is, on the side of Extension, but to
  10172. mutilate it on the side of Thought. With Spinoza, with Leibniz, we
  10173. suppose the unifying synthesis of the phenomena of matter achieved, and
  10174. everything in matter explained mechanically. But, for the conscious
  10175. facts, we no longer push the synthesis to the end. We stop half-way. We
  10176. suppose consciousness to be coextensive with a certain part of nature
  10177. and not with all of it. We are thus led, sometimes to an
  10178. "epiphenomenalism" that associates consciousness with certain particular
  10179. vibrations and puts it here and there in the world in a sporadic state,
  10180. and sometimes to a "monism" that scatters consciousness into as many
  10181. tiny grains as there are atoms; but, in either case, it is to an
  10182. incomplete Spinozism or to an incomplete Leibnizianism that we come
  10183. back. Between this conception of nature and Cartesianism we find,
  10184. moreover, intermediate historical stages. The medical philosophers of
  10185. the eighteenth century, with their cramped Cartesianism, have had a
  10186. great part in the genesis of the "epiphenomenalism" and "monism" of the
  10187. present day.
  10188. * * * * *
  10189. These doctrines are thus found to fall short of the Kantian criticism.
  10190. Certainly, the philosophy of Kant is also imbued with the belief in a
  10191. science single and complete, embracing the whole of the real. Indeed,
  10192. looked at from one aspect, it is only a continuation of the metaphysics
  10193. of the moderns and a transposition of the ancient metaphysics. Spinoza
  10194. and Leibniz had, following Aristotle, hypostatized in God the unity of
  10195. knowledge. The Kantian criticism, on one side at least, consists in
  10196. asking whether the whole of this hypothesis is necessary to modern
  10197. science as it was to ancient science, or if part of the hypothesis is
  10198. not sufficient. For the ancients, science applied to _concepts_, that is
  10199. to say, to kinds of _things_. In compressing all concepts into one, they
  10200. therefore necessarily arrived at a _being_, which we may call Thought,
  10201. but which was rather thought-object than thought-subject. When Aristotle
  10202. defined God the [Greek: noêseôs noêsis], it is probably on [Greek:
  10203. noêseôs], and not on [Greek: noêsis] that he put the emphasis. God was
  10204. the synthesis of all concepts, the idea of ideas. But modern science
  10205. turns on laws, that is, on relations. Now, a relation is a bond
  10206. established by a mind between two or more terms. A relation is nothing
  10207. outside of the intellect that relates. The universe, therefore, can only
  10208. be a system of laws if phenomena have passed beforehand through the
  10209. filter of an intellect. Of course, this intellect might be that of a
  10210. being infinitely superior to man, who would found the materiality of
  10211. things at the same time that he bound them together: such was the
  10212. hypothesis of Leibniz and of Spinoza. But it is not necessary to go so
  10213. far, and, for the effect we have here to obtain, the human intellect is
  10214. enough: such is precisely the Kantian solution. Between the dogmatism of
  10215. a Spinoza or a Leibniz and the criticism of Kant there is just the same
  10216. distance as between "it may be maintained that--" and "it suffices
  10217. that--." Kant stops this dogmatism on the incline that was making it
  10218. slip too far toward the Greek metaphysics; he reduces to the strict
  10219. minimum the hypothesis which is necessary in order to suppose the
  10220. physics of Galileo indefinitely extensible. True, when he speaks of the
  10221. human intellect, he means neither yours nor mine: the unity of nature
  10222. comes indeed from the human understanding that unifies, but the unifying
  10223. function that operates here is impersonal. It imparts itself to our
  10224. individual consciousnesses, but it transcends them. It is much less than
  10225. a substantial God; it is, however, a little more than the isolated work
  10226. of a man or even than the collective work of humanity. It does not
  10227. exactly lie within man; rather, man lies within it, as in an atmosphere
  10228. of intellectuality which his consciousness breathes. It is, if we will,
  10229. a _formal_ God, something that in Kant is not yet divine, but which
  10230. tends to become so. It became so, indeed, with Fichte. With Kant,
  10231. however, its principal rôle was to give to the whole of our science a
  10232. relative and _human_ character, although of a humanity already somewhat
  10233. deified. From this point of view, the criticism of Kant consisted
  10234. chiefly in limiting the dogmatism of his predecessors, accepting their
  10235. conception of science and reducing to a minimum the metaphysic it
  10236. implied.
  10237. But it is otherwise with the Kantian distinction between the matter of
  10238. knowledge and its form. By regarding intelligence as pre-eminently a
  10239. faculty of establishing relations, Kant attributed an extra-intellectual
  10240. origin to the terms between which the relations are established. He
  10241. affirmed, against his immediate predecessors, that knowledge is not
  10242. entirely resolvable into terms of intelligence. He brought back into
  10243. philosophy--while modifying it and carrying it on to another plane--that
  10244. essential element of the philosophy of Descartes which had been abandoned
  10245. by the Cartesians.
  10246. Thereby he prepared the way for a new philosophy, which might have
  10247. established itself in the extra-intellectual matter of knowledge by a
  10248. higher effort of intuition. Coinciding with this matter, adopting the
  10249. same rhythm and the same movement, might not consciousness, by two
  10250. efforts of opposite direction, raising itself and lowering itself by
  10251. turns, become able to grasp from within, and no longer perceive only
  10252. from without, the two forms of reality, body and mind? Would not this
  10253. twofold effort make us, as far as that is possible, re-live the
  10254. absolute? Moreover, as, in the course of this operation, we should see
  10255. intellect spring up of itself, cut itself out in the whole of mind,
  10256. intellectual knowledge would then appear as it is, limited, but not
  10257. relative.
  10258. Such was the direction that Kantianism might have pointed out to a
  10259. revivified Cartesianism. But in this direction Kant himself did not go.
  10260. He _would_ not, because, while assigning to knowledge an
  10261. extra-intellectual matter, he believed this matter to be either
  10262. coextensive with intellect or less extensive than intellect. Therefore
  10263. he could not dream of cutting out intellect in it, nor, consequently, of
  10264. tracing the genesis of the understanding and its categories. The molds
  10265. of the understanding and the understanding itself had to be accepted as
  10266. they are, already made. Between the matter presented to our intellect
  10267. and this intellect itself there was no relationship. The agreement
  10268. between the two was due to the fact that intellect imposed its form on
  10269. matter. So that not only was it necessary to posit the intellectual form
  10270. of knowledge as a kind of absolute and give up the quest of its genesis,
  10271. but the very matter of this knowledge seemed too ground down by the
  10272. intellect for us to be able to hope to get it back in its original
  10273. purity. It was not the "thing-in-itself," it was only the refraction of
  10274. it through our atmosphere.
  10275. If now we inquire why Kant did not believe that the matter of our
  10276. knowledge extends beyond its form, this is what we find. The criticism
  10277. of our knowledge of nature that was instituted by Kant consisted in
  10278. ascertaining what our mind must be and what Nature must be _if_ the
  10279. claims of our science are justified; but of these claims themselves Kant
  10280. has not made the criticism. I mean that he took for granted the idea of
  10281. a science that is one, capable of binding with the same force all the
  10282. parts of what is given, and of coördinating them into a system
  10283. presenting on all sides an equal solidity. He did not consider, in his
  10284. _Critique of Pure Reason_, that science became less and less objective,
  10285. more and more symbolical, to the extent that it went from the physical
  10286. to the vital, from the vital to the psychical. Experience does not move,
  10287. to his view, in two different and perhaps opposite ways, the one
  10288. conformable to the direction of the intellect, the other contrary to it.
  10289. There is, for him, only _one_ experience, and the intellect covers its
  10290. whole ground. This is what Kant expresses by saying that all our
  10291. intuitions are sensuous, or, in other words, infra-intellectual. And
  10292. this would have to be admitted, indeed, if our science presented in all
  10293. its parts an equal objectivity. But suppose, on the contrary, that
  10294. science is less and less objective, more and more symbolical, as it goes
  10295. from the physical to the psychical, passing through the vital: then, as
  10296. it is indeed necessary to perceive a thing somehow in order to symbolize
  10297. it, there would be an intuition of the psychical, and more generally of
  10298. the vital, which the intellect would transpose and translate, no doubt,
  10299. but which would none the less transcend the intellect. There would be,
  10300. in other words, a supra-intellectual intuition. If this intuition exist,
  10301. a taking possession of the spirit by itself is possible, and no longer
  10302. only a knowledge that is external and phenomenal. What is more, if we
  10303. have an intuition of this kind (I mean an ultra-intellectual intuition)
  10304. then sensuous intuition is likely to be in continuity with it through
  10305. certain intermediaries, as the infra-red is continuous with the
  10306. ultra-violet. Sensuous intuition itself, therefore, is promoted. It will
  10307. no longer attain only the phantom of an unattainable thing-in-itself. It
  10308. is (provided we bring to it certain indispensable corrections) into the
  10309. absolute itself that it will introduce us. So long as it was regarded as
  10310. the only material of our science, it reflected back on all science
  10311. something of the relativity which strikes a scientific knowledge of
  10312. spirit; and thus the perception of bodies, which is the beginning of the
  10313. science of bodies, seemed itself to be relative. Relative, therefore,
  10314. seemed to be sensuous intuition. But this is not the case if
  10315. distinctions are made between the different sciences, and if the
  10316. scientific knowledge of the spiritual (and also, consequently, of the
  10317. vital) be regarded as the more or less artificial extension of a certain
  10318. manner of knowing which, applied to bodies, is not at all symbolical.
  10319. Let us go further: if there are thus two intuitions of different order
  10320. (the second being obtained by a reversal of the direction of the first),
  10321. and if it is toward the second that the intellect naturally inclines,
  10322. there is no essential difference between the intellect and this
  10323. intuition itself. The barriers between the matter of sensible knowledge
  10324. and its form are lowered, as also between the "pure forms" of
  10325. sensibility and the categories of the understanding. The matter and form
  10326. of intellectual knowledge (restricted to its own object) are seen to be
  10327. engendering each other by a reciprocal adaptation, intellect modeling
  10328. itself on corporeity, and corporeity on intellect.
  10329. But this duality of intuition Kant neither would nor could admit. It
  10330. would have been necessary, in order to admit it, to regard duration as
  10331. the very stuff of reality, and consequently to distinguish between the
  10332. substantial duration of things and time spread out in space. It would
  10333. have been necessary to regard space itself, and the geometry which is
  10334. immanent in space, as an ideal limit in the direction of which material
  10335. things develop, but which they do not actually attain. Nothing could be
  10336. more contrary to the letter, and perhaps also to the spirit, of the
  10337. _Critique of Pure Reason_. No doubt, knowledge is presented to us in it
  10338. as an ever-open roll, experience as a push of facts that is for ever
  10339. going on. But, according to Kant, these facts are spread out on one
  10340. plane as fast as they arise; they are external to each other and
  10341. external to the mind. Of a knowledge from within, that could grasp them
  10342. in their springing forth instead of taking them already sprung, that
  10343. would dig beneath space and spatialized time, there is never any
  10344. question. Yet it is indeed beneath this plane that our consciousness
  10345. places us; there flows true duration.
  10346. In this respect, also, Kant is very near his predecessors. Between the
  10347. non-temporal, and the time that is spread out in distinct moments, he
  10348. admits no mean. And as there is indeed no intuition that carries us into
  10349. the non-temporal, all intuition is thus found to be sensuous, by
  10350. definition. But between physical existence, which is spread out in
  10351. space, and non-temporal existence, which can only be a conceptual and
  10352. logical existence like that of which metaphysical dogmatism speaks, is
  10353. there not room for consciousness and for life? There is, unquestionably.
  10354. We perceive it when we place ourselves in duration in order to go from
  10355. that duration to moments, instead of starting from moments in order to
  10356. bind them again and to construct duration.
  10357. Yet it was to a non-temporal intuition that the immediate successors of
  10358. Kant turned, in order to escape from the Kantian relativism. Certainly,
  10359. the ideas of becoming, of progress, of evolution, seem to occupy a large
  10360. place in their philosophy. But does duration really play a part in it?
  10361. Real duration is that in which each form flows out of previous forms,
  10362. while adding to them something new, and is explained by them as much as
  10363. it explains them; but to deduce this form directly from one complete
  10364. Being which it is supposed to manifest, is to return to Spinozism. It
  10365. is, like Leibniz and Spinoza, to deny to duration all efficient action.
  10366. The post-Kantian philosophy, severe as it may have been on the
  10367. mechanistic theories, accepts from mechanism the idea of a science that
  10368. is one and the same for all kinds of reality. And it is nearer to
  10369. mechanism than it imagines; for though, in the consideration of matter,
  10370. of life and of thought, it replaces the successive degrees of
  10371. complexity, that mechanism supposed by degrees of the realization of an
  10372. Idea or by degrees of the objectification of a Will, it still speaks of
  10373. degrees, and these degrees are those of a scale which Being traverses in
  10374. a single direction. In short, it makes out the same articulations in
  10375. nature that mechanism does. Of mechanism it retains the whole design; it
  10376. merely gives it a different coloring. But it is the design itself, or at
  10377. least one half of the design, that needs to be re-made.
  10378. If we are to do that, we must give up the method of _construction_,
  10379. which was that of Kant's successors. We must appeal to experience--an
  10380. experience purified, or, in other words, released, where necessary, from
  10381. the molds that our intellect has formed in the degree and proportion of
  10382. the progress of our action on things. An experience of this kind is not
  10383. a non-temporal experience. It only seeks, beyond the spatialized time in
  10384. which we believe we see continual rearrangements between the parts, that
  10385. concrete duration in which a radical recasting of the whole is always
  10386. going on. It follows the real in all its sinuosities. It does not lead
  10387. us, like the method of construction, to higher and higher
  10388. generalities--piled-up stories of a magnificent building. But then it
  10389. leaves no play between the explanations it suggests and the objects it
  10390. has to explain. It is the detail of the real, and no longer only the
  10391. whole in a lump, that it claims to illumine.
  10392. * * * * *
  10393. That the thought of the nineteenth century called for a philosophy of
  10394. this kind, rescued from the arbitrary, capable of coming down to the
  10395. detail of particular facts, is unquestionable. Unquestionably, also, it
  10396. felt that this philosophy ought to establish itself in what we call
  10397. concrete duration. The advent of the moral sciences, the progress of
  10398. psychology, the growing importance of embryology among the biological
  10399. sciences--all this was bound to suggest the idea of a reality which
  10400. _endures_ inwardly, which is duration itself. So, when a philosopher
  10401. arose who announced a doctrine of evolution, in which the progress of
  10402. matter toward perceptibility would be traced together with the advance
  10403. of the mind toward rationality, in which the complication of
  10404. correspondences between the external and the internal would be followed
  10405. step by step, in which change would become the very substance of
  10406. things--to him all eyes were turned. The powerful attraction that
  10407. Spencerian evolutionism has exercised on contemporary thought is due to
  10408. that very cause. However far Spencer may seem to be from Kant, however
  10409. ignorant, indeed, he may have been of Kantianism, he felt, nevertheless,
  10410. at his first contact with the biological sciences, the direction in
  10411. which philosophy could continue to advance without laying itself open to
  10412. the Kantian criticism.
  10413. But he had no sooner started to follow the path than he turned off
  10414. short. He had promised to retrace a genesis, and, lo! he was doing
  10415. something entirely different. His doctrine bore indeed the name of
  10416. evolutionism; it claimed to remount and redescend the course of the
  10417. universal becoming; but, in fact, it dealt neither with becoming nor
  10418. with evolution.
  10419. We need not enter here into a profound examination of this philosophy.
  10420. Let us say merely that _the usual device of the Spencerian method
  10421. consists in reconstructing evolution with fragments of the evolved_. If
  10422. I paste a picture on a card and then cut up the card into bits, I can
  10423. reproduce the picture by rightly grouping again the small pieces. And a
  10424. child who working thus with the pieces of a puzzle-picture, and putting
  10425. together unformed fragments of the picture finally obtains a pretty
  10426. colored design, no doubt imagines that he has _produced_ design and
  10427. color. Yet the act of drawing and painting has nothing to do with that
  10428. of putting together the fragments of a picture already drawn and already
  10429. painted. So, by combining together the most simple results of evolution,
  10430. you may imitate well or ill the most complex effects; but of neither the
  10431. simple nor the complex will you have retraced the genesis, and the
  10432. addition of evolved to evolved will bear no resemblance whatever to the
  10433. movement of evolution.
  10434. Such, however, is Spencer's illusion. He takes reality in its present
  10435. form; he breaks it to pieces, he scatters it in fragments which he
  10436. throws to the winds; then he "integrates" these fragments and
  10437. "dissipates their movement." Having _imitated_ the Whole by a work of
  10438. mosaic, he imagines he has retraced the design of it, and made the
  10439. genesis.
  10440. Is it matter that is in question? The diffused elements which he
  10441. integrates into visible and tangible bodies have all the air of being
  10442. the very particles of the simple bodies, which he first supposes
  10443. disseminated throughout space. They are, at any rate, "material points,"
  10444. and consequently unvarying points, veritable little solids: as if
  10445. solidity, being what is nearest and handiest to us, could be found at
  10446. the very origin of materiality! The more physics progresses, the more it
  10447. shows the impossibility of representing the properties of ether or of
  10448. electricity--the probable base of all bodies--on the model of the
  10449. properties of the matter which we perceive. But philosophy goes back
  10450. further even than the ether, a mere schematic figure of the relations
  10451. between phenomena apprehended by our senses. It knows indeed that what
  10452. is visible and tangible in things represents our possible action on
  10453. them. It is not by dividing the evolved that we shall reach the
  10454. principle of that which evolves. It is not by recomposing the evolved
  10455. with itself that we shall reproduce the evolution of which it is the
  10456. term.
  10457. Is it the question of mind? By compounding the reflex with the reflex,
  10458. Spencer thinks he generates instinct and rational volition one after the
  10459. other. He fails to see that the specialized reflex, being a terminal
  10460. point of evolution just as much as perfect will, cannot be supposed at
  10461. the start. That the first of the two terms should have reached its final
  10462. form before the other is probable enough; but both the one and the other
  10463. are _deposits_ of the evolution movement, and the evolution movement
  10464. itself can no more be expressed as a function solely of the first than
  10465. solely of the second. We must begin by mixing the reflex and the
  10466. voluntary. We must then go in quest of the fluid reality which has been
  10467. precipitated in this twofold form, and which probably shares in both
  10468. without being either. At the lowest degree of the animal scale, in
  10469. living beings that are but an undifferentiated protoplasmic mass, the
  10470. reaction to stimulus does not yet call into play one definite mechanism,
  10471. as in the reflex; it has not yet choice among several definite
  10472. mechanisms, as in the voluntary act; it is, then, neither voluntary nor
  10473. reflex, though it heralds both. We experience in ourselves something of
  10474. this true original activity when we perform semi-voluntary and
  10475. semi-automatic movements to escape a pressing danger. And yet this is
  10476. but a very imperfect imitation of the primitive character, for we are
  10477. concerned here with a mixture of two activities already formed, already
  10478. localized in a brain and in a spinal cord, whereas the original activity
  10479. was a simple thing, which became diversified through the very
  10480. construction of mechanisms like those of the spinal cord and brain. But
  10481. to all this Spencer shuts his eyes, because it is of the essence of his
  10482. method to recompose the consolidated with the consolidated, instead of
  10483. going back to the gradual process of consolidation, which is evolution
  10484. itself.
  10485. Is it, finally, the question of the correspondence between mind and
  10486. matter? Spencer is right in defining the intellect by this
  10487. correspondence. He is right in regarding it as the end of an evolution.
  10488. But when he comes to retrace this evolution, again he integrates the
  10489. evolved with the evolved--failing to see that he is thus taking useless
  10490. trouble, and that in positing the slightest fragment of the actually
  10491. evolved he posits the whole--so that it is vain for him, then, to
  10492. pretend to make the genesis of it.
  10493. For, according to him, the phenomena that succeed each other in nature
  10494. project into the human mind images which represent them. To the
  10495. relations between phenomena, therefore, correspond symmetrically
  10496. relations between the ideas. And the most general laws of nature, in
  10497. which the relations between phenomena are condensed, are thus found to
  10498. have engendered the directing principles of thought, into which the
  10499. relations between ideas have been integrated. Nature, therefore, is
  10500. reflected in mind. The intimate structure of our thought corresponds,
  10501. piece by piece, to the very skeleton of things--I admit it willingly;
  10502. but, in order that the human mind may be able to represent relations
  10503. between phenomena, there must first be phenomena, that is to say,
  10504. distinct facts, cut out in the continuity of becoming. And once we posit
  10505. this particular mode of cutting up such as we perceive it to-day, we
  10506. posit also the intellect such as it is to-day, for it is by relation to
  10507. it, and to it alone, that reality is cut up in this manner. Is it
  10508. probable that mammals and insects notice the same aspects of nature,
  10509. trace in it the same divisions, articulate the whole in the same way?
  10510. And yet the insect, so far as intelligent, has already something of our
  10511. intellect. Each being cuts up the material world according to the lines
  10512. that its action must follow: it is these lines of _possible action_
  10513. that, by intercrossing, mark out the net of experience of which each
  10514. mesh is a fact. No doubt, a town is composed exclusively of houses, and
  10515. the streets of the town are only the intervals between the houses: so,
  10516. we may say that nature contains only facts, and that, the facts once
  10517. posited, the relations are simply the lines running between the facts.
  10518. But, in a town, it is the gradual portioning of the ground into lots
  10519. that has determined at once the place of the houses, their general
  10520. shape, and the direction of the streets: to this portioning we must go
  10521. back if we wish to understand the particular mode of subdivision that
  10522. causes each house to be where it is, each street to run as it does.
  10523. Now, the cardinal error of Spencer is to take experience already
  10524. allotted as given, whereas the true problem is to know how the allotment
  10525. was worked. I agree that the laws of thought are only the integration of
  10526. relations between facts. But, when I posit the facts with the shape they
  10527. have for me to-day, I suppose my faculties of perception and
  10528. intellection such as they are in me to-day; for it is they that portion
  10529. the real into lots, they that cut the facts out in the whole of reality.
  10530. Therefore, instead of saying that the relations between facts have
  10531. generated the laws of thought, I can as well claim that it is the form
  10532. of thought that has determined the shape of the facts perceived, and
  10533. consequently their relations among themselves: the two ways of
  10534. expressing oneself are equivalent; they say at bottom the same thing.
  10535. With the second, it is true, we give up speaking of evolution. But, with
  10536. the first, we only speak of it, we do not think of it any the more. For
  10537. a true evolutionism would propose to discover by what _modus vivendi_,
  10538. gradually obtained, the intellect has adopted its plan of structure, and
  10539. matter its mode of subdivision. This structure and this subdivision work
  10540. into each other; they are mutually complementary; they must have
  10541. progressed one with the other. And, whether we posit the present
  10542. structure of mind or the present subdivision of matter, in either case
  10543. we remain in the evolved: we are told nothing of what evolves, nothing
  10544. of evolution.
  10545. And yet it is this evolution that we must discover. Already, in the
  10546. field of physics itself, the scientists who are pushing the study of
  10547. their science furthest incline to believe that we cannot reason about
  10548. the parts as we reason about the whole; that the same principles are not
  10549. applicable to the origin and to the end of a progress; that neither
  10550. creation nor annihilation, for instance, is inadmissible when we are
  10551. concerned with the constituent corpuscles of the atom. Thereby they tend
  10552. to place themselves in the concrete duration, in which alone there is
  10553. true generation and not only a composition of parts. It is true that the
  10554. creation and annihilation of which they speak concern the movement or
  10555. the energy, and not the imponderable medium through which the energy and
  10556. the movement are supposed to circulate. But what can remain of matter
  10557. when you take away everything that determines it, that is to say, just
  10558. energy and movement themselves? The philosopher must go further than the
  10559. scientist. Making a clean sweep of everything that is only an
  10560. imaginative symbol, he will see the material world melt back into a
  10561. simple flux, a continuity of flowing, a becoming. And he will thus be
  10562. prepared to discover real duration there where it is still more useful
  10563. to find it, in the realm of life and of consciousness. For, so far as
  10564. inert matter is concerned, we may neglect the flowing without committing
  10565. a serious error: matter, we have said, is weighted with geometry; and
  10566. matter, the reality which _descends_, endures only by its connection
  10567. with that which _ascends_. But life and consciousness are this very
  10568. ascension. When once we have grasped them in their essence by adopting
  10569. their movement, we understand how the rest of reality is derived from
  10570. them. Evolution appears and, within this evolution, the progressive
  10571. determination of materiality and intellectuality by the gradual
  10572. consolidation of the one and of the other. But, then, it is within the
  10573. evolutionary movement that we place ourselves, in order to follow it to
  10574. its present results, instead of recomposing these results artificially
  10575. with fragments of themselves. Such seems to us to be the true function
  10576. of philosophy. So understood, philosophy is not only the turning of the
  10577. mind homeward, the coincidence of human consciousness with the living
  10578. principle whence it emanates, a contact with the creative effort: it is
  10579. the study of becoming in general, it is true evolutionism and
  10580. consequently the true continuation of science--provided that we
  10581. understand by this word a set of truths either experienced or
  10582. demonstrated, and not a certain new scholasticism that has grown up
  10583. during the latter half of the nineteenth century around the physics of
  10584. Galileo, as the old scholasticism grew up around Aristotle.
  10585. FOOTNOTES:
  10586. [Footnote 96: The part of this chapter which treats of the history of
  10587. systems, particularly of the Greek philosophy, is only the very succinct
  10588. résumé of views that we developed at length, from 1900 to 1904, in our
  10589. lectures at the Collège de France, especially in a course on the
  10590. _History of the Idea of Time_ (1902-1903). We then compared the
  10591. mechanism of conceptual thought to that of the cinematograph. We believe
  10592. the comparison will be useful here.]
  10593. [Footnote 97: The analysis of the idea of the nought which we give here
  10594. (pp. 275-298) has appeared before in the _Revue philosophique_ (November
  10595. 1906).]
  10596. [Footnote 98: Kant, _Critique of Pure Reason_, 2nd edition, p. 737:
  10597. "From the point of view of our knowledge in general ... the peculiar
  10598. function of negative propositions is simply to prevent error." Cf.
  10599. Sigwart, _Logik_, 2nd edition, vol. i. pp. 150 ff.]
  10600. [Footnote 99: That is, we do not consider the sophism of Zeno refuted by
  10601. the fact that the geometrical progression _a_(1 + 1/_n_ + 1/_n_2 +
  10602. 1/_n_3 +,... etc.)--in which _a_ designates the initial distance between
  10603. Achilles and the tortoise, and _n_ the relation of their respective
  10604. velocities--has a finite sum if _n_ is greater than 1. On this point we
  10605. may refer to the arguments of F. Evellin, which we regard as conclusive
  10606. (see Evellin, _Infini et quantité_, Paris, 1880, pp. 63-97; cf. _Revue
  10607. philosophique_, vol. xi., 1881, pp. 564-568). The truth is that
  10608. mathematics, as we have tried to show in a former work, deals and can
  10609. deal only with lengths. It has therefore had to seek devices, first, to
  10610. transfer to the movement, which is not a length, the divisibility of the
  10611. line passed over, and then to reconcile with experience the idea
  10612. (contrary to experience and full of absurdities) of a movement that is a
  10613. length, that is, of a movement _placed upon_ its trajectory and
  10614. arbitrarily decomposable like it.]
  10615. [Footnote 100: Plato, _Timaeus_, 37 D.]
  10616. [Footnote 101: We have tried to bring out what is true and what is false
  10617. in this idea, so far as spatiality is concerned (see Chapter III.). It
  10618. seems to us radically false as regards _duration_.]
  10619. [Footnote 102: Aristotle, _De anima_, 430 a 14 [Greek: kai hestin ho men
  10620. toioutos nous tô pynta ginesthai, ho de tô panta poiein, ôs hexis tis,
  10621. oion to phôs. tropon gar tina ka to phôs poiei ta dynamei onta chrômata
  10622. energeia chrômata].]
  10623. [Footnote 103: _De caelo_, ii. 287 a 12 [Greek: tês eschatês periphoras
  10624. oute kenon estin exôthen oute topos.] _Phys._ iv. 212 a 34 [Greek: to de
  10625. pan esti men hôs kinêsetai hesti d' hôs ou. hôs men gar holon, hama ton
  10626. topon hou metaballei. kyklô de kinêsetai, tôn moriôn gar outos ho
  10627. topos].]
  10628. [Footnote 104: _De caelo_, i. 279 a 12 [Greek: oude chronos hestin hexô
  10629. tou ouranou]. _Phys._ viii. 251 b 27 [Greek: ho chronos pathos ti
  10630. kinêseôs].]
  10631. [Footnote 105: Especially have we left almost entirely on one side those
  10632. admirable but somewhat fugitive intuitions that Plotinus was later to
  10633. seize, to study and to fix.]
  10634. [Footnote 106: See page 10.]
  10635. [Footnote 107: Descartes, _Principes_, ii. § 29.]
  10636. [Footnote 108: Descartes, _Principes_, ii. §§ 36 ff.]
  10637. [Footnote 109: In a course of lectures on Plotinus, given at the Collège
  10638. de France in 1897-1898, we tried to bring out these resemblances. They
  10639. are numerous and impressive. The analogy is continued even in the
  10640. formulae employed on each side.]
  10641. [Footnote 110: "Le Paralogisme psycho-physiologique" (_Revue de
  10642. métaphysique et de morale_, Nov. 1904, pp. 895-908). Cf. _Matière et
  10643. mémoire_, Paris, 1896, chap. i.]
  10644. INDEX
  10645. (Compiled by the Translator)
  10646. Abolition of everything a self-contradiction, 280, 283, 296, 298
  10647. idea of, 279, 282, 283, 295, 296.
  10648. _See_ Nought
  10649. Absence of order, 231, 234, 274.
  10650. _See_ Disorder
  10651. Absolute and freedom, 277
  10652. reality, 99, 228-9, 269, 358, 361
  10653. reality of the person, 269
  10654. time and the, 239, 240, 298, 340, 344
  10655. Absoluteness of duration, 206
  10656. of understanding, xi, 47, 152, 190, 197, 199
  10657. Abstract becoming, 304-7
  10658. multiplicity, 257-9
  10659. time, 9, 17, 20-2, 37, 39, 46, 51, 163, 318-9, 336, 352-3
  10660. Accident and essence in Aristotle's philosophy, 353
  10661. in evolution, 86-7, 104, 114-5, 127, 169, 170, 252, 254-5, 266, 267,
  10662. 326-7
  10663. Accidental variations, 55, 63, 68, 69, 74, 85-6, 168
  10664. Accumulation of energy, function of vegetable organisms, 253, 255
  10665. Achilles and tortoise, in Zeno, 311, 312-3
  10666. Acquired characters, inheritance of, 76-9, 83-4, 87, 169, 170, 173, 231
  10667. Act, consciousness as inadequacy of, to representation, 144
  10668. form (or essence), quality, three classes of representation, 302-3
  10669. Action, creativeness of free, 192, 247
  10670. and concepts, 160, 297
  10671. and consciousness, xiii, 5, 143-4, 145, 179-80, 207, 262
  10672. discontinuity of, 154, 307
  10673. freedom of, in animals, 130
  10674. as function of nervous system, 262-3
  10675. indivisibility of, 94, 95, 308-9
  10676. and inert matter, 96, 136, 141-2, 156, 187, 198, 226, 366
  10677. instinct and, 136, 141
  10678. instrument of, consciousness, 180
  10679. instrument of, life, 162
  10680. instrument of matter, 161, 198-9
  10681. as instrument of consciousness, 180
  10682. and intellect. _See_ Intellect and action
  10683. intensity of consciousness varies with ratio of possible, to real, 145
  10684. meaning of, 301-3
  10685. moves from want to fulness, 297, 298
  10686. organism a machine for, 252, 254, 300
  10687. and perception, 5, 11, 12, 93, 188, 189, 206, 227-30, 300, 307, 368
  10688. possible, 12, 13, 96, 144, 145, 146-7, 159, 165, 179-81, 188, 264
  10689. and science, 93, 195-6, 198-9, 329-30
  10690. and space, 203
  10691. sphere of the intellect, 155
  10692. tension in a free, 200, 207, 238, 240, 301-2
  10693. Activity, dissatisfaction the starting-point of, 297
  10694. of instinct, continuous with vital process, 139, 140
  10695. life as, 128-9, 247
  10696. mutually inverse factors in vital, 248
  10697. and nervous system, 110, 130, 132-3, 134-5, 180, 252, 261-3
  10698. organism as, 174
  10699. potential. _See_ Action, possible
  10700. tension of free, 200, 202, 207-8, 223-4, 237, 239, 300-1
  10701. and torpor in evolution, 109, 111, 113, 114, 119-20, 129-30,
  10702. 135-6, 181, 292
  10703. vital, has evolved divergently, 134
  10704. _See_ Divergent lines of evolution
  10705. Adaptation, 50-1, 55, 57-8, 59, 70, 101, 129, 133, 192, 255, 270, 305-6
  10706. and causation, 102
  10707. mutual, between materiality and intellectuality, 187, 206-7
  10708. and progress, 101-2
  10709. Adequate and inadequate in Spinoza, 353
  10710. Adjectives, substantives and verbs, 303-4, 315
  10711. Aesthetics and philosophy, 177
  10712. Affection, Role of, in the idea of chance, 234
  10713. in the idea of nought, 281-3, 289, 293, 295, 296
  10714. in negation, 286-7
  10715. Affirmation and negation, 285-6, 293
  10716. Age and individuality, 15-6
  10717. Albuminoid substances, 121-2
  10718. Alciope, 96
  10719. Alexandrian philosophy, 322, 323
  10720. Algae in illustration of probable consciousness in vegetable forms, 112
  10721. Alimentation, 113-4, 117, 247
  10722. Allegory of the Cave, 191
  10723. Alternations of increase and decrease of mutability of the universe, 245-6
  10724. Alveolar froth, 33-4
  10725. Ambiguity of the idea of "generality" in philosophy, 230-1, 320-1
  10726. of primitive organisms, 99, 112, 113, 129-30
  10727. Ammophila hirsuta, paralyzing instinct in, 173
  10728. Amoeba, in illustration of imitation of the living by the unorganized, 33-6
  10729. in illustration of the ambiguity of primitive organisms, 99
  10730. in illustration of the mobility characteristic of animals, 108
  10731. in illustration of the "explosive" expenditure of energy characteristic
  10732. of animals, 120, 253
  10733. Anagenesis, 34
  10734. Anarchy, idea of, 233, 234.
  10735. _See_ Disorder
  10736. Anatomy, comparative, and transformism, 25
  10737. Ancient philosophy, Achilles and tortoise, 311-2
  10738. Alexandrian philosophy, 322-3
  10739. Allegory of the Cave, 191
  10740. Anima (De), 322 _note_
  10741. Apogee of sensible object, 344, 345, 349
  10742. Archimedes, 343-4
  10743. Aristotle, 135, 174-5, 227-8, 314, 316, 321, 323, 324, 328-33, 347, 349,
  10744. 353, 356, 370
  10745. Arrow of Zeno, 308-13
  10746. ascent toward God, in Aristotle, 323
  10747. Astronomy, ancient and modern, 334-6
  10748. attraction and impulsion in, 323-4
  10749. becoming in, 313-4, 317
  10750. bow and indivisibility of motion, 308-9
  10751. Caelo (De), of Aristotle, 322 _note_, 324 _note_
  10752. and Cartesian geometry, 334-5
  10753. causality in, 323, 325-6
  10754. change in, 313-4, 317, 328-9, 342-3
  10755. cinematographical nature of, 315
  10756. circularity of God's thought, 323-4
  10757. concentric spheres, 328
  10758. concepts, 326-7, 356
  10759. "conversion" and "procession" in, 323
  10760. degradation of ideas into sensible flux, 317-8, 321, 323-4, 327, 328,
  10761. 343-5, 352-3
  10762. degrees of reality, 323-4, 327
  10763. diminution, derivation of becoming by. _See_ Degradation of Ideas, etc.
  10764. duration, 317-9 _note_, 323-4, 327-9
  10765. Eleatic philosophy, 308, 314
  10766. Enneads of Plotinus, 210 _note_
  10767. essence and accident, 354
  10768. essence or form, 314-5
  10769. eternal, 317-8, 324-6
  10770. Eternity, 317-8, 320, 324, 328-9
  10771. extension, 210 _note_, 318, 324, 327
  10772. form or idea, 314-20, 322, 327, 329-31, 352
  10773. geometry, Cartesian, and ancient philosophy, 334
  10774. God of Aristotle, 196-7, 322-4, 349, 352, 356
  10775. [Greek: hylê], 353
  10776. Idea, 314-22, 352-3
  10777. and indivisibility of motion, 307-8, 311
  10778. intelligible reality in, 326
  10779. intelligibles of Plotinus, 353
  10780. [Greek: logos], of Plotinus, 210 _note_
  10781. matter in Aristotle's philosophy, 316, 327
  10782. and modern astronomy, 333-4, 335
  10783. and modern geometry, 333-4
  10784. and modern philosophy, 226-7, 228-9, 232, 281-2, 344-5, 346, 349-51, 364,
  10785. 369
  10786. and modern science, 329-30, 336, 342-3, 344-5, 357
  10787. motion in, 307-8, 312-3
  10788. necessity in, 327
  10789. [Greek: noêseôs noêsis], 356
  10790. non-being, 316, 327
  10791. [Greek: nous poiêtikos], 322
  10792. oscillation about being, sensible reality as, 317-8
  10793. Physics of Aristotle, 227-8 _note_, 324 _note_, 330-1
  10794. Plato, 48, 156, 191, 210 _note_, 316-8, 321-4, 327, 330, 348, 349
  10795. Plotinus, 210, 316, 323, 326 _note_, 349, 352-4
  10796. procession in Alexandrian philosophy, 323
  10797. [Greek: psychê], 210 _note_, 350
  10798. realism in, 232
  10799. refraction of idea through matter or non-being, 317
  10800. sectioning of becoming, 318-9
  10801. sensible reality, 314, 316-8, 321, 327-9, 352-3
  10802. [Greek: sôma], 350
  10803. space and time, 317-9, 320
  10804. Timaeus, 318 _note_
  10805. time in ancient and in modern science, 330-1, 336-7, 341-4
  10806. time and space, 317-9, 320
  10807. vision of God in Alexandrian philosophy, 322
  10808. Zeno, 308, 313
  10809. Ancient science and modern, 329-31, 336-7, 342-5, 357
  10810. Anima (De), of Aristotle, 322 _note_
  10811. Animal kingdom, 12, 105-6, 119-21, 126, 129, 131-2, 134-6, 137-8, 139, 179,
  10812. 184-5
  10813. Animals, 105-47, 167, 170, 181, 183, 187, 212, 214, 246, 252, 253, 254,
  10814. 262-5, 267, 271, 293, 301
  10815. deduction in, 212
  10816. induction in, 214
  10817. and man, 139-43, 183, 187, 188, 212, 263, 264, 267
  10818. and man in respect to brain, 183, 184-5, 263-5
  10819. and man in respect to consciousness, 139-43, 180, 183, 187, 188, 192,
  10820. 212, 263-8
  10821. and man in respect to instruments of action, 139-43, 150-1
  10822. and man in respect to intelligence, 137-8, 187, 188, 191-2, 212
  10823. and plants, 105-39, 124-6, 143, 145, 146-7, 168-70, 181-2, 253, 254, 293
  10824. and plants in respect to activity of consciousness, 109, 111, 113,
  10825. 119-21, 128-9, 132, 134-6, 142-3, 144, 181-2, 293
  10826. and plants in respect to function, 117-8, 121-2, 127
  10827. and plants in respect to instinct, 167, 170
  10828. and plants in respect to mobility, 109, 110, 113, 129-30, 132-3, 135, 181
  10829. and plants in respect to nature of consciousness, 134-5
  10830. Antagonistic currents of the vital impetus, 129, 135-6, 181, 184, 250,
  10831. 258-9
  10832. Anthophora, 146-7
  10833. Antinomies of Kant, 204, 205
  10834. Antipathy. _See_ Sympathy, Feeling, Divination
  10835. Antithesis and thesis, 205
  10836. Ants, 101, 134, 140, 157
  10837. Ape's brain and consciousness contrasted with man's, 263
  10838. Aphasia, 181
  10839. Apidae, social instinct in the, 171
  10840. Apogee of instinct in the hymenoptera and of intelligence in man, 174-5
  10841. _See_ Evolutionary superiority
  10842. Apogee of sensible object, in philosophy of Ideas, 343-4, 349
  10843. Approximateness of the knowledge of matter, 206-7
  10844. Approximation, in matter, to the mathematical order, 218.
  10845. _See_ Order
  10846. Archimedes, 333-4
  10847. Aristotle. _See_ Ancient Philosophy, Aristotle
  10848. Arrow, Flying, of Zeno, 308-9, 310, 312-3
  10849. Art, 6-7, 29 _note_, 45, 89, 177
  10850. Artemia Salina, transformations of, 72, 73
  10851. Arthropods in evolution, 130-5, 142
  10852. Articulate species, 133
  10853. Articulations of matter relative to action, 156, 367
  10854. of motion, 310-1
  10855. of real time, 332-3
  10856. Artificial, how far scientific knowledge is, 197, 218-9
  10857. instruments, 138, 139, 140-1
  10858. Artist, in illustration of the creativeness of duration, 340-1
  10859. Ascending cosmic movement, 11, 208, 275, 369
  10860. Ascent toward God, in Aristotle, 323
  10861. Association of organisms, 260.
  10862. _See_ Individuation
  10863. universal oscillation between association and individuation, 259, 260.
  10864. _See_ Societies
  10865. Astronomy and deduction, 213
  10866. and the inert order, 224
  10867. modern, in reference to ancient science, 334-6
  10868. Atmosphere of spatiality bathing intelligence, 204
  10869. Atom, 240, 254, 255
  10870. as an intellectual view of matter, 203, 250
  10871. and interpenetration, 207
  10872. Attack and defence in evolution, 131-2
  10873. Attention, 2, 148-9, 154, 184, 209
  10874. discontinuity of, 2
  10875. in man and in lower animals, 184.
  10876. _See_ Tension and instinct, Tension as inverted extension,
  10877. Tension of personality, Sympathetic appreciation, etc.,
  10878. Relaxation and intellect
  10879. Attraction and impulsion in Greek philosophy, 323, 324
  10880. Attribute and subject, 148
  10881. Automatic activity, 145
  10882. as instrument of voluntary, 252
  10883. order, 224, 231-4.
  10884. _See_ Negative movement, etc., Geometrical order
  10885. Automatism, 127, 143-4, 174, 223-4, 261, 264
  10886. Background of instinct and intelligence, consciousness as, 186
  10887. Backward-looking attitude of the intellect, 47, 48, 237
  10888. Baldwin, J.M., 27 _note_
  10889. Ballast of intelligence, 152, 230, 239, 369-70
  10890. Bastian, 212 _note_
  10891. Bateson, 63
  10892. Becoming, 164, 236, 248-9, 273, 299-304, 307-8, 313-4, 316, 337-8,
  10893. 342-3, 345, 363
  10894. in ancient philosophy, 313-4, 317
  10895. in Descartes's philosophy, 346
  10896. in Eleatic philosophy, 313-4, 315
  10897. in general, or abstract becoming, 304, 306-7
  10898. instantaneous and static views of, 272, 304-5
  10899. states of, falsely so called, 164, 247-8, 273, 298-301, 307-8
  10900. in the successors of Kant, 363.
  10901. _See_ Change, New, Duration, Time, Views of reality
  10902. Bees, 101, 140, 142, 146, 166, 172
  10903. Beethoven, 224
  10904. Berthold, 34 _note_
  10905. Bethe, 176 _note_
  10906. Bifurcations of tendency, 54.
  10907. _See_ Divergent lines of evolution
  10908. Biology, 12, 25, 26, 31-2, 43, 168-9, 174-5, 194-6
  10909. evolutionist, 168-9
  10910. and philosophy, 43, 194-6
  10911. and physico-chemistry, 26
  10912. Blaringhem, 85
  10913. Bodies, 156, 188, 189, 300-1, 360.
  10914. _See_ Inert matter as a relaxation of the unextended into the
  10915. extended defined as bundles of qualities, 349
  10916. Bois-Reymond (Du), 38
  10917. Boltzmann, 245
  10918. Bombines, social instincts in, 171
  10919. Bouvier, 142 _note_
  10920. Bow, strain of, illustrating indivisibility of motion, 308-10
  10921. Brain and consciousness, 5, 109, 110, 179-80, 183-4, 212 _note_, 252,
  10922. 261-4, 270, 354, 356, 366.
  10923. _See_ Nervous System in man and lower animals, 183, 184, 263-5
  10924. Brandt, 66 _note_
  10925. Breast-Plate, in reference to animal mobility, 130, 131.
  10926. _See_ Carapace, Cellulose envelope
  10927. Brown-Séquard, 80-2
  10928. Bulb, medullary, in the development of the nervous system, 110, 252
  10929. Busquet, 259 _note_
  10930. Bütschli, 33 _note_
  10931. Buttel-Reepen, 171 _note_
  10932. Butterflies, in illustration of variation from evolutionary type, 72
  10933. Caelo (De), of Aristotle, 322 _note_, 324 _note_
  10934. Calcareous sheath, in reference to animal mobility, 130-1
  10935. Calkins, 16 _note_
  10936. Canal, in illustration of the relation of function and structure, 93
  10937. Canalization, in illustration of the function of animal organisms, 93,
  10938. 95, 110, 126, 256, 270
  10939. Canvas, embroidering "something" on the, of "nothing," 297
  10940. Caprice, an attribute not of freedom but of mechanism, 47
  10941. Carapace, in reference to animal mobility, 130-1
  10942. Carbohydrates, in reference to the function of the animal organism, 121-2
  10943. Carbon, in reference to the function of organisms, 107, 113, 114, 117,
  10944. 254, 255
  10945. Carbonic acid, in reference to the function of organisms, 254, 255
  10946. Carnot, 243, 246, 256
  10947. Cartesian geometry, compared with ancient, 334
  10948. Cartesianism, 345, 356, 358
  10949. Cartesians, 358. _See_ Spinoza, Leibniz
  10950. Carving, the, of matter by intellect, 155
  10951. Categorical propositions, characteristic of instinctive knowledge, 149-50
  10952. Categories, conceptual, x, xiii, 48, 147, 148-9, 165, 189-90, 195-7, 207,
  10953. 220-1, 257-60, 265, 358, 361.
  10954. _See_ Concept deduction of, and genesis of the intellect, 196, 207, 359.
  10955. _See_ Genesis of matter and of the intellect
  10956. innate, 147, 148-9
  10957. misfit for the vital, x, xiii, 48, 165, 195-9, 220-1, 257-9
  10958. in reference to the adaptation to each other of the matter and form of
  10959. knowledge, 361
  10960. Cats, in illustration of the law of correlation, 67
  10961. Causal relation in Aristotle, 325
  10962. between consciousness and movement, 111
  10963. in Greek philosophy, 324-5
  10964. Causality, mechanical, a category which does not apply to life, x, xiv, 177
  10965. in the philosophy of Ideas, 323-6
  10966. Causation and adaptation, 101, 102
  10967. final, involves mechanical, 44
  10968. Cause and effect as mathematical functions of each other, 20, 21
  10969. efficient, 238, 277, 323
  10970. efficient, in Aristotle's philosophy, 324
  10971. efficient, in Leibniz's philosophy, 353
  10972. final, 40, 44, 238
  10973. final, in Aristotle's philosophy, 324
  10974. by impulsion, release and unwinding, 73
  10975. mechanical, as containing effect, 14, 233, 269
  10976. in the vital order, 95, 164
  10977. Cave, Plato's allegory of the, 191
  10978. Cell, 16, 24, 33, 162, 166, 167, 260, 269
  10979. as artificial construct, 162
  10980. in the "colonial theory," 260
  10981. division, 16, 24, 33
  10982. instinct in the, 166, 167
  10983. in relation to the soul, 269
  10984. Cellulose envelope in reference to vegetable immobility and torpor, 108,
  10985. 111, 130
  10986. Cerebral activity and consciousness, 5, 109-10, 180-1, 183-4, 212 _note_,
  10987. 252, 253, 261, 264, 268, 270, 350, 351, 354, 355, 366
  10988. mechanism, 5, 252, 253, 262, 264, 366
  10989. Cerebro-spinal system, 124. _See_ Nervous system
  10990. Certainty of induction, 215, 216
  10991. Chance analogous to disorder, 233, 234.
  10992. _See_ Affection
  10993. in evolution, 86-7, 104, 114-5, 126, 169-70, 171, 252, 254, 255, 266,
  10994. 267, 326-7.
  10995. _See_ Indetermination
  10996. Change, 1, 7-8, 18, 85-6, 248, 275, 294, 300-304, 308, 313-4, 317, 326,
  10997. 328-9, 343-4, 344-5
  10998. in ancient philosophy, 313-4, 316-7, 325-6, 327-9, 343, 345
  10999. in Eleatic philosophy, 314
  11000. known only from within, 307-8
  11001. Chaos, 232.
  11002. _See_ Disorder
  11003. Character, moral, 5, 99-100
  11004. Charrin, 81 _note_
  11005. Chemistry, 27, 34-6, 55, 72, 74, 98, 194, 226, 256, 260
  11006. Child, intelligence in, 147-8
  11007. adolescence of, in illustration of evolutionary becoming, 311-3
  11008. Chipped stone, in paleontology, 139
  11009. Chlorophyllian function, 107-9, 114, 117, 246, 253
  11010. Choice, 110, 125, 143-5, 179, 180, 252, 260-4, 276, 366
  11011. and consciousness, 110, 179, 260-4
  11012. Chrysalis, 114 _note_
  11013. Cinematograph, 306-7, 339-40
  11014. Cinematographical character of ancient philosophy, 315-6
  11015. of intellectual knowledge, 306, 307, 312-8, 323-4, 331-3, 346
  11016. of language, 306-7, 312-5
  11017. of modern science, 329-31, 336-7, 341-3, 345, 346, 347
  11018. Circle of the given, broken by action, 192, 247
  11019. logical and physical, 277
  11020. vicious, in intellectualist philosophy, 193, 197, 320
  11021. vicious, in the intuitional method is only apparent, 192, 193
  11022. Circularity of God's thought in Aristotle's philosophy, 324
  11023. of each special evolution, 128
  11024. Circulation, protoplasmic, imitated, 32-3
  11025. in plants and animals, 108
  11026. Circumstances in the determination of evolution, 101-2, 128-9, 133, 138,
  11027. 142, 150-1, 167, 168, 170-1, 193, 194, 252, 256
  11028. in relation to special instincts, 138, 168, 193
  11029. Classes of words corresponding to the three kinds of representation, 303-4
  11030. Clausius, 243
  11031. Clearness characteristic of intellect, 160
  11032. Cleft between the organized and the unorganized, 190, 196-9
  11033. Climbing plants, instincts of, 170 _note_
  11034. Coincidence of matter with space as in Kant, 206, 207, 244
  11035. of mind with intellect as in Kant, 48, 206
  11036. of qualities, 216
  11037. of seeing and willing, 237
  11038. of self with self, definition of the feeling of duration, 199-200
  11039. Coleopter, instinct in, 146
  11040. Colonial theory, 259, 260
  11041. Colonies, microbial, 259
  11042. Color variation in lizards, 72, 74
  11043. Coming and going of the mind between the without and the within gives rise
  11044. to the idea of "Nothing," 279
  11045. between nature and mind, the true method of philosophy, 239
  11046. Common-sense, 29, 153, 161, 213, 224, 277
  11047. defined as continuous experience of the real, 213
  11048. Comparison of ancient philosophy with modern, 226, 228-9, 232, 328-9,
  11049. 345-6, 349-51, 353-4, 356
  11050. Compenetration, 352-3. _See_ Interpenetration
  11051. Complementarity of forms evolved, xii, xiii, 51, 101, 103, 113, 116-7,
  11052. 135, 136, 254, 255
  11053. of instinct and intelligence, 146, 173.
  11054. _See_ Opposition of Instinct and Intelligence
  11055. of intuition and intellect, 343, 345
  11056. in the powers of life, 49, 96-7, 140-3, 177, 178-9, 183-5, 239, 246,
  11057. 254, 343
  11058. of science and metaphysics, 344
  11059. Complexity of the order of mathematics, 208-10, 217, 251
  11060. Compound reflex, instinct as a, 174
  11061. Concentration, intellect as, 191, 301
  11062. of personality, 198-9, 201
  11063. Concentric spheres in Aristotle's philosophy, 328
  11064. Concept accessory to action, ix
  11065. analogy of, with the solid body, ix
  11066. in animals, 187
  11067. externality of, 160, 168, 175-8, 199-200, 251, 306, 311, 314
  11068. fringed about with intuition, 46
  11069. and image distinguished, 160, 279
  11070. impotent to grasp life, ix-xiii, 49
  11071. intellect the concept-making faculty, vi, 49
  11072. misfit for the vital, 48
  11073. representation of the act by which the intellect is fixed on things, 161
  11074. synthesis of, in ancient philosophy, 325-6, 356.
  11075. _See_ Categories, Externality, Frames, Image, Space, Symbol
  11076. Conditions, external, in evolution, 128-9, 133, 138, 141-2, 150-1, 166-7,
  11077. 168, 170, 193, 194, 251, 256, 257
  11078. external, in determination of special instinct, 141-2, 150-1, 167,
  11079. 168, 171
  11080. Conduct, mechanism and finality in the evolution of, 47.
  11081. _See_ Freedom, Determination, Indetermination
  11082. Confused plurality of life, 257
  11083. Conjugation of Infusoria, 16
  11084. Consciousness and action, ix, 5, 144, 145, 179-80, 207, 260-1
  11085. consciousness as appendage to action, ix
  11086. consciousness as arithmetical difference between possible and real
  11087. activity, 145
  11088. consciousness as auxiliary to action, 179-80
  11089. consciousness as inadequacy of act to representation, 144
  11090. consciousness as instrument of action, 180
  11091. consciousness as interval between possible and real action, 145, 179
  11092. consciousness as light from zone of possible actions surrounding the
  11093. real act, 179
  11094. consciousness and locomotion, 262
  11095. consciousness plugged up by action, 144, 145.
  11096. _See_ Torpor, Sleep
  11097. consciousness as sketch of action, 207
  11098. intensity of, varies with ratio of possible to real action, 145
  11099. Consciousness in animals, as distinguished from the consciousness of
  11100. plants, 130, 135-6, 143
  11101. as distinguished from the consciousness of man, 139-43, 180, 183, 184,
  11102. 187, 188, 212, 263-9.
  11103. _See_ Torpor, Sleep
  11104. characteristic of animals, torpor of plants, 109, 111, 113, 120, 128-9,
  11105. 135-6, 181, 182, 292
  11106. as background of instinct and intelligence, 186
  11107. and brain, 180, 262, 263, 269, 270, 354
  11108. and choice, 110, 144-5, 179, 262-4
  11109. coextensive with universal life, 186, 270
  11110. and creation, consciousness as demand for creation, 261
  11111. current of, penetrating matter, 181, 270
  11112. as deficiency of instinct, 145
  11113. in dog and man, 180
  11114. double form of, 179
  11115. function of, 207
  11116. as hesitation or choice, 143, 144
  11117. imprisonment of, 180, 183-4, 264
  11118. as invention and freedom, 264, 270
  11119. in man as distinguished from, in lower forms of life, 180, 263, 264,
  11120. 267, 268
  11121. and matter, 179, 181-2
  11122. as motive principle of evolution, 181-2
  11123. nullified, as distinguished from the absence of consciousness, 143
  11124. and the organism, 270
  11125. in plants, 131, 135-6, 143
  11126. as world principle, 237, 261
  11127. Conservation of energy, 243, 244
  11128. Construction, 139-42, 150-1, 156, 157-8, 180, 182.
  11129. _See_ Manufacture, Solid
  11130. the characteristic work of intellect, 163-4
  11131. as the method of Kant's successors, 364-5
  11132. Contingency, 96, 255, 268.
  11133. _See_ Accident, Chance
  11134. the, of order, 231, 235
  11135. Continuation of vital process in instinct, 138, 139, 166, 167, 246.
  11136. _See_ Variations, Vital process
  11137. Continuity, 1, 26, 29-30, 37, 138-40, 154, 162-4, 258, 302, 306-7, 311-2,
  11138. 321, 325-6, 329-30, 347
  11139. of becoming, 306-7, 312
  11140. of change, 325-6
  11141. of evolution, 18, 19
  11142. of extension, 154
  11143. of germinative plasma, 26, 37
  11144. of instinct with vital process, 139, 140, 166-7, 246
  11145. of life, 1-11, 29, 163-4, 258
  11146. of living substance, 162
  11147. of psychic life, 1, 30
  11148. of the real, 302, 329-30
  11149. of sensible intuition with ultra-intellectual, 361
  11150. of sensible universe, 346
  11151. Conventionality of science, 207
  11152. "Conversion" and "procession" in Alexandrian philosophy, 323
  11153. Cook, Plato's comparison of the, and the dialectician, 156
  11154. Cope, 35 _note_, 77, 111
  11155. Correlation, law of, 66, 67
  11156. Correspondence between mind and matter in Spencer, 368.
  11157. _See_ Simultaneity
  11158. Cortical mechanism, 252, 253, 262.
  11159. _See_ Cerebral mechanism
  11160. Cosmogony and genesis of matter, 188.
  11161. _See_ Genesis of matter and of intellect, Spencer
  11162. Cosmology the, that follows from the philosophy of Ideas, 315, 328
  11163. as reversed psychology, 208
  11164. Counterweight representation as, to action, 145
  11165. Counting simultaneities, the measurement of time is, 338, 341-2
  11166. Creation, xi, 7, 11, 12, 22, 29, 30, 45, 93, 100, 101, 103, 105, 108, 114,
  11167. 128-31, 161, 163-4, 178, 200, 217, 218, 223, 226, 230, 237-40, 261,
  11168. 270, 275, 339-40
  11169. in Descartes's philosophy, 345
  11170. of intellect, 248-9
  11171. of matter, 237, 239, 247-8, 249.
  11172. _See_ Materiality the inversion of spirituality
  11173. of present by past, 5, 20-3, 27, 167, 199-202
  11174. the vital order as, 230
  11175. Creative evolution, 7, 15, 21, 27, 29, 36, 37, 65, 100, 104-5, 161,
  11176. 163, 223-4, 230-1, 237, 264, 269
  11177. Creativeness of free action, 192, 243
  11178. of invention, 250
  11179. Creeping plants in illustration of vegetable mobility, 108
  11180. Cricket victim of paralyzing instinct of sphex, 172
  11181. Criterion, quest of a, 53 _ff._
  11182. of evolutionary rank, 133, 265
  11183. Criticism, Kantian, 205, 287 _note_, 356, 360-2
  11184. of knowledge, 194-5
  11185. Cross-cuts through becoming by intellect, 314.
  11186. _See_ Views of reality
  11187. through matter by perception, 206
  11188. Cross-roads of vital tendency, 51, 52, 54, 110, 126
  11189. Crustacea, 19, 111, 129-30
  11190. Crystal illustrating (by contrast) individuation, 12
  11191. Cuénot, 79 _note_
  11192. Culminating points of evolutionary progress, 50, 133-5.
  11193. _See_ Evolutionary superiority
  11194. Current, 26, 27, 51, 185, 236, 237, 250, 266, 269
  11195. Currents, antagonistic, 250
  11196. of existence, 185
  11197. of life penetrating matter, 26, 27, 266, 270
  11198. vital, 26, 27, 51, 237, 266, 270
  11199. of will penetrating matter, 237
  11200. Curves, as symbol of life, 32, 90, 213
  11201. Cuts through becoming by the intellect, 313-4.
  11202. _See_ Views of reality, Snapshots in illustration, etc.
  11203. through matter by perception, 206
  11204. Cuvier, 125 _note_
  11205. Dantec (Le), 18 _note_, 34 _note_
  11206. Darwin, 62-5, 66, 72, 108, 170 _note_
  11207. Darwinism, 56, 85, 86
  11208. Dastre, 36 _note_
  11209. Dead, the, is the object of intellect, 165
  11210. Dead-locks in speculation, 155, 312
  11211. Death, 246 _note_, 271
  11212. Declivity descended by matter, 208, 246, 256, 339-40.
  11213. _See_ Descending movement
  11214. Decomposing and recomposing powers characteristic of intellect, 157, 251
  11215. Deduction, analogy between, related to moral sphere and tangent to
  11216. curve, 213
  11217. and astronomy, 213
  11218. duration refractory to, 213
  11219. geometry the ideal limit of, 213-26, 361
  11220. in animals, 212
  11221. inverse to positive spiritual effort, 212
  11222. nature of, 211
  11223. physics and, 213
  11224. weakness of, in psychology and moral science, 213
  11225. Defence and attack in evolution, 132
  11226. Deficiency of will the negative condition of mathematical order and
  11227. complexity, 209
  11228. Definition in the realm of life, 13, 105, 106
  11229. Degenerates, 133-5
  11230. _Dégénérescence sénile (La)_, by Metchnikoff, 18 _note_
  11231. Degradation of energy, 241, 242, 246
  11232. of the extra-spatial into the spatial, 207
  11233. of the ideas into the sensible flux in ancient philosophy, 317-9,
  11234. 324-5, 327-9, 331, 343, 345, 352-3
  11235. Degrees of being in the successors of Kant, 362-3
  11236. Degrees of reality in Greek philosophy, 324, 327
  11237. Delage, 59 _note_, 81 _note_, 260 _note_
  11238. Delamare, 81 _note_
  11239. Deliberation, 144
  11240. De Manacéine, 124 _note_
  11241. Deposit, instinct and intelligence as deposits, emanations, issues, or
  11242. aspects of life, x, xii, xiii, 49, 103, 105, 136, 365
  11243. De Saporta, 107 _note_
  11244. Descartes, 280, 334, 345, 346, 353, 358
  11245. becoming, 345-6
  11246. creation, 346
  11247. determinism, 345
  11248. duration, 346
  11249. freedom, 345, 346
  11250. geometry, 334
  11251. God, 346
  11252. image and idea or concept, 281
  11253. indeterminism, 345
  11254. mechanism, 345, 346
  11255. motion, 346
  11256. vacillation between abstract time and real duration, 345
  11257. Descending movement of existence, 11, 202, 203, 208, 271, 275, 369
  11258. Design, motionless, of action the object of intellect, 154-5, 299,
  11259. 301-2, 303
  11260. Detention in the dream state, 202
  11261. of intuition in intellect, 238
  11262. Determination, 76-7, 129-30, 223, 246
  11263. Determinism, 217, 264, 345, 348. _See_ Inert matter, Geometry
  11264. in Descartes, 345
  11265. Development, 133, 134-5, 141.
  11266. _See_ Order, Progress, Evolution, Superiority
  11267. Deviation from type, 82-4
  11268. Dialect and intuition in philosophy, 238
  11269. Dichotomy of the real in modern philosophy, 350
  11270. Differentiation of parts in an organism, 253, 260
  11271. Dilemma of any systematic metaphysics, 195, 197, 230
  11272. Diminution, derivation of becoming from being by, in ancient philosophy,
  11273. 316, 317, 322, 323-4, 327-8, 343-5, 352
  11274. geometrical order as, or lower complication of the vital order, 236
  11275. Dionaea illustrating certain animal characteristics in plants, 107,
  11276. 108, 109
  11277. Discontinuity of action, 154, 306-7
  11278. of attention, 2
  11279. of extension relative to action, 154, 163
  11280. of knowledge, 306
  11281. of living substance, 163
  11282. a positive idea, 154
  11283. Discontinuous the object of intellect, 154
  11284. Discord in nature, 127, 128, 254-5, 267
  11285. Disorder, 40, 104, 222-3, 225-6, 232-5, 274.
  11286. _See_ Expectation, Order, mathematical, Orders of reality, two
  11287. Disproportion between an invention and its consequences, 182
  11288. Dissociation as a cosmic principle opposed to association, 260
  11289. of tendencies, 54, 89, 135, 254, 255, 257, 258.
  11290. _See_ Divergent lines of evolution
  11291. Distance, extension as the, between what is and what ought to be, 318-9,
  11292. 327-8, 331
  11293. Distinct multiplicity in the dream state, 201, 210
  11294. of the inert, 257
  11295. Distinctness characteristic of the intellect, 160, 237, 251
  11296. characteristic of perception, 227, 251
  11297. as spatiality, 203, 207-8, 244, 250
  11298. Divergent lines of evolution, xii, 54, 55, 87, 97-101, 103-4, 106, 107,
  11299. 109, 112, 113, 116, 119, 130, 132, 134-5, 142, 149, 150, 168, 173, 181,
  11300. 254, 255, 266, 267.
  11301. _See_ Dissociation of tendencies, Complementarity, etc., Schisms
  11302. in the primitive impulsion of life
  11303. Diversity, sensible, 205, 220-1, 231, 235, 236
  11304. Divination, instinct as, 176.
  11305. _See_ Sympathy, etc.
  11306. Divisibility of extension, 154, 162
  11307. Division as function of intellect, 152, 154, 162-3, 189
  11308. of labor, 99, 110, 118, 157, 166, 260
  11309. of labor in cells, 166
  11310. Dog and man, consciousness in, 180
  11311. Dogmatism of the ancient epistemology contrasted with the relativism of
  11312. the modern, 230
  11313. of Leibniz and Spinoza, 356-7
  11314. skepticism, and relativism, 196-7, 230
  11315. Dogs and the law of correlation, 66
  11316. Domestication of animals and heredity, 80
  11317. Dominants of Reinke, 42 _note_
  11318. Dorfmeister, 72
  11319. Dream, 144, 180-1, 202, 209, 256.
  11320. _See_ Interpenetration, Relaxation, Detention, Recollection
  11321. as relaxation, 202
  11322. Driesch, 42 _note_
  11323. Drosera, 107, 108, 109
  11324. Dufourt, 124 _note_
  11325. Duhem, 242 _note_
  11326. Dunan, Ch., xv _note_
  11327. Duration, xiv _note_, 2, 4-6, 8-11, 15, 17, 21, 22, 37, 39, 46, 51,
  11328. 199, 201, 206, 213, 216, 240, 272, 273, 276, 298-9, 308-9, 317-8, 319
  11329. _note_, 324, 328, 332, 339, 342, 343, 345, 354, 361, 363-4
  11330. absoluteness of, 206
  11331. and deduction, 213
  11332. in Descartes's philosophy, 346
  11333. gnawing of, 4, 8, 46
  11334. indivisibility of, 6, 308-9
  11335. and induction, 216
  11336. and the inert, 343-4
  11337. in the philosophy of the Ideas, 316-7, 319 _note_, 324, 327, 328-9
  11338. rhythm of, 11, 128, 346.
  11339. _See_ Creation, Evolution, Invention, Time, Unforeseeableness,
  11340. Uniqueness
  11341. Echinoderms in reference to animal mobility, 130, 131
  11342. Efficient cause in conception of chance, 234
  11343. Spinoza and, 269
  11344. Effort in evolution, 170
  11345. [Greek: Eidos], 314-5
  11346. Eimer, 55, 72, 73, 86
  11347. Elaborateness of the mathematical order, 208-10, 217, 251
  11348. Eleatic philosophy, 308, 314-5
  11349. Emanation, logical thought an, issue, aspect or deposit of life, ix, xii,
  11350. xiii, 49
  11351. Embroidering "something" on the canvas of "nothing," 297
  11352. Embroidery by descendants on the canvas handed down by ancestors, 23
  11353. Embryo, 18, 19, 26, 27, 75, 81, 89, 101, 166
  11354. Embryogeny, comparative, and transformism, 25
  11355. Embryonic life, 27, 166
  11356. Empirical study of evolution the centre of the theory of knowledge and of
  11357. the theory of life, 178
  11358. theories of knowledge, 205
  11359. Empty, thinking the full by means of the empty, 273-4
  11360. End in Eleatic philosophy, 314-5
  11361. of science is practical utility, 329
  11362. Energy, 115-7, 120-3, 242, 243, 245, 246, 252-5, 256, 257, 262
  11363. conservation of, 242
  11364. degradation of, 242, 243, 246
  11365. solar, stored by plants, released by animals, 245, 254
  11366. Enneadae of Plotinus, 210 _note_
  11367. Entelechy of Driesch, 42 _note_
  11368. Entropy, 243
  11369. Environment in evolution, 129, 133, 138, 140, 142, 150, 167, 168, 170,
  11370. 192, 193, 252, 256, 257
  11371. and special instincts, 138, 168, 192, 193
  11372. Epiphenomenalism, 262
  11373. Essence and accidents in Aristotle's philosophy, 353
  11374. or form in Eleatic philosophy, 314-5
  11375. the meaning of, 302-3
  11376. Essences (or forms), qualities and acts, the three kinds of
  11377. representation, 303-4
  11378. Eternity, 39, 298, 314, 317, 320, 324, 328, 346, 352, 354
  11379. in the philosophy of Ideas, 316-7, 319, 324, 328
  11380. in Spinoza's philosophy, 353
  11381. Euglena, 116
  11382. Evellin, 311 _note_
  11383. Eventual actions, 11, 96.
  11384. _See_ Possible activity
  11385. Evolution, ix-xv, 18, 20, 22, 24, 25, 26-7, 37, 46-55, 63, 68, 79
  11386. _note_, 84-8, 97-105, 107, 113, 116, 126, 127, 129-30, 131-2,
  11387. 133, 134, 136, 138-40, 141-2, 143, 161, 166, 167, 168-72, 173, 174,
  11388. 175, 179, 181, 182, 185, 186, 190, 193, 198-9, 207-8, 224, 231, 242
  11389. _note_, 246, 248, 249, 251, 252, 254, 264-6, 268, 273, 302, 311,
  11390. 345, 359, 360, 366
  11391. accident in, 104, 169, 170, 173, 174, 251, 252
  11392. animal, a progress toward mobility, 131
  11393. antagonistic tendencies in, 103, 113, 185
  11394. automatic and determinate, is action being undone, 248
  11395. blind alleys of, 129
  11396. circularity of each special, 128
  11397. complementarity of the divergent lines of, 97-102, 103, 116
  11398. conceptually inexpressible, 49, 50, 52, 53, 127, 181, 273
  11399. continuity of, 18, 19, 26, 37, 46, 273, 302, 312, 345
  11400. creative, 7, 15, 21, 27, 30, 36, 37, 65, 100, 105, 161, 162, 163, 223,
  11401. 230, 238, 264, 269
  11402. culminating points of, 50, 133, 174, 185, 265, 266, 268
  11403. development by, 133, 134, 141-2
  11404. divergent lines of, xii, 53, 54, 87, 97-101, 103-4, 107, 173-4, 246
  11405. and duration, 20, 22, 37, 45-6
  11406. empirical study of, the centre of the theory of knowledge and of life,
  11407. 178
  11408. and environment, 101-3, 129, 133, 138, 142, 150, 167, 168, 169, 192,
  11409. 193, 251, 256, 257
  11410. of instinct, 170, 171, 174-5.
  11411. _See_ Divergent lines, etc., Culminating points, etc., Evolution
  11412. and environment
  11413. of intellect, x-xii, 153, 186, 189-90, 193, 198-9, 207-8, 359, 360.
  11414. _See_ Divergent lines, etc., Culminating points, etc., Genesis
  11415. of matter and of intellect
  11416. as invention, 344
  11417. of man, 264, 266, 268. _See_ Culminating points, etc.
  11418. motive principle of, is consciousness, 181
  11419. of species product of the vital impetus opposed by matter, 247-8, 254
  11420. and transformism, 24
  11421. unforeseeable, 47, 48, 53, 86, 224
  11422. variation in, 23-4, 55, 63, 68, 72 _note_, 85, 131, 137-8, 167, 169,
  11423. 171, 264
  11424. Evolutionary, qualitative, and extensive motion 302-3, 311, 312
  11425. superiority, 133-5, 174-5.
  11426. _See_ Success, Criterion of evolutionary rank, Culminating points, etc.
  11427. Evolutionism, x-xii, xiv, 77, 84, 364
  11428. Exhaustion of the mutability of the universe, 337-8
  11429. Existence, logical, as contrasted with psychical and physical, 276, 362
  11430. of matter tends toward instantaneity, 201
  11431. of self means change, 1 _ff._
  11432. superaddition of, upon nothingness, 276
  11433. Expectation, 214-6, 221, 222, 226, 233, 235, 274, 281, 292
  11434. in conception of disorder, 221, 222, 226, 233, 234, 235, 274
  11435. in conception of void or naught, 282, 292
  11436. Experience, 138, 147, 177, 197, 204, 229, 321, 354, 359, 363, 368
  11437. Explosion, illustrating cause by release, 73
  11438. Explosive character of animal energy, 116, 119, 120, 246
  11439. of organization, 92
  11440. Explosives, manufacture of, by plants and use by animals, 246, 254
  11441. Extension, 149, 154, 161, 202, 203, 207, 211, 223, 236, 245, 318-20,
  11442. 324, 327, 351, 352
  11443. continuity of, 154
  11444. discontinuity of, relative to action, 154, 162
  11445. as the distance between what is and what ought to be, 318
  11446. divisibility of, 154, 162
  11447. the most general property of matter, 154, 250, 251
  11448. the inverse movement to tension, 245
  11449. of knowledge, 150
  11450. in Leibniz's philosophy, 351, 352
  11451. of matter in space, 204, 211
  11452. in the philosophy of Ideas, 318-9, 323-4, 327
  11453. and relaxation, 202, 207, 209, 211, 212, 218, 223, 245
  11454. in Spinoza's philosophy, 350
  11455. in the Transcendental Aesthetic, 203
  11456. unity of, 158-9
  11457. as weakening of the essence of being, in Plotinus, 210 _note_
  11458. Extensive, evolutionary and qualitative motion, 302-3, 311, 312
  11459. External conditions in evolution, 128, 133, 137, 141-2, 150-1, 167,
  11460. 168, 170, 192, 193, 252, 256, 257
  11461. finality, 41
  11462. Externality of concepts, 160, 168, 174, 177, 199, 251, 305, 311-4
  11463. the most general property of matter, 154, 250, 251
  11464. Externalized action in distinction from internalized, 147, 165.
  11465. _See_ Somnambulism, etc., Automatic activity, etc.
  11466. Eye of mollusc and vertebrate compared, 60, 75, 77, 84, 86, 87-8
  11467. Fabre, 172 _note_
  11468. Fabrication. _See_ Construction
  11469. Fallacies, two fundamental, 272, 273
  11470. Fallacy of thinking being by not-being, 276, 277, 284, 297-8
  11471. of thinking the full by the empty, 273-5
  11472. of thinking motion by the motionless, 272, 273, 297-8, 307-8, 309-14
  11473. Fallibility of instinct, 172-3
  11474. Falling back of matter upon consciousness, 264
  11475. bodies, comparison of Aristotle and Galileo, 228, 331-2, 334
  11476. weight, figure of material world, 245, 246
  11477. Familiar, the, is the object of intellect, 163, 164, 199, 270
  11478. Faraday, 203
  11479. Fasting, in reference to primacy of nervous system over the other
  11480. physiological systems, 124
  11481. Fauna, menace of torpor in primitive, 130
  11482. Feeling in the conception of chance, 207
  11483. and instinct, 143, 174-5
  11484. Fencing-master, illustrating hereditary transmission, 79
  11485. Ferments, certain characteristics of, 106
  11486. Fertilization of orchids by insects, by Darwin, 170 _note_
  11487. Fichte's conception of the intellect, 189-90, 357
  11488. Filings, iron, in illustration of the relation of structure to
  11489. function, 94, 95
  11490. Film, cinematographic, figure of abstract motion, 304-6
  11491. Final cause, 40, 45, 234, 325
  11492. conception of, involves conception of mechanical cause, 44
  11493. God as, in Aristotle, 322-3
  11494. Finalism, 39-53, 58, 74, 88-97, 101-5, 126-8
  11495. Finality, 41, 164, 177-8, 185, 223, 224, 266
  11496. external and internal, 41
  11497. misfit for the vital, 177, 223-4, 225, 266
  11498. and the unforeseeableness of life, 164, 185
  11499. Fischel, 75 _note_
  11500. Fish in illustration of animal tendency to mobility, 130, 131
  11501. Fixation of nutritive elements, 107-9, 113, 117, 246, 247, 253
  11502. Fixity, 108-13, 118, 119, 130, 155.
  11503. _See_ Torpor
  11504. apparent or relative, 155
  11505. cellulose envelope and the, of plants, 108, 111, 130
  11506. of extension, 155
  11507. of plants, 108-13, 118, 119, 130-1
  11508. of torpid animals, 130
  11509. Flint hatchets and human intelligence, 137
  11510. Fluidity of life, 153, 165, 193
  11511. of matter as a whole, 186, 369
  11512. Flux of material bodies, 265
  11513. of reality, 250, 251, 337, 342, 344
  11514. Flying arrow of Zeno, 308, 309, 310
  11515. Focalization of personality, 201
  11516. Food, 106-9, 113-4, 117, 120, 121, 246, 247, 254
  11517. Foraminifera, failure of certain, to evolve, 197
  11518. Force, 126-7, 141, 149, 150, 175, 246, 254, 339
  11519. life a, inverse to matter, 246
  11520. limitedness of vital force, 126, 127, 141, 149, 162
  11521. time as, 339-40
  11522. Forel, 176 _note_
  11523. Foreseeing, 8, 28, 29, 30, 37, 45, 47, 96.
  11524. _See_ Unforeseeableness
  11525. Form, xi, 51, 101, 104, 113, 116-8, 129, 135-6, 148-53, 155, 156, 160,
  11526. 164, 195-7, 222, 237, 250, 255, 302, 303, 314, 317, 318, 322, 341,
  11527. 357, 359, 361, 362
  11528. complementarity of forms evolved, xi, 51, 101, 104, 113, 116-8, 135-6,
  11529. 255
  11530. expansion of the forms of consciousness, xii, xiii
  11531. (or essences), qualities and acts the three kinds of representation,
  11532. 302-3
  11533. God as pure form in Aristotle, 196, 322
  11534. or idea in ancient philosophy, 317, 318, 330
  11535. of intelligence, xiv, 48, 147, 148, 165, 190, 195, 196, 198, 207, 219,
  11536. 257-9, 266, 358-9, 361. _See_ Concept
  11537. and matter in creation, 239, 250
  11538. and matter in knowledge, 195, 361
  11539. a snapshot view of transition, 302
  11540. Formal knowledge, 152
  11541. logic, 292
  11542. Forms of sensibility, 361
  11543. Fossil species, 102
  11544. Foster, 125 _note_
  11545. Fox in illustration of animal intelligence, 138
  11546. Frames of the understanding, 46-7, 48, 150-2, 173, 177, 197-9, 219-20,
  11547. 223-4, 258, 270, 313, 358, 364
  11548. fit the inert, 197, 218
  11549. inadequate to reality entire, 364
  11550. misfit for the vital, x, xiii, xiv, 46, 48, 173, 177, 197-9, 223,
  11551. 258, 313
  11552. product of life, 358
  11553. transform freedom into necessity, 270
  11554. utility of, lies in their unlimited application, 149-50, 152
  11555. Freedom, 11, 48, 126, 130, 163, 164, 200, 202, 207, 208, 217, 223, 231,
  11556. 237, 239, 247, 249, 264-6, 269, 270, 277, 300, 339-41, 345, 346
  11557. the absolute as freely acting, 277
  11558. affirmed by conscience, 269
  11559. animal characteristic rather than vegetable, 129-30
  11560. caprice attribute not of, but of mechanism, 47
  11561. coextensiveness of consciousness with, 111, 112, 202, 264, 270
  11562. of creation and life, 247, 254, 255
  11563. creativeness of, 223, 239, 248
  11564. in Descartes's philosophy, 345, 346
  11565. as efficient causality, 277
  11566. inversion of necessity, 236
  11567. and liberation of consciousness, 265, 266.
  11568. _See_ Imprisonment of consciousness
  11569. and novelty, 12, 163, 164, 200, 218, 231, 239, 249, 270, 339-42
  11570. order in, 223
  11571. property of every organism, 129-31
  11572. relaxation of, into necessity, 217
  11573. tendency of, to self-negation in habit, 127
  11574. tension of, 200, 201, 202, 207, 223, 237, 301
  11575. transformed by the understanding into necessity, 270
  11576. _See_ Spontaneity
  11577. Fringe of intelligence around instinct, 136
  11578. of intuition around intellect, xii, xiii, 46
  11579. of possible action around real action, 179, 272
  11580. Froth, alveolar, in imitation of organic phenomena, 33-4
  11581. Full, fallacy of thinking the, by the empty, 273-6
  11582. Function, ix, 3, 5, 44, 46, 47, 88-90, 94, 95, 106-10, 113, 114, 117, 120,
  11583. 121, 127, 132, 140, 141, 145, 152, 153, 157, 161, 163, 164, 168, 173-5,
  11584. 186-92, 199, 206, 207, 233, 237, 246, 251, 254-6, 262, 263, 270, 273,
  11585. 298, 306, 346, 358, 369
  11586. accumulation of energy the function of vegetable organisms, 254, 255
  11587. action the, of intellect, ix, 12, 44, 47, 93, 161, 162, 186-8, 206, 251,
  11588. 273, 305
  11589. action the, of nervous system, 262, 263
  11590. alimentation, 106, 107, 120, 121, 246, 254
  11591. of animals is canalization of energy, 93, 110, 126, 255, 256
  11592. carbon and the, of organisms, 107, 113, 114, 117, 254, 255
  11593. chlorophyllian, 107-9, 114, 117, 246, 254
  11594. concept-making the, of intellect, x, 49
  11595. of consciousness: sketching movements, 207
  11596. construction the, of intellect, 108
  11597. illumination of action, of perception, 5, 206, 307-8
  11598. of intelligence: action, ix, 12, 44, 46, 93, 160, 162, 186-8, 206, 251,
  11599. 273, 307-8
  11600. of intelligence: concept-making, x, 50
  11601. of intelligence: construction, 160, 163, 181-2
  11602. of intelligence: division, 154, 155, 162, 189
  11603. of intelligence: illumination of action by perception, 5, 206, 301
  11604. of intelligence: repetition, 164, 199, 214-6
  11605. of intelligence: retrospection, 47, 237
  11606. of intelligence: connecting same with same, 199, 233, 270
  11607. of intelligence: scanning the rhythm of the universe, 346
  11608. of intelligence: tactualizing all perception, 168
  11609. of intelligence: unification, 152, 154, 357
  11610. of the nervous system: action, 262, 263
  11611. and organ, 88-90, 94, 95, 132-3, 140, 141, 158.
  11612. _See_ Function and structure
  11613. and organ in arthropods, vertebrates and man, 132-3
  11614. of the organism, 94, 106-10, 112, 114, 117, 120, 126, 173-5, 246, 253-6
  11615. of the organism, alimentation, 106, 107, 120, 121, 246, 254
  11616. of the organism, animal: canalization of energy, 93, 110, 126, 255, 256
  11617. of the organism, carbon in, 107, 113, 114, 117, 254, 255
  11618. of the organism, chlorophyllian function, 107-9, 114, 117, 246, 247, 254
  11619. of the organism, primary functions of life: storage and expenditure of
  11620. energy, 254-6
  11621. of the organism, vegetable: accumulation of energy, 254, 255
  11622. of philosophy: adoption of the evolutionary movement of life and
  11623. consciousness, 370
  11624. of science, 168, 346
  11625. sketching movements the, of consciousness, 207
  11626. and structure, 55, 62, 66, 69, 74, 75, 76, 86, 88-91, 93, 94, 96, 118,
  11627. 132, 140, 141, 158, 162, 250, 252, 256
  11628. tactualizing all perception the, of science, 168
  11629. of vegetable organism: accumulation of energy, 254, 255
  11630. Functions of life, the two: storage and expenditure of energy, 254-6
  11631. Galileo, homogeneity of time in, 332
  11632. his influence on metaphysics, 20, 228
  11633. his influence on modern science, 334, 335
  11634. extension of Galileo's physics, 357, 370
  11635. his theory of the fall of bodies compared with Aristotle's, 228, 331,
  11636. 332, 334
  11637. Ganoid breast-plate of ancient fishes, in reference to animal mobility,
  11638. 130, 131
  11639. Gaudry, 130 _note_
  11640. Genera, relation of, to individuals, 226
  11641. relation of, to laws, 225, 226, 330
  11642. potential, 226-7
  11643. and signs, 158
  11644. Generality, ambiguity of the idea of, in philosophy, 229-31, 236
  11645. Generalization dependent on repetition, 230, 231
  11646. distinguished from transference of sign, 158
  11647. in the vital and mathematical orders, 224, 225, 230
  11648. Generic, type of the: similarity of structure between generating and
  11649. generated, 223, 224
  11650. Genesis, xiii, xiv, 153, 186-199, 207, 359, 360
  11651. of intellect, xiii, xiv, 153, 186, 187, 190, 193, 194, 196-7, 207,
  11652. 264, 360
  11653. of knowledge, 191
  11654. of matter, xiii, xiv, 153, 186, 188, 190, 193, 199, 207, 360
  11655. Genius and the willed order, 223, 237
  11656. Genus. _See_ Genera
  11657. Geometrical, the, is the object of the intellect, 190
  11658. Geometrical order as a diminution or lower complication of the vital,
  11659. 223, 225, 236, 330.
  11660. _See_ Genera, Relation of, to laws
  11661. mutual contingency of, and vital order, 235
  11662. _See_ Mathematical order
  11663. space, relation of, to the spatiality of things, 203
  11664. Geometrism, the latent, of intellect, 194, 211-3
  11665. Geometry, fitness of, to matter, 10
  11666. goal of intellectual operations, 211, 213, 218
  11667. ideal limit of induction and deduction, 214-8, 361.
  11668. _See_ Space, Descending movement of existence
  11669. modern, compared with ancient, 36, 161, 333-4
  11670. natural, 194, 211-2
  11671. perception impregnated with, 205, 230
  11672. reasoning in, contrasted with reasoning concerning life, 7, 8
  11673. scientific, 161, 211
  11674. Germ, accidental predisposition of, in Neo-Darwinism, 168, 169, 170
  11675. Germ-plasm, continuity of, 27, 37, 78-83
  11676. Giard, 84
  11677. Glucose in organic function, 122, 123
  11678. Glycogen in organic function, 122-4
  11679. God, as activity, 249
  11680. of Aristotle, 196, 322, 325, 349, 353, 356-7
  11681. ascent toward, in Aristotle's philosophy, 322-3
  11682. circularity of God's thought, in Aristotle's philosophy, 324, 325
  11683. in Descartes's philosophy, 346, 347
  11684. as efficient cause in Aristotle's philosophy, 324
  11685. as hypostasis of the unity of nature, 196, 322, 357
  11686. in Leibniz's philosophy, 352, 353, 356-7
  11687. as eternal matter, 196-7
  11688. as pure form, 196-7, 322
  11689. in Spinoza's philosophy, 351, 357
  11690. Greek philosophy. _See_ Ancient philosophy
  11691. Green parts of plants, 107-9, 114, 117, 246, 247, 254
  11692. Growing old, 15
  11693. Growth, creation is, 240-1, 275
  11694. and novelty, 231
  11695. of the powers of life, 132, 134-5
  11696. reality is, 237
  11697. of the universe, 343, 345
  11698. Guérin, P., 59 _note_
  11699. Guinea-pig, in illustration of hereditary transmission, 80, 81
  11700. Habit and consciousness annulled, 143
  11701. form of knowledge a habit or bent of attention, 148
  11702. and heredity, 78, 93, 169, 170, 173.
  11703. _See_ Acquired characters, inheritance of
  11704. instinct as an intelligent, 173-4
  11705. and invention in animals, 264
  11706. and invention in man, 265
  11707. tendency of freedom to self-negation in, 127-8
  11708. Harmony between instinct and life, and between intelligence and the
  11709. inert, 187, 194-5, 198
  11710. of the organic world is complementarity due to a common original
  11711. impulse 50, 51, 103, 116, 118
  11712. pre-established, 205, 206
  11713. in radical finalism, 127-8.
  11714. _See_ Discord
  11715. Hartog, 60 _note_
  11716. Hatchets, ancient flint, and human intellect, 137
  11717. Heliocentric radius-vector in Kepler's laws, 333-4
  11718. Hereditary transmission, 76-83, 87, 168-9, 170, 173, 225-6, 230
  11719. domestication of animals and, 80-1
  11720. habit and, 79, 83, 169, 170, 173
  11721. Hesitation or choice, consciousness as, 143, 144
  11722. Heteroblastia and identical structures on divergent lines of evolution, 75
  11723. Heymons, 72 _note_
  11724. History as creative evolution, 6, 15, 21, 26, 29, 36, 37, 65-6, 103-4,
  11725. 105, 163, 264, 269
  11726. of philosophy, 238
  11727. Hive as an organism, 166
  11728. _Homo faber_, designation of human species, 139
  11729. Homogeneity of space, 156, 212
  11730. the sphere of intellect, 163
  11731. of time in Galileo, 332
  11732. Horse-fly illustrating the object of instinct, 146
  11733. Houssay, 109 _note_
  11734. Human and animal attention, 184
  11735. and animal brain, 184, 263-5
  11736. and animal consciousness, 139-43, 180, 183, 184, 187, 188, 191,
  11737. 212, 263-8
  11738. and animal instruments of action, 139-43, 150
  11739. and animal intelligence, 138, 187, 188, 191, 192, 212
  11740. and animal invention, relation of, to habit, 264, 265
  11741. intellect and language, 157-8
  11742. intellect and manufacture, 137, 138
  11743. Humanity in evolution, 134, 137-9, 142, 147, 158, 181, 184, 185, 264-71.
  11744. _See_ Culminating points, etc.
  11745. goal of evolution, 266, 267
  11746. Huxley, 38
  11747. Hydra and individuality, 13
  11748. [Greek: Hylê] of Aristotle, 353
  11749. Hymenoptera, the culmination of arthropod and instinctive evolution,
  11750. 134, 173-4
  11751. as entomologists, 146, 172-3
  11752. organization and instinct in, 140
  11753. paralyzing instinct of, 146, 172, 173-4
  11754. social instincts of, 101, 171
  11755. Hypostasis of the unity of nature, God as, 196-7, 322, 356
  11756. Hypothetical propositions characteristic of intellectual knowledge, 149-50
  11757. Idea or form in ancient philosophy, 49, 314, 316-7, 318, 329-30
  11758. in ancient philosophy, [Greek: eidos], 314-5
  11759. in ancient philosophy, Platonic, 48
  11760. and image in Descartes, 280
  11761. Idealism, 232
  11762. Idealists and realists alike assume the possibility of an absence of
  11763. order, 220, 232
  11764. Identical structures in divergent lines of evolution, 55, 60-1, 62, 69,
  11765. 74-7, 86, 119
  11766. Illumination of action the function of perception, 5, 206, 307
  11767. Image and idea in Descartes, 280
  11768. distinguished from concept, 160-1, 280
  11769. Imitation of being in Greek philosophy, 324, 327
  11770. of instinct by science, 168-9, 173-4
  11771. of life in intellectual representation, 4, 33, 88-9, 101, 176, 208,
  11772. 209, 213, 226, 259, 341, 365
  11773. of life by the unorganized, 33, 35, 36
  11774. of motion by intelligence, 305, 307-8, 312, 313, 329.
  11775. _See_ Imitation of the real, etc.
  11776. of the physical order by the vital, 230
  11777. of the real by intelligence, 258, 270, 307
  11778. Immobility of extension, 155
  11779. and plants, 108-13, 118, 119, 130
  11780. of primitive and torpid animals, 130-1
  11781. relative and apparent; mobility real, 155
  11782. Impatience, duration as, 10, 339-40
  11783. Impelling cause, 73
  11784. Impetus, vital, divergence of, 26-7, 51-5, 97-105, 110, 118-9, 126-7,
  11785. 131, 134-6, 257, 258, 266, 270
  11786. vital, limitedness of, 126, 141, 148-9, 254
  11787. vital, loaded with matter, 239
  11788. vital, as necessity for creation, 252, 261
  11789. vital, transmission of, through organisms, 25, 27, 79, 85, 87, 88,
  11790. 230, 231, 250, 251
  11791. vital, _See_ Impulse of life
  11792. Implement, the animal, is natural: the human, artificial, 139-43
  11793. artificial, 137-40, 150-1
  11794. constructing, function of intelligence, 159, 182-3
  11795. life known to intelligence only as, 162
  11796. matter known to intelligence only as, 161, 198
  11797. natural, 141, 145, 150
  11798. organized, 141, 145, 150
  11799. unorganized, 137-9, 141, 150-1
  11800. Implicit knowledge, 148
  11801. Impotence of intellect and perception to grasp life, 176-8
  11802. Imprisonment of consciousness, 180-3, 264-6
  11803. Impulse of life, divergence of, 26, 27, 51-5, 97-105, 110, 118-9,
  11804. 126-7, 131, 134-6, 257, 258, 266, 270
  11805. limitedness of, 126, 141, 148-9, 254
  11806. loaded with matter, 239
  11807. tendency to mobility, 131, 132
  11808. as necessity for creation, 252, 261
  11809. negates itself, 247, 248
  11810. prolonged in evolution, 246
  11811. prolonged in our will, 239
  11812. transmitted through generations of organisms, 25, 26, 79, 85, 87,
  11813. 230, 231
  11814. unity of, 202, 250, 270
  11815. Impulsion and attraction in Greek philosophy, 323-4
  11816. release and unwinding, the three kinds of cause, 73
  11817. given to mind by matter, 202
  11818. Inadequacy of act to representation, consciousness as, 143
  11819. Inadequate and adequate in Spinoza, 353
  11820. Inanition, illustrating primacy of nervous system, 124 _note_
  11821. Incoherence, 236.
  11822. _See_ Absence of order, Chance, Chaos
  11823. in nature, 104
  11824. Incommensurability of free act with conceptual idea, 47, 201
  11825. of instinct and intelligence, 167-8, 175
  11826. Incompatibility of developed tendencies, 104, 168
  11827. Independent variable, time as, 20, 335-6
  11828. Indetermination, 86, 114, 126, 252, 253, 326.
  11829. _See_ Accident in evolution
  11830. Indeterminism in Descartes, 345
  11831. Individual, viewed by intelligence as aggregate of molecules and of
  11832. facts, 250-1
  11833. and division of labor, 140
  11834. in evolutionist biology, 169, 171, 246 _note_
  11835. and genus, 226-9
  11836. mind in philosophy, 191
  11837. aesthetic intuition only attains the, 177
  11838. and society, 260, 265
  11839. transmits the vital impetus, 250, 259, 270
  11840. Individuality never absolute, x, 12, 13, 16, 19, 42, 260
  11841. and age, 15-23, 27, 43
  11842. corporeal, physics tends to deny, 188, 189, 208.
  11843. _See_ Interpenetration, Obliteration of outlines, Solidarity
  11844. of the parts of matter
  11845. and generality, 226-8
  11846. the many and the one in the idea of, x, 258
  11847. as plan of possible influence, 11
  11848. Individuation never absolute, x, 12-16, 43, 260
  11849. as a cosmic principle in contrast with association, 259-60
  11850. property of life, 12-5
  11851. partly the work of matter, 257-8, 259, 270
  11852. Indivisibility of action, 94, 95
  11853. of duration, 6, 308
  11854. of invention, 164
  11855. of life, 225, 270-1.
  11856. _See_ Unity
  11857. of life of motion, 307-11
  11858. Induction in animals, 214
  11859. certainty of, approached as factors approach pure magnitudes, 222, 223
  11860. and duration, 216
  11861. and expectation, 214-6
  11862. geometry the ideal limit of, 214-8, 361.
  11863. _See_ Space, Geometry, Reasoning, "Descending" movement of matter, etc.
  11864. and magnitude, 215, 216
  11865. repetition the characteristic function of intellect, 164, 199, 205-16
  11866. and space, 216.
  11867. _See_ Space as the ideal limit, Systems, etc.
  11868. Industry, ix, 161, 162, 164
  11869. Inert matter and action, 96, 136, 141, 155, 187, 198, 225, 367
  11870. in Aristotle, 316, 327, 353
  11871. bodies, 7, 8, 12, 14, 20, 21, 156, 159, 174, 186, 188, 189, 204, 213,
  11872. 215, 228, 240, 241, 298, 300, 341, 342, 346-8, 360
  11873. Creation of. _See_ Inert matter the inversion of life
  11874. flux of, 186, 265, 273, 369
  11875. and form, 148, 149, 157, 239, 250
  11876. genesis of, 188
  11877. homogeneity of, 156
  11878. imitation of living matter by, 33, 35, 36
  11879. imitation of physical order by vital, 230
  11880. instantaneity of, 10, 201
  11881. and intellect, ix, 31, 141, 159-62, 164, 165, 167-8, 175, 179, 181, 186,
  11882. 187, 195, 196, 197, 198, 205-12, 216-9, 224, 264, 270, 319, 369
  11883. the inversion or interruption of life, 93, 94, 98, 99, 128-9, 153, 177,
  11884. 186, 189, 190, 196, 197, 201, 203, 208, 216-9, 231, 235, 236, 239, 240,
  11885. 245-50, 252, 254, 256, 258, 259, 261, 264, 267, 272, 276, 319,
  11886. 339-40, 343.
  11887. _See_ Inert matter, order inherent in
  11888. knowledge of, approximate but not relative, 206
  11889. the metaphysics and the physics of, 195-6
  11890. as necessity, 252, 264
  11891. the order inherent in, 40, 103, 153, 201, 207-12, 216, 226-7, 230-6,
  11892. 245, 251, 263, 274, 319-20.
  11893. _See_ Inert matter, inversion of life
  11894. penetration of, by life, 25, 26, 51, 179, 181, 237, 239, 266, 270, 271
  11895. and perception, 12, 206, 226
  11896. and the psychical, 201, 202, 205, 269, 270, 350, 367
  11897. solidarity of the parts of, 188, 202, 207, 241, 257-9, 270, 271, 352
  11898. and space, 10, 153, 189, 204-11, 214, 244, 250, 251, 257
  11899. in Spencer's philosophy, 365
  11900. Inertia, 176, 224
  11901. Infant, intelligence in, 147, 148
  11902. Inference a beginning of invention, 138
  11903. Inferiority in evolutionary rank, 174-5
  11904. Influence, possible, 11, 189
  11905. Infusoria, conjugation of, 15
  11906. development of the eye from its stage in, 60-1, 72, 78, 84
  11907. and individuation, 260
  11908. and mechanical explanations, 34, 35
  11909. vegetable function in, 116
  11910. Inheritance of acquired characters. _See_ Hereditary transmission
  11911. Innate knowledge, 146-7, 150-1
  11912. Innateness of the categories, 148, 149-50
  11913. Inorganic matter. _See_ Inert matter
  11914. Insectivorous plants, 107-9
  11915. Insects, 19, 101, 107, 126, 131, 134, 135, 140-1, 146, 147, 157, 166,
  11916. 169, 171-5, 188
  11917. apogee of instinct in hymenoptera, 134, 173-4
  11918. consciousness and instinct, 145, 167, 173
  11919. continuity of instinct with organization, 139, 145
  11920. fallibility of instinct in, 172-3
  11921. instinct in general in, 169, 173-4
  11922. language of ants, 157-8
  11923. object of instinct in, 146
  11924. paralyzing instinct in, 146, 171, 172-3
  11925. social instinct in, 101, 157-8, 171
  11926. special instincts as variations on a theme, 167.
  11927. _See_ Arthropods in evolution
  11928. Insensible variation, 63, 66
  11929. Inspiration of a poem an undivided intuitive act, contrasted with its
  11930. intellectual imitation in words, 209, 210, 258.
  11931. _See_ Sympathy
  11932. Instantaneity of the intellectual view, 31, 70, 84, 89, 199, 201-2, 207,
  11933. 226, 249, 258, 273, 300-6, 311, 314, 331-3, 342, 351, 352
  11934. Instinct and action on inert matter, 136, 141
  11935. in animals as distinguished from plants, 170
  11936. in cells, 166
  11937. and consciousness, 143-5, 166, 167, 173, 174, 175, 186
  11938. culmination of, in evolution, 133, 174-5.
  11939. _See_ Arthropods in evolution, Evolutionary superiority
  11940. fallibility of, 173-4
  11941. in insects in general, 169, 173-4
  11942. and intelligence, xii, 51, 100, 103, 113, 116-8, 132-7, 141-3, 145, 150,
  11943. 152, 159, 168-70, 173-9, 184-5, 186, 197-8, 238, 246, 254, 255, 259,
  11944. 267, 268, 343, 345, 366
  11945. and intuition, 177, 178-9, 181
  11946. object of, 146-52, 165, 168, 172-9, 186, 189, 195, 234, 254
  11947. and organization, 23-4, 138-40, 145, 166-8, 171-2, 173, 176, 193,
  11948. 194, 264
  11949. paralyzing, in certain hymenoptera, 146, 171, 172-3
  11950. in plants, 170, 171
  11951. social, of insects, 101, 157-8, 171
  11952. Instinctive knowledge, 148, 167, 168, 173-4
  11953. learning, 193
  11954. metaphysics, 192, 269, 270, 277
  11955. Instrument, action as, of consciousness, 180
  11956. animal, is natural; human artificial, 139-43
  11957. automatic activity as instrument of voluntary, 252
  11958. consciousness as, of action, 180
  11959. intelligence: the function of intelligence is to construct
  11960. instruments, 159, 192-3
  11961. intelligence transforms life into an, 162
  11962. intelligence transforms matter into an, 161, 198
  11963. intelligence: the instruments of intelligence are artificial, ix, 137-9,
  11964. 140-1, 150-1
  11965. natural or organized instruments of instinct, 140-1, 145, 150
  11966. Intellect and action, ix, 11, 29, 44-8, 93, 136, 142, 152-7, 162, 179,
  11967. 186, 187, 192, 195, 197-8, 219, 220, 226-9, 251, 270, 273, 297-9, 301,
  11968. 302, 306, 329, 346-7
  11969. in animals, 187
  11970. Fichte's conception of the, 189, 190, 357
  11971. function of the, 5, 11, 12, 44-50, 92, 93, 126, 137-45, 149-60, 162-4,
  11972. 168, 174, 176, 181, 187-99, 204-8, 214-9, 229, 233, 237, 241, 242,
  11973. 246, 247, 251, 270, 290, 298, 299, 328, 336, 337, 341, 342, 347,
  11974. 348, 356, 357
  11975. genesis of the, xi-xv, 49, 103, 104-5, 126-7, 152, 153, 186, 187, 189,
  11976. 193, 194, 195, 198, 207, 247-9, 358, 359, 366
  11977. as inversion of intuition, 7, 8, 11, 12, 46, 49, 51, 86, 88-91, 93, 94,
  11978. 103-4, 113, 116-8, 129, 132, 133, 135, 136, 139-43, 145, 157, 161,
  11979. 168-80, 181, 183, 184, 185, 190-204, 207-12, 216-8, 221, 223, 225-6,
  11980. 230-3, 235, 236, 238, 245-52, 254-9, 264, 267-71, 276, 277, 313, 330,
  11981. 339, 342-5, 361, 369
  11982. and language, 4, 148, 158-60, 258, 265, 292, 303, 304, 312, 313, 326
  11983. and matter, ix-xv, 10, 11, 48-9, 92, 135, 136, 141, 142, 152-4, 155,
  11984. 160, 161, 165, 168, 175, 179, 181, 182, 186-7, 190, 193, 194, 195,
  11985. 198, 199, 201-4, 205-10, 213, 215, 218-20, 224, 225-30, 240-2, 245,
  11986. 246, 248-52, 254, 256-9, 264, 270, 271, 272, 273, 275, 297-8, 306,
  11987. 319, 321, 329, 340, 341-3, 347-9, 355, 358-61, 368, 369
  11988. mechanism of the, ix-xv, 4, 30, 32, 47-9, 70, 84-5, 88-9, 101, 137-8,
  11989. 150-5, 156-7, 160, 161, 164, 165, 167, 168, 173, 174, 176, 177,
  11990. 186, 187, 190-3, 194-218, 223-40, 244, 246-7, 249-51, 254, 255, 257,
  11991. 258, 266, 270, 273, 276-7, 292, 300-21, 325, 329, 330, 332, 337, 338,
  11992. 339, 341-8, 351, 358-9, 361-2, 363-4, 365, 367
  11993. object of the, ix-xv, 7, 8, 10, 17, 20, 21, 30, 31, 34, 35, 37, 46-9,
  11994. 52, 71, 74, 84, 87-92, 93, 95, 102, 103, 139, 140, 149, 152-66, 168,
  11995. 173, 175-9, 180, 181, 186, 190, 193-211, 213, 216-20, 223, 224, 226,
  11996. 228-30, 233, 237, 238, 240, 245, 249-51, 254, 255, 257-9, 261, 264,
  11997. 265, 270, 271, 273, 274, 298-314, 318-22, 326, 328, 329, 332-8, 342,
  11998. 344-9, 351, 352-7, 359-61, 363, 365, 369-70
  11999. and perception, 4-5, 11, 12, 93-4, 161-2, 168, 176-7, 188, 189, 205,
  12000. 207, 226-7, 228-9, 230, 238, 249-51, 273, 299-300, 301, 306, 359-60
  12001. and rhythm, 299, 300-1, 306-7, 329, 337, 346-7
  12002. and science, 8-12, 31, 92-3, 152, 153, 157-8, 159, 160-1, 162-3, 168,
  12003. 173-6, 187, 193-8, 202, 204, 207-9, 214-6, 217, 225-6, 228-9, 241,
  12004. 251, 270, 273, 297-8, 306, 321, 322, 329, 333-5, 345, 346-8, 354,
  12005. 356, 357, 359-60, 362-3, 369-70
  12006. and space, 10-11, 154, 156-7, 160-3, 174-5, 176-7, 189, 202-4, 207-12,
  12007. 215, 218, 222-3, 244, 245, 250, 251, 257-8, 361-2
  12008. and time, 4, 8-9, 17, 18, 20-2, 36, 39, 45-6, 47, 51, 163, 300, 301,
  12009. 331-2, 335-7, 341
  12010. possibility of transcending the, xii, xiii, 48, 152, 177-8, 193-4,
  12011. 198-200, 205-6, 207-8, 266, 360-1.
  12012. _See_ Philosophy, Intelligence
  12013. Intellectualism, hesitation of Descartes between, and intuitionism, 345
  12014. Intelligence and action, 137-41, 150, 154-5, 161, 162-3, 181, 189, 198, 306
  12015. animal, 138, 187, 188, 212
  12016. categories of, x, 48, 195-6
  12017. of the child, 147-8
  12018. and consciousness, 187
  12019. culmination of, 130, 139-40, 174-5.
  12020. _See_ Superiority
  12021. genesis of, 136, 177-8, 366
  12022. and the individual, 251
  12023. and instinct, 109, 135, 136, 141, 142, 168-70, 173-7, 179, 186, 197,
  12024. 209, 238, 259, 267
  12025. in Kant's philosophy, 357-8
  12026. and laws, 229-30
  12027. limitations of, 152
  12028. and matter, 152, 159-60, 161-2, 175, 179, 181, 186, 189, 194-8, 230,
  12029. 237, 250, 369, 370
  12030. mechanism of, 152, 153, 164, 165
  12031. and motion, 153, 159-60, 274, 303-7, 312, 313, 329
  12032. object of, 145-56, 161, 162, 175, 179, 250
  12033. practical nature of, ix-xv, 137-9, 141, 150-1, 247-8, 305, 306, 328-9
  12034. and reality, ix-xv, 161-2, 177, 237, 251, 258, 269, 271, 307
  12035. and science, 175, 176, 193, 194-5
  12036. and signs, 157, 158, 159, 160
  12037. and space, 205
  12038. _See_ Intellect, Understanding, Reason
  12039. Intelligent, the, contrasted with the merely intelligible, 175
  12040. Intelligible reality in ancient philosophy, 316-7
  12041. world, 160-1
  12042. Intelligibles of Plotinus, 353
  12043. Intension of knowledge, 149-50
  12044. Intensity of consciousness varies with ratio of possible to real
  12045. action, 144-5
  12046. Intention as contrasted with mechanism, 233.
  12047. _See_ Automatic order, Willed order
  12048. of life the object of instinct, 176, 233
  12049. Interaction, universal, 188-9
  12050. Interest as cause of variation, 131
  12051. in representation of "nought," 296, 297.
  12052. _See_ Affection, rôle of, etc.
  12053. Internal finality, 41
  12054. Internality of instinct, 168, 174-5, 176-7
  12055. of subject in object the condition of knowledge of reality, 307,
  12056. 317, 358-9
  12057. Interpenetration, 161, 162, 174-5, 177, 184 _note_, 188, 189, 201-3,
  12058. 207-8, 257, 258, 270, 319-20, 341, 352
  12059. Interruption, materiality an, of positivity, 219, 246, 247-8, 319-20.
  12060. _See_ Inverse relation, etc.
  12061. Interval of time, 8-9, 22, 23
  12062. between what is done and what might be done covered by consciousness, 179
  12063. Intuition, continuity between sensible and ultra-intellectual, 360-1
  12064. dialectic and, in philosophy, 238.
  12065. _See_ Intellect as inversion of intuition
  12066. fringe of, around the nucleus of intellect, xiii, 12, 46, 49, 193
  12067. and instinct, 176-9, 182
  12068. and intellect in theoretical knowledge, 176-9, 270-1
  12069. Intuitional cosmology as reversed psychology, 207-8
  12070. metaphysics contrasted with intellectual or systematic, 191-2,
  12071. 268-70, 277-8
  12072. method of philosophy, apparent vicious circle of, 191-4, 195-8
  12073. Intuitionism in Spinoza, 347-8
  12074. and intellectualism in Descartes, 345-6
  12075. Invention, consciousness as, and freedom, 264, 270-1
  12076. creativeness of, 164, 237, 340, 341
  12077. disproportion between, and its consequences, 181, 182-3
  12078. duration as, 10-1
  12079. evolution as, 102-3, 255, 344-5
  12080. fervor of, 164
  12081. indivisibility of, 164
  12082. inference a beginning of, 138
  12083. mechanical, 142-3, 194-5
  12084. of steam engine as epoch-marking, 138-9
  12085. time as, 341
  12086. unforeseeableness of, 164
  12087. upspringing of, 164
  12088. _See_ New
  12089. Inverse relation of the physical and psychical, 126-7, 143-4, 145, 173-4,
  12090. 177-8, 201, 202, 206-7, 208, 210-1, 212, 217, 218, 222, 223, 236, 240,
  12091. 245, 246, 247-8, 249, 256, 257, 261, 264, 265, 270, 319-20
  12092. Irreversibility of duration. _See_ Repetition
  12093. Isolated systems of matter, 204, 213, 215, 241, 242, 341, 342, 346, 347-8.
  12094. _See_ Bodies
  12095. Janet, Paul, 60-1 _note_
  12096. Jennings, 35 _note_
  12097. Jourdain and the two kinds of order, 221
  12098. Juxtaposition, 207-8, 338, 339, 341.
  12099. Cf. Succession
  12100. Kaleidoscopic variation, 74
  12101. Kant, antinomies of, 204-5, 206
  12102. becoming in Kant's successors, 362
  12103. coincidence of matter with space in Kant's philosophy, 206, 207-8, 244
  12104. construction the method of Kant's successors, 364-5
  12105. his criticism of pure reason, 205, 287 _note_, 356-62, 364
  12106. degrees of being in Kant's successors, 362-3
  12107. duration in Kant's successors, 362-3
  12108. intelligence in Kant's philosophy, 230, 357
  12109. ontological argument in Kant's philosophy, 285
  12110. space and time in Kant's philosophy, 204-6
  12111. and Spencer, 364
  12112. _See_ Mind and matter, Sensuous manifold, Thing-in-itself
  12113. Kantianism, 358, 364
  12114. Katagenesis, 34
  12115. Kepler, 228-9, 332-5
  12116. Knowledge and action, 150, 193-4, 196, 197, 206-7, 208, 218
  12117. criticism of, 193-4
  12118. discontinuity of, 306
  12119. extension of, 149
  12120. form of, 148, 194-5, 358-362
  12121. formal, 152
  12122. genesis of, 190
  12123. innate or natural, 146-50
  12124. instinct in, 143, 144, 166-9, 173, 177, 192-3, 198, 268
  12125. intellect in, ix-xv, 48, 149, 162-4, 177, 179, 193-4, 196-9, 206-7, 208,
  12126. 218, 237, 238, 251, 270, 305, 306, 312, 313, 315, 317, 325, 331-2,
  12127. 342, 343, 347-8, 359-60, 361
  12128. intension of, 149-50
  12129. of reality viewed as the internality of subject in object, 307,
  12130. 317, 358-9
  12131. intuition and intellect in theoretical knowledge, 174-7, 179, 238,
  12132. 270, 342-4
  12133. matter of, 194-5, 357-8, 359-62
  12134. of matter, xi, 48, 206-7, 360-1
  12135. object of, ix-xv, 1, 48, 147, 148, 159-60, 163, 164, 197-9, 270,
  12136. 342, 359-60
  12137. fundamental problem of, 273-5
  12138. as relative to certain requirements of the mind, 152, 190-1, 230
  12139. scientific, 193-4, 196-8, 206, 207, 218
  12140. theory of, xiii, 177, 179, 197, 204-5, 207-8, 229, 231
  12141. unconscious, 142-6, 146, 150, 165, 166
  12142. alleged unknowableness of the thing-in-itself, 205, 206
  12143. Kunstler, 260 _note_
  12144. Labbé 260 _note_
  12145. Labor, division of, 99, 110, 118, 140, 157, 166, 260
  12146. Lalande, André, 246 _note_
  12147. Lamarck, 75-6
  12148. Lamarckism, 75-6, 77, 84-87
  12149. Language, 4, 147, 157-60, 258, 265, 293, 302-3, 305, 312-4, 320
  12150. La Place, 38
  12151. Lapsed intelligence, instinct as, 169, 175
  12152. Larvae, 19, 140, 145-66, 172-3
  12153. Latent geometrism of intellect, 194, 211-2
  12154. Law of correlation, 66, 67
  12155. and genera, 226-9, 330
  12156. heliocentric radius-vector in Kepler's laws, 334
  12157. imprint of relations and laws upon consciousness in Spencer's
  12158. philosophy, 188
  12159. and intuitional philosophy, 176-7
  12160. physical, contrasted with the laws of our codes, 218-9
  12161. physical, expression of the negative movement, 218
  12162. physical, mathematical form of, 218, 219, 229-30, 241
  12163. relation as, 228, 229-30
  12164. Learning, instinctive, 192, 193
  12165. Le Dantec, 18 _note_
  12166. Leibniz, cause in, 277
  12167. dogmatism of, 356, 357
  12168. extension in, 351, 352
  12169. God in, 351, 352, 356
  12170. mechanism in, 348, 351, 355, 356
  12171. his philosophy a systematization of physics, 347
  12172. space in, 351-2
  12173. teleology in, 39, 40
  12174. time in, 352, 362
  12175. Lepidoptera, 114 _note_, 134
  12176. Le Roy, Ed., 218 _note_
  12177. Liberation of consciousness, 183-4, 265, 266
  12178. Liberty. _See_ Freedom
  12179. Life as activity, 128-9, 246
  12180. cause in the realm of, 94, 164
  12181. complementarity of the powers of, ix-xv, 25-6, 27, 51-5, 97-105, 110,
  12182. 113, 116-9, 126-7, 131-6, 140-3, 176, 177, 183, 184, 246, 254-7, 266,
  12183. 270, 343, 344-5
  12184. consciousness coextensive with, 186, 257, 270, 362-3
  12185. mutual contingency of the orders of life and matter, 235
  12186. continuity of, 1-11, 29, 30, 162, 163, 258
  12187. as creation, 57-8, 161-2, 223, 230, 246, 247-8, 252, 254, 255
  12188. symbolized by a curve, 31, 89, 90
  12189. embryonic, 166
  12190. and finality, 44, 89, 164, 185, 222-3
  12191. fluidity of, 153, 165, 191-2, 193
  12192. as free, 129-30
  12193. function of, 93-4, 106-10, 113, 114, 117, 120, 121, 126-7, 173-5,
  12194. 246, 254-6
  12195. harmony of the realm of, 50, 51, 103, 116, 117-8, 127
  12196. imitation of the inert by, 230
  12197. imitation of, by the inert, 33-6
  12198. impulse of, prolonged in our will, 239
  12199. and individuation, 12-4, 26, 27, 79-80, 85, 87, 88, 127-8, 149, 195-6,
  12200. 230, 231, 250, 259, 261, 269, 300-1, 302-3.
  12201. _See_ Individuality
  12202. indivisibility of, 225-6, 270
  12203. and instinct. 136-40, 145, 165-8, 170, 172, 173, 175-9, 186, 192-7, 233,
  12204. 264, 366
  12205. and intellect, ix-xv, 13, 32-5, 44-9, 89, 101, 102-3, 104-5, 127, 136,
  12206. 152, 160-5, 168, 173-4, 176-9, 181, 191-201, 206, 207, 213, 220,
  12207. 222-3, 224, 225-6, 257-61, 266, 270, 300-1, 342, 355, 359-61, 365, 366
  12208. and interpenetration, 271
  12209. as inversion of the inert, 6-7, 8, 176, 177, 186, 190, 191, 196,
  12210. 197, 201, 202, 207, 208-9, 210-1, 212, 216, 217, 218, 222-3, 225-6,
  12211. 232, 235, 236, 238, 239, 245-50, 264, 329-31
  12212. a limited force, 126, 127, 141, 148, 149, 254
  12213. and memory, 167
  12214. penetrating matter, 26, 27, 52, 179, 181, 182, 237, 239, 266, 269-70
  12215. as tendency to mobility, 128, 131, 132
  12216. and physics and chemistry, 31, 33, 35, 36, 225-6
  12217. in other planets, 256
  12218. as potentiality, 258
  12219. repetition in, and in the inert, 224, 225, 230, 231
  12220. sinuousness of, 71, 98, 99, 102, 112, 113, 116, 129-30, 212
  12221. social, 138, 140, 157-8, 265
  12222. in other solar systems, 256
  12223. and evolution of species, 247-8, 254, 269
  12224. theory of, and theory of knowledge, xii, 177, 179, 197
  12225. unforeseeableness of, 6, 8-9, 20, 26-7, 28, 29, 37, 45-6, 47, 48, 52,
  12226. 86, 96, 163, 164, 184, 223-4, 249, 339, 341
  12227. unity of, 250, 268, 270
  12228. as a wave flowing over matter, 251, 266
  12229. _See_ Impulse of, Organic substance, Organism, Organization,
  12230. Vital impetus, Vital order, Vital principle, Vitalism, Willed order
  12231. Limitations of instinct and of intelligence, 152
  12232. Limitedness of the scope of Galileo's physics, 357, 370
  12233. of the vital impetus, 126, 127, 141, 148, 149, 255
  12234. Linden, Maria von, 114 _note_
  12235. Lingulae illustrating failure to evolve, 102
  12236. Lizards, color variation in, 72, 74
  12237. Locomotion and consciousness, 108, 111, 115, 261.
  12238. _See_ Mobility, Movement
  12239. Logic and action, ix, 44, 46, 162, 179
  12240. formal, 292
  12241. genesis of, x-xi, xiii-xiv, 49, 103, 104-5, 136, 191-2, 193, 301,
  12242. 359, 366
  12243. and geometry, ix, 161, 176, 212
  12244. impotent to grasp life, x, 13, 32, 35, 36, 46-9, 89, 101, 152, 162-5,
  12245. 194-201, 205, 206, 213, 219, 220, 222, 223, 225-6, 256-61, 266, 270,
  12246. 313, 355, 360-1, 365
  12247. natural, 161, 194-5
  12248. of number, 208
  12249. and physics, 319-20, 321
  12250. and time, 4, 277
  12251. _See_ Intellect, Intelligence, Understanding, Order, mathematical
  12252. Logical existence contrasted with psychical and physical, 277, 298,
  12253. 328, 361-2
  12254. categories, x, 48, 195, 196
  12255. and physical contrasted, 276-7
  12256. _Logik_, by Sigwart, 287 _note_
  12257. [Greek: logos], in Plotinus, 210 _note_
  12258. Looking backward, the attitude of intellect, 46, 237
  12259. Lumbriculus, 13
  12260. Machinery and intelligence, 141
  12261. Machines, natural and artificial, 139.
  12262. _See_ Implement, Instrument
  12263. organisms, for action, 252, 254, 300-1
  12264. Magnitude, certainty of induction approached as factors approach pure
  12265. magnitudes, 215-16
  12266. and modern science, 333, 335
  12267. Man in evolution, attention, 184
  12268. brain, 183, 184, 263-5
  12269. consciousness, 139-43, 180, 181, 183, 185, 187, 188, 191-2, 212, 262-8
  12270. goal, 134, 174-5, 185, 266, 267, 269, 270
  12271. habit and invention, 265
  12272. intelligence, 133, 137-9, 143, 146, 174, 175, 187, 188, 212, 266, 267
  12273. language, 158
  12274. Manacéine (de), 124 _note_
  12275. Manufacture, the aim of intellect, 137, 138, 145, 152-4, 159-65, 181, 191,
  12276. 192, 199, 251, 298
  12277. and organization, 92, 93, 126-7, 139-43, 150
  12278. and repetition, 44, 45, 155-8
  12279. _See_ Construction, Solid, Utility
  12280. Many and one, categories inapplicable to life, x, 162-3, 177-8, 257,
  12281. 261, 268
  12282. in the idea of individuality, 258
  12283. _See_ Multiplicity
  12284. Martin, J., 102 _note_
  12285. Marion, 107 _note_
  12286. Material knowledge, 152
  12287. Materialists, 240
  12288. Materiality the inversion of spirituality, 212
  12289. Mathematical order. _See_ Inert matter, Order
  12290. Matter. _See_ Inert matter
  12291. Maturation as creative evolution, 47-8, 230
  12292. Maupas, 35 _note_
  12293. Measurement a human convention, 218, 242
  12294. of real time an illusion, 336-40
  12295. Mechanical account of action after the fact, 47
  12296. cause, x, 34, 35, 40, 44, 177, 234, 235
  12297. procedure of intellect, 165
  12298. invention, 138, 140, 194-5
  12299. necessity, 47, 215, 216, 218, 236, 252, 265, 270, 327
  12300. Mechanics of transformation, 32
  12301. Mechanism, cerebral, 252, 253, 262, 263, 265, 366.
  12302. _See_ Cerebral activity and consciousness
  12303. of the eye, 88
  12304. instinct as, 176-7
  12305. of intellect. _See_ Intellect, mechanism of
  12306. and intention, 233.
  12307. _See_ Automatic order, Willed order
  12308. life more than, x, xiv _note_, 78-9
  12309. Mechanistic philosophy, xii, xiv, 17, 29, 30, 37, 74, 88-96, 101, 102,
  12310. 194-5, 218, 223, 264, 345, 346, 347, 348, 351, 355, 356, 362
  12311. Medical philosophers of the eighteenth century, 356
  12312. science, 165
  12313. Medullary bulb in the development of the nervous system, 252
  12314. and consciousness, 110
  12315. Memory, 5, 17, 20, 21, 167, 168, 180, 181, 201
  12316. Menopause in illustration of crisis of evolution, 19
  12317. Mental life, unity of, 268
  12318. Metamorphoses of larvae, 139-40, 146-7, 166
  12319. Metaphysics and duration, 276
  12320. and epistemology, 177, 179, 185, 197, 208-9
  12321. Galileo's influence on, 20, 238
  12322. instinctive, 191-2, 269, 270, 277-8
  12323. and intellect, 189-90
  12324. and matter, 194
  12325. natural, 21, 325
  12326. and science, 176-7, 194-5, 198, 208-9, 344, 354, 369-70
  12327. systematic, 191, 192, 194, 195-6, 238, 269, 270, 347
  12328. Metchnikoff, 18 _note_
  12329. Method of philosophy, 191-2
  12330. Microbes, illustrating divergence of tendency, 117
  12331. Microbial colonies, 259
  12332. Mind, individual, in philosophy, 191
  12333. and intellect, 48-9, 205-6
  12334. knowledge as relative to certain requirements of the mind, 152,
  12335. 190-1, 230
  12336. and matter, 188-9, 201, 202, 203, 205-6, 264, 269, 270, 350, 365-9
  12337. _See_ Psychic, Psycho-physiological parallelism, Psychology and
  12338. Philosophy, [Greek: psychê]
  12339. Minot, Sedgwick, 17 _note_
  12340. Mobility, tendency toward, characterizes animals, 109, 110, 113, 129-32,
  12341. 135, 180
  12342. and consciousness, 108, 111, 115-6, 261
  12343. and intellect, 154-5, 161-2, 163, 300, 326, 327, 337
  12344. of intelligent signs, 158, 159
  12345. life as tendency toward, 127-8, 131, 132
  12346. in plants, 112, 135
  12347. _See_ Motion
  12348. Möbius, 60 _note_
  12349. Model necessary to the constructive work of intellect, 164, 166-7
  12350. Modern astronomy compared with ancient science, 334, 335
  12351. geometry compared with ancient science, 31, 161, 334
  12352. idealism, 231
  12353. philosophy compared with ancient, 225-9, 231, 327-8, 344, 345,
  12354. 349-51, 354, 356-7
  12355. philosophy: parallelism of body and mind in, 180, 350, 355, 356
  12356. science: cinematographical character of, 329, 330, 336, 341, 342, 346-7
  12357. science compared with ancient, 329-36, 342-5, 356-7
  12358. science, Galileo's influence on, 334, 335
  12359. science, Kepler's influence on, 334
  12360. science, magnitudes the object of, 333, 335
  12361. science, time an independent variable in, 20, 335
  12362. Molecules, 251
  12363. Molluscs, illustrating animal tendency to mobility, 129-31
  12364. perception in, 189
  12365. vision in, 60, 75, 77, 83, 86, 87
  12366. Monads of Leibniz, 351-4
  12367. Monera, 126
  12368. Monism, 355
  12369. Moral sciences, weakness of deduction in, 212
  12370. Morat, 123 _note_
  12371. Morgan, L., 79 _note_, 80
  12372. Motion, abstract, 304
  12373. articulations of, 310-1
  12374. an animal characteristic, 252
  12375. and the cinematograph, 304-5
  12376. continuity of, 310
  12377. in Descartes, 346-7
  12378. evolutionary, extensive and qualitative, 302, 303, 311, 312
  12379. in general (_i.e._ abstract), 304-5
  12380. indivisibility of, 306-7, 311, 336-7, 338
  12381. and instinct, 139-40, 331-2
  12382. and intellect, 71, 155, 156, 159-60, 273, 274, 298, 317-8, 321, 329,
  12383. 331-2, 338, 344-5
  12384. organization of, 310-1
  12385. track laid by motion along its course, 308-11, 337, 338
  12386. _See_ Mobility, Movement
  12387. Motive principle of evolution: consciousness, 181-2
  12388. Motor mechanisms, cerebral, 252, 253, 263, 265
  12389. Moulin-Quignon, quarry of, 137
  12390. Moussu, 81
  12391. Movement and animal life, 108, 131, 132
  12392. ascending, 12, 101, 103, 104, 185, 208-9, 210-1, 369-70.
  12393. _See_ Vital impetus
  12394. consciousness and, 111, 118, 144-5, 207-8
  12395. descending, 11-2, 202-4, 207-10, 212, 246, 252, 256, 270, 276, 339,
  12396. 361, 369-70
  12397. goal of, the object of the intellect, 155, 299-300, 302, 303
  12398. intellect unable to grasp, 313
  12399. mutual inversion of cosmic movements, 126-7, 143, 144, 173-4, 176, 177,
  12400. 209-10, 212, 217, 218, 222-3, 236, 245-51, 261, 264, 265, 272, 342-3
  12401. life as, 166, 176-7
  12402. and the nervous system, 110, 132, 134, 180, 262-3
  12403. of plants, 109, 135-6
  12404. _See_ Mobility, Motion, Locomotion, Current, Tendency, Impetus,
  12405. Impulse, Impulsion
  12406. Movements, antagonistic cosmic, 128-9, 135, 181, 185, 250, 259.
  12407. _See_ Movement, Mutual inversion of cosmic
  12408. Multiplicity, abstract, 257, 259
  12409. distinct, 202, 209-10, 257. _See_ Interpenetration
  12410. does not apply to life, x, 162, 177, 257, 261, 270
  12411. Mutability, exhaustion of, of the universe, 244, 245
  12412. Mutations, sudden, 28, 62-3, 64-8
  12413. theory of, 85-6
  12414. Natural geometry, 195-6, 211-2
  12415. instrument, 141, 144-5, 150-1
  12416. or innate knowledge, 147, 150-1
  12417. logic, 161, 194-5
  12418. metaphysic, 21, 325-6
  12419. selection, 54, 56-7, 59-60, 61-5, 68, 95, 169-70
  12420. Nature, Aristotelian theory of, 135, 174
  12421. discord in, 127-8, 255, 267
  12422. facts and relations in, 368
  12423. incoherence in, 104
  12424. as inert matter, 161-2, 218, 219, 228-9, 239, 245, 264, 280-1, 303,
  12425. 356, 359-60, 367
  12426. as life, 100, 138, 139-40, 141-2, 143, 144-5, 150, 154, 155-6, 227,
  12427. 241, 260, 269, 270, 301-2
  12428. order of, 225-6
  12429. as ordered diversity, 231, 233
  12430. unity of, 105, 190, 191, 195, 196-9, 322, 352-7, 358
  12431. Nebula, cosmic, 249, 257
  12432. Necessity for creation, vital impetus as, 252, 261
  12433. and death of individuals, 246 _note_
  12434. and freedom, 218, 236, 270
  12435. in Greek philosophy, 326-7
  12436. in induction, 215, 216
  12437. and matter, 252, 264
  12438. Negation, 275, 285-97. _See_ Nought
  12439. Negative cause of mathematical order, 217. _See_ Inverse relation, etc.
  12440. cosmic principle, 126-7, 143, 144, 173-4, 176-7, 209, 212, 218, 223-4,
  12441. 236, 245-51, 261, 264-5, 272, 243.
  12442. _See_ Inert matter, Opposition of the two ultimate cosmic movements, etc.
  12443. Neo-Darwinism, 55, 56, 85, 86, 169-70
  12444. Neo-Lamarckism, 42 _note_
  12445. Nervous system a centre of action, 109, 130-1, 132, 134-5, 180, 253, 261-3
  12446. of the plant, 114
  12447. primacy of, 120-1, 126-7, 252
  12448. Neurone and indetermination, 126
  12449. New, freedom and the, 11-2, 164, 165, 199-200, 218, 230, 239, 249,
  12450. 270, 339-42
  12451. Newcomen, 184
  12452. Newton, 335
  12453. Nitrogen and the function of organisms, 108, 113-4, 117, 255
  12454. [Greek: noêseôs noêsis] of Aristotle, 356
  12455. Non-existence. _See_ Nought
  12456. Nothing. _See_ Nought
  12457. Nought, conception of the, 273-80, 281-3, 289-90, 292-8, 316-7, 327.
  12458. _See_ Negation, Pseudo-ideas, etc.
  12459. [Greek: nous poiêtikos] of Aristotle, 322
  12460. Novelty. _See_ new.
  12461. Nucleus intelligence as the luminous, enveloped by instinct, 166-7
  12462. in microbial colonies, 259
  12463. intelligence as the solid, bathed by a mist of instinct, 193, 194
  12464. of Stentor, 260
  12465. Number illustrating degrees of reality, 324-5, 327
  12466. logic of, 208
  12467. Nuptial flight, 146
  12468. Nutritive elements, fixation of, 107-9, 114, 117, 246, 247, 254
  12469. Nymph (Zool.), 139, 146
  12470. Object of this book, ix-xv
  12471. of instinct, 146-52, 163, 175-9
  12472. of intellect, 146-52, 161-5, 175, 179, 190-1, 199-200, 237, 250,
  12473. 252, 270, 273, 298-304, 307-8, 311-2, 354, 359
  12474. internality of subject in, the condition of knowledge of reality,
  12475. 307-8, 317-8, 359
  12476. of knowledge, 147, 148-9, 159-60
  12477. idea of, contrasted with that
  12478. of universal interaction, 11, 188-9, 207-8
  12479. of philosophy as contrasted with object of science, 195-6, 220-1, 225-6,
  12480. 227, 239, 251, 270, 273, 297-9, 305-6, 347
  12481. of science, 329, 332-3, 335-6
  12482. Obliteration of outlines in the real, 11, 188, 189, 207-8
  12483. Oenothera Lamarckiana, 63, 85-6
  12484. Old, growing. _See_ Age
  12485. the, is the object of the intellect, 163, 164, 199, 270
  12486. One and many in the idea of individuality, x, 258. _See_ Unity
  12487. Ontological argument in Kant, 284
  12488. Opposition of the two ultimate cosmic movements, 128-9, 175-6, 179,
  12489. 186, 201, 203, 238, 248, 254, 259, 261, 267.
  12490. _See_ Inverse relation of the physical and psychical
  12491. Orchids, instincts of, 170
  12492. Order and action, 226-7
  12493. complementarity of the two orders, 145-6, 173-4, 221-2.
  12494. _See_ Order, Mutual inversion of the two orders
  12495. mutual contingency of the two orders, 231, 235
  12496. and disorder, 40, 103-4, 220-2, 225-6, 231-6, 274
  12497. mutual inversion of the two orders, 186, 201, 202, 206-9, 211, 212,
  12498. 216-8, 219-21, 222-3, 225-6, 230, 232, 235, 236, 238, 240, 245-8,
  12499. 256, 257, 258, 264, 270, 274, 313, 330
  12500. mathematical, 153, 209-11, 217-9, 223-6, 230-3, 236, 245, 251, 270, 330-1
  12501. of nature, 225-6, 231, 233
  12502. as satisfaction, 222, 223, 274
  12503. vital, 94-5, 164, 222-7, 230, 235, 236, 237, 330-1
  12504. willed, 224, 239
  12505. Organ and function, 88-91, 93-4, 95, 132, 140, 141, 157, 161-2
  12506. Organic destruction and physico-chemistry, 226
  12507. substance, 131, 140, 141-2, 149, 162-3, 195-6, 240 _note_, 255, 267
  12508. world, cleft between, and the inorganic, 190, 191, 196, 197-8
  12509. world, harmony of, 50-1, 103, 104, 116, 118, 126-7
  12510. world, instinct the procedure of, 165
  12511. Organism and action, 123-4, 125, 174, 253, 254, 300-1
  12512. ambiguity of primitive, 99, 112, 113, 116, 129, 130
  12513. association of organisms, 260
  12514. change and the, 301, 302-3
  12515. complementarity of intelligence and instinct in the, 141-2, 150, 181,
  12516. 184, 185
  12517. complexity of the, 162, 250, 252, 253, 260
  12518. consciousness and the, 111, 145, 179, 180, 262, 270
  12519. contingency of the actual chemical nature of the, 255, 257
  12520. differentiation of parts in, 252, 260.
  12521. _See_ Organism, complexity of
  12522. extension of, by artificial instruments, 141, 161
  12523. freedom the property of every, 130, 131
  12524. function of, 26, 27, 79, 80, 85, 87, 88, 93-4, 106-110, 113, 114, 117,
  12525. 120, 121, 126-7, 128, 136, 173-5, 230, 231, 246, 247, 250, 251, 254,
  12526. 255, 256, 258, 270
  12527. function and structure, 55, 61, 62, 69, 74, 75, 76-7, 86, 88-91, 93-4,
  12528. 95, 96-7, 118-9, 132, 139, 140, 157-8, 161-3, 250, 252, 256
  12529. generality typified by similarity among organisms, 223, 224, 228-9, 230
  12530. hive as, 166
  12531. and individuation, x, 12, 13, 15, 23, 26-7, 42, 149, 195-6, 225-6,
  12532. 228-9, 259, 260, 261, 270
  12533. mutual interpenetration of organisms, 177-8
  12534. mechanism of the, 31, 92-3, 94
  12535. philosophy and the, 195-6
  12536. unity of the, 176-8
  12537. Organization of action, 142, 145, 147-8, 150, 181, 184, 185
  12538. of duration, 5-6, 15, 25, 26
  12539. explosive character of, 92
  12540. and instinct, 24, 138-46, 150, 165-7, 171-2, 173, 176, 192-3, 194, 264
  12541. and intellect, 161-2
  12542. and manufacture, 92, 93, 94-5, 96, 126-8
  12543. is the _modus vivendi_ between the antagonistic cosmic
  12544. currents, 181, 250, 254
  12545. of motion, 310
  12546. and perception, 226-7
  12547. Originality of the willed order, 224
  12548. Orthogenesis, 69, 86-7
  12549. Oscillation between association and individuation, 259, 261.
  12550. _See_ Societies
  12551. of ether, 301-2
  12552. of instinct and intelligence about a mean position, 136
  12553. of pendulum, illustrating space and time in ancient philosophy,
  12554. 318-9, 320
  12555. between representation of inner and outer reality, 279-80
  12556. of sensible reality in ancient philosophy about being, 316-8
  12557. Outlines of perception the plan of action, 5, 11, 12, 93, 188, 189, 204-5,
  12558. 206-7, 226-7, 228-9, 230, 250, 299-300, 306
  12559. Oxygen, 114, 254, 255
  12560. Paleontology, 24-5, 129, 139
  12561. Paleozoic era, 102
  12562. Parallelism, psycho-physiological, 180, 350, 351, 355, 356
  12563. Paralyzing instinct in hymenoptera, 139-40, 146, 172, 174-5
  12564. Parasites, 106, 108, 109, 111-13, 134-5
  12565. Parasitism, 132
  12566. Passivity, 222-4
  12567. Past, subsistence of, in present, 4, 20-3, 26-7, 108, 199-202
  12568. Peckham, 173-4 _note_
  12569. Pecten, illustrating identical structures in divergent lines of
  12570. evolution, 62, 63, 75
  12571. Pedagogical and social nature of negation, 287-97
  12572. Pedagogy and the function of the intellect, 165
  12573. Penetration, reciprocal, 161-2.
  12574. _See_ Interpenetration
  12575. Perception and action, 4-5, 11, 12, 93, 188, 189, 206, 226-7, 228-9,
  12576. 300-1, 306-7
  12577. and becoming, 176-7, 303-6
  12578. cinematographical character of, 206-7, 249, 251, 331-2
  12579. distinctness of, 226-7, 250
  12580. and geometry, 205, 230
  12581. in molluscs, 188
  12582. and organization, 226-7
  12583. prolonged in intellect, 161-2, 273
  12584. reaction in, 264
  12585. and recollection, 180, 181
  12586. refracts reality, 204, 238, 359-60
  12587. rhythm of, 299-300, 301
  12588. and science, 168
  12589. Permanence an illusion, 299-301
  12590. Peron, 80
  12591. Perrier, Ed., 260 _note_
  12592. Personality, absolute reality of, 269
  12593. concentration of, 201, 202
  12594. and matter, 269, 270
  12595. the object of intuition, 268
  12596. tension of, 199, 200, 201
  12597. Perthes, Boucher de, 137
  12598. Phaedrus, 156 _note_
  12599. Phagocytes and external finality, 42
  12600. Phagocytosis and growing old, 18
  12601. Phantom ideas and problems, 177, 277, 283, 296
  12602. Philosophical explanation contrasted with scientific explanation, 168
  12603. Philosophy and art, 176-7
  12604. and biology, 43-4, 194-6
  12605. and experience, 197-8
  12606. function of 29-30, 84-5, 93-4, 168, 173-4, 194-7, 198, 268, 269, 369-70
  12607. history of, 238
  12608. incompletely conscious of itself, 207-8, 209
  12609. individual mind in, 191
  12610. and intellect, ix-xv
  12611. intellect and intuition in, 238
  12612. of intuition, 176-7, 191-4, 196, 197, 277
  12613. method of, 191-2, 194, 195, 239
  12614. object of, 239
  12615. and the organism, 195-6
  12616. and physics, 194, 208
  12617. and psychology, 194, 196
  12618. and science, 175, 196-7, 208, 345, 370
  12619. _See_ Ancient philosophy, Cosmology, Finalism, Mechanistic
  12620. philosophy, Metaphysics, Modern philosophy, Post-Kantian philosophy
  12621. Phonograph illustrating "unwinding" cause, 73
  12622. Phosphorescence, consciousness compared to, 262
  12623. Photograph, illustrating the nature of the intellectual view of
  12624. reality, 31, 304-5
  12625. Photography, instantaneous, illustrating the mechanism of the
  12626. intellect, 331-2, 333
  12627. Physical existence, as contrasted with logical, 276, 297-8, 328, 361
  12628. laws, their precise form artificial, 218, 219, 229, 240-1
  12629. laws and the negative cosmic movement, 218
  12630. operations the object of intelligence, 175, 250
  12631. order, imitation of, by the vital, 230
  12632. science, 176-7
  12633. Physicochemistry and organic destruction, 226
  12634. and biology, 25-6, 29-30, 34, 35, 36, 55, 57, 98, 194
  12635. Physics, ancient, "logic spoiled," 320, 321-2
  12636. of ancient philosophy, 315, 320, 321-2, 355
  12637. of Aristotle, 228 _note_, 324 _note_, 331, 332
  12638. and deduction, 213
  12639. of Galileo, 357, 369-70
  12640. and individuality of bodies, 188, 208
  12641. as inverted psychics, 202
  12642. and logic, 319-20, 321
  12643. and metaphysics, 194, 208
  12644. and mutability, 245
  12645. success of, 218, 219
  12646. Pigment-spot and adaptation, 60, 61, 71-3, 76-7
  12647. and heredity, 83, 84
  12648. Pinguicula, certain animal characteristics of, 107
  12649. Plan, motionless, of action the object of intellect, 155, 298-9, 301-2, 303
  12650. Planets, life in other, 256
  12651. Plants and animals in evolution, 105-39, 142-3, 144, 145-6, 147, 168,
  12652. 169-70, 181, 182, 183-4, 185, 254, 267
  12653. complementarity of, to animals, 183-4, 185, 267
  12654. consciousness of, 109, 111, 113, 120, 128-35, 142-3, 144, 181, 182, 292.
  12655. _See_ Torpor, Sleep
  12656. function of, 107-9, 113, 114, 117, 246, 247, 254, 256
  12657. function and structure in, 67, 77-8, 79
  12658. individuation in, 12
  12659. instinct in, 170, 171
  12660. and mobility, 108, 109, 111-13, 118-9, 129, 130, 135-6
  12661. parallelism of evolution with animals, 59-60, 106-8, 116
  12662. supporters of all life, 271
  12663. variation of, 85, 86
  12664. Plasma, continuity of germinative, 25-6, 42, 78-83
  12665. Plastic substances, 255
  12666. Plato, 49, 156, 191, 210 _note_, 316, 318, 319, 320, 321, 327, 330, 347, 349
  12667. Platonic ideas, 49, 315-6, 321, 322, 327, 330, 352
  12668. Plotinus, 210 _note_, 314-5, 323, 324 _note_, 349, 352, 353
  12669. Plurality, confused, of life, 257.
  12670. _See_ Interpenetration
  12671. Poem, sounds of, distinct to perception; the sense indivisible to
  12672. intuition, 209
  12673. illustrating creation of matter, 240, 319-20
  12674. [Greek: poiêtikos, nous], of Aristotle, 322
  12675. Polymorphism of ants, bees, and wasps, 140
  12676. of insect societies, 157
  12677. Polyzoism, 260
  12678. Positive reality, 208, 212. _See_ Reality
  12679. Positivity, materiality an inversion or interruption of, 219, 246,
  12680. 247-8, 319-20
  12681. Possible activity as a factor in consciousness, 11, 12, 96, 144, 145,
  12682. 146-7, 158-9, 165, 179, 180, 181, 189, 264, 368
  12683. existence, 290, 295
  12684. Post-Kantian philosophy, 362, 363
  12685. Potential activity. _See_ Possible activity
  12686. genera, 226
  12687. knowledge, 142-7, 150, 166
  12688. Potentiality, life as an immense, 258, 270
  12689. zone of, surrounding acts, 179, 180, 181, 264. _See_ Possible activity
  12690. Powers of life, complementarity of, xii, xiii, 26, 27, 51-5, 97-105, 110,
  12691. 113, 116-8, 119, 126-7, 131-6, 140-3, 176, 177, 183, 184, 246, 254, 255,
  12692. 257, 266, 270, 343, 345
  12693. Practical nature of perception and its prolongation in intellect and
  12694. science, 137-41, 150, 193-4, 196, 197, 206, 207-8, 218, 247-8, 273,
  12695. 281, 305, 306-7, 328, 329
  12696. Preëstablished harmony, 205-6, 207
  12697. Present, creation of, by past, 5, 20-3, 26-7, 167, 199-202
  12698. Prevision. _See_ Foreseeing
  12699. Primacy of nervous system, 120-6, 252
  12700. Primary instinct, 138-9, 168
  12701. Primitive organisms, ambiguous forms of, 99, 112, 113, 116, 129, 130
  12702. "Procession" in Alexandrian philosophy, 323
  12703. Progress, adaptation and, 101 ff.
  12704. evolutionary, 50, 133, 134, 138, 141-2, 173-4, 175, 185, 264-5, 266
  12705. Prose and verse, illustrating the two kinds of orders, 221, 232
  12706. Protophytes, colonizing of, 259
  12707. Protoplasm, circulation of, 32-3, 108
  12708. and senescence, 18, 19
  12709. imitation of, 32-3, 35
  12710. primitive, and the nervous system, 124, 126-7
  12711. of primitive organisms, 99, 108, 109
  12712. and the vital principle, 42-3
  12713. Protozoa, association of, 259-61
  12714. ageing of, 16
  12715. of ambiguous form, 112
  12716. and individuation, 14, 259-61
  12717. mechanical explanation of movements of, 33
  12718. and nervous system, 126
  12719. reproduction of, 14
  12720. Pseudo-ideas and problems, 177, 277, 283, 296
  12721. Pseudoneuroptera, division of labor among, 140
  12722. [Greek: pschnê] of Aristotle, 350
  12723. of Plotinus, 210 _note_
  12724. Psychic activity, twofold nature of, 136, 140-1, 142-3
  12725. life, continuity of, 1-11, 29-30
  12726. Psychical existence contrasted with logical, 276, 297-8, 327-8, 361
  12727. nature of life, 257
  12728. Psychics inverted physics, 201, 202.
  12729. _See_ Inverse relation of the physical and psychical
  12730. Psychology and deduction, 212-3
  12731. and the genesis of intellect, 187, 194, 195-6, 197
  12732. intuitional cosmology as reversed, 208-9
  12733. Psycho-physiological parallelism, 180, 350, 351, 355, 356
  12734. Puberty, illustrating crises in evolution, 19, 320-1
  12735. Qualitative, evolutionary and extensive becoming, 313
  12736. motion, 302-3, 304, 311
  12737. Qualities, acts, forms, the classes of representation, 303, 314
  12738. bodies as bundles of, 300-1
  12739. coincidence of, 309
  12740. and movements, 299-300
  12741. and natural geometry, 211
  12742. superimposition of, in induction, 216
  12743. Quality is change, 299-300
  12744. in Eleatic philosophy, 314-5
  12745. and quantity in ancient philosophy, 323-4
  12746. and quantity in modern philosophy, 350
  12747. and rhythm, 300-2
  12748. Quaternary substances, 121
  12749. Quinton, René, 134 _note_
  12750. Radius-vector, Heliocentric, in Kepler's laws, 334
  12751. Rank, evolutionary, 50, 133-5, 173-4, 265
  12752. Reaction, rôle of, in perception, 226-7
  12753. Ready-made categories, x, xiv, 48, 237, 250, 251, 273, 311, 321,
  12754. 329, 354, 359
  12755. Real activity as distinguished from possible, 145
  12756. common-sense is continuous experience of the, 213
  12757. continuity of the, 302, 329
  12758. dichotomy of the, in modern philosophy, 349
  12759. imitation of the, by intelligence, 90, 204, 258, 270, 307, 355
  12760. obliteration of outlines in the, 11-2, 188, 189, 207-8
  12761. representation of the, by science, 203-4
  12762. Realism, ancient, 231-2
  12763. Realists and idealists alike assume possibility of absence of order,
  12764. 220, 231-2
  12765. Reality, absolute, 198, 228-9, 230, 269, 359-60, 361
  12766. as action, 47, 191-2, 194-5, 249
  12767. degrees of, 323, 327
  12768. in dogmatic metaphysics, 196
  12769. double form of, 179-80, 216, 230-1, 236
  12770. as duration, 11-2, 217, 272
  12771. as flux, 165, 250, 251, 294, 337, 338, 342
  12772. and the frames of the intellect, 363-4, 365.
  12773. _See_ Frames of the understanding
  12774. as freedom, 247
  12775. of genera in ancient philosophy, 226-7
  12776. is growth, 239
  12777. imitation of, by the intellect, 89-90, 365
  12778. and the intellect, 52, 89-90, 153, 191, 192, 314-5, 355-6
  12779. intelligible, in ancient philosophy, 317
  12780. knowledge of, 307-8, 317, 358-9
  12781. and mechanism, 351, 354-5
  12782. as movement, 90, 155, 301-2, 312
  12783. and not-being, 276, 280, 285
  12784. of the person, 269
  12785. refraction of, through the forms of perception, 204, 238, 359-60
  12786. and science, 194, 196, 198, 199, 203-4, 206-8, 354, 357
  12787. sensible, in ancient philosophy, 314, 317, 321, 327, 328, 352
  12788. symbol of, xi, 30-1, 71, 88-9, 93-4, 195-6, 197, 209, 240, 342,
  12789. 360-1, 369
  12790. undefinable conceptually, 13, 49
  12791. unknowable in Kant, 205
  12792. unknowable in Spencer, xi
  12793. views of, 30-1, 71, 84, 88, 199, 201, 206-7, 225-6, 249, 258, 273,
  12794. 300-7, 311, 314, 331-2, 342, 351, 352
  12795. Reason and life, 7, 8, 48, 161
  12796. cannot transcend itself, 193-4
  12797. Reasoning and acting, 192-3
  12798. and experience, 203-4
  12799. and matter, 204-5, 208-9
  12800. on matter and life, 7, 8
  12801. Recollection, dependence of, on special circumstances, 167, 180
  12802. in the dream, 202, 207-8
  12803. and perception, 180, 181
  12804. Recommencing, continual, of the present in the state of relaxation, 201
  12805. Recomposing, decomposing and, the characteristic powers of intellect,
  12806. 157, 251
  12807. Record, false comparison of memory with, 5
  12808. Reflection, 158-9
  12809. Reflex activity, 110
  12810. compound, 173-4, 175-6
  12811. Refraction of the idea through matter or non-being, 316-7
  12812. of reality through forms of perception, 204, 238, 359-60
  12813. Regeneration and individuality, 13, 14
  12814. Register of time, 16, 20, 37
  12815. Reinke, 42 _note_
  12816. Relation, imprint of relations and laws upon consciousness, 188
  12817. as law, 229, 230-1
  12818. and thing, 147-52, 156-7, 160, 161, 187, 202, 352, 357
  12819. Relativism, epistemological, 196, 197, 230
  12820. Relativity of immobility, 155
  12821. of the intellect, xi, 48-9, 152, 153, 187, 195-6, 197-8, 199, 219,
  12822. 273, 306-7, 360-1
  12823. of knowledge, 152, 191, 230
  12824. of perception, 226-7, 228, 300-1
  12825. Relaxation in the dream state, 201, 209-10
  12826. and extension, 201, 207-8, 209, 210, 212, 218, 223, 245
  12827. and intellect, 200, 207-8, 209, 212, 218
  12828. logic a, of virtual geometry, 212
  12829. matter a, of unextended into extended, 218
  12830. memory vanishes in complete, 200
  12831. necessity as, of freedom, 218
  12832. present continually recommences in the state of relaxation, 200
  12833. will vanishes in complete, 200, 207-8
  12834. _See_ Tension
  12835. Releasing cause, 73, 74, 115, 118-9, 120
  12836. Repetition and generalization, 230-1, 232
  12837. and fabrication, 44-5, 46, 155-8
  12838. and intellect, 156-7, 199, 214-6
  12839. of states, 5-6, 7-8, 28-9, 30, 36, 45-6, 47
  12840. in the vital and in the mathematical order, 225, 226, 230, 231
  12841. Representation and action, 143-4, 145, 180
  12842. classes of: qualities, forms, acts, 302-3, 314
  12843. and consciousness, 143-4
  12844. of motion, 159-60, 303-4, 305, 306-7, 308, 313, 315, 344-5
  12845. of the Nought, 273-80, 281-4, 289-317, 327
  12846. Represented or internalized action distinguished from externalized
  12847. action, 144-7, 158-9, 165
  12848. Reproduction and individuation, 13, 14
  12849. Resemblance. _See_ Similarity
  12850. Reservoir, organism a, of energy, 115, 116, 125-6, 245, 246, 254
  12851. Rest and motion in Zeno, 308-12
  12852. Retrogression in evolution, 133, 134
  12853. Retrospection the function of intellect, 47-8, 237
  12854. Reversed psychology: intuitional cosmology, 208
  12855. Rhizocephala and animal mobility, 111
  12856. Rhumbler, 34 _note_
  12857. Rhythm of duration, 11-2, 127-8, 300-1, 345-7
  12858. intelligence adopts the, of action, 305-6
  12859. of perception, 299-300, 301
  12860. and quality, 301
  12861. scanning the, of the universe the function of science, 346-7
  12862. of science must coincide with that of action, 320
  12863. of the universe untranslatable into scientific formulae, 337
  12864. Rings of arthropods, 132-3
  12865. Ripening, creative evolution as, 47-8, 340-1
  12866. Romanes, 139
  12867. Roule, 27 _note_
  12868. Roy (Le), Ed., 218 _note_
  12869. _Salamandra maculata_, vision in, 75
  12870. Salensky, 75 _note_
  12871. Same, function of intellect connecting same with same, 199-200, 233, 270
  12872. Samter and Heymons, 72 _note_
  12873. Saporta (De), 112 _note_
  12874. Savage's sense of distance and direction, 212
  12875. Skepticism or dogmatism the dilemma of any systematic metaphysics,
  12876. 195-6, 197, 230-1
  12877. Schisms in the primitive impulsion of life, 254-5, 257.
  12878. _See_ Divergent lines of evolution
  12879. Scholasticism, 370
  12880. Science and action, 93, 195, 198, 328-9
  12881. ancient, and modern, 329-37, 342-5, 357
  12882. astronomy, ancient and modern, 334-5, 336
  12883. cartesian geometry and ancient geometry, 333-4
  12884. cinematographical character of modern, 329, 330, 336-7, 340-1, 342, 345-8
  12885. conventionality of a certain aspect of, 206-7
  12886. and deduction, 212-3
  12887. and discontinuity, 161-2
  12888. function of, 92, 167-8, 173-4, 176-7, 193-4, 195-6, 198-9, 328-9, 346-7
  12889. Galileo's influence on modern, 333-4, 335
  12890. and instinct, 169, 170, 173-4, 175, 193-5
  12891. and intelligence, 176, 177, 193-6
  12892. Kepler's influence on modern, 334
  12893. and matter, 194-5, 206-7, 208
  12894. modern. _See_ Modern science
  12895. object of, 195-6, 220, 221, 251, 270-1, 273, 296-8, 306-7, 328-9,
  12896. 332-3, 335-6, 347-8
  12897. and perception, 168
  12898. and philosophy, 175-6, 196-7, 208-9, 344, 370
  12899. physical. _See_ Physics and reality. _See_ Reality and science
  12900. and time, 8-13, 20, 335-8
  12901. unity of, 195-6, 197, 228-9, 230, 321-2, 323, 344-5, 347-8, 349, 354,
  12902. 355-6, 359-60, 362-3
  12903. Scientific concepts, 338-40
  12904. explanation and philosophical explanation, 168
  12905. formulae, 337
  12906. geometry, 161, 211
  12907. knowledge, 193-4, 196-7, 198, 199, 207, 208, 218
  12908. Sclerosis and ageing, 19
  12909. Scolia, paralyzing instinct in, 172
  12910. Scope of action indefinitely extended by intelligent instruments, 141
  12911. of Galileo's physics, 357, 370
  12912. Scott, 63 _note_
  12913. Sea-urchin and individuality, 13
  12914. Séailles, 29 _note_
  12915. Secondary instincts, 139, 168
  12916. Sectioning of becoming in the philosophy of ideas, 317-8
  12917. of matter by perception, 206-7, 249, 251
  12918. Sedgwick, 260 _note_
  12919. Seeing and willing, coincidence of, in intuition, 237
  12920. Selection, natural, 54, 56-7, 59-60, 61-2, 63, 64, 68, 95-6, 169, 170
  12921. Self, coincidence of, with, 199
  12922. existence of, means change, 1 ff.
  12923. knowledge of, 1 ff.
  12924. Senescence, 15-23, 26-7, 42-3
  12925. Sensation and space, 202
  12926. Sense-perception. _See_ Perception
  12927. Sensible flux, 316-7, 318, 321, 322, 327, 343, 345
  12928. intuition and ultra-intellectual, 360-1
  12929. object, apogee of, 342-3, 344-5, 349
  12930. reality, 314, 317, 319, 327, 328, 352
  12931. Sensibility, forms of, 361
  12932. Sensitive plant, in illustration of mobility in plants, 109
  12933. Sensori-motor system. _See_ Nervous system
  12934. Sensuous manifold, 205, 221, 232, 235, 236
  12935. Sentiment, poetic, in illustration of individuation, 258, 259
  12936. Serkovski, 259 _note_
  12937. Serpula, in illustration of identical evolution in divergent lines, 96
  12938. Sexual cells, 14, 26, 27, 79-81
  12939. Sexuality parallel in plants and animals, 58-60, 119-21
  12940. Shaler, N.S., 133 _note_, 184 _note_
  12941. Sheath, calcareous, in illustration of animal tendency to mobility, 130-1
  12942. Signs, function of, 158, 159, 160
  12943. the instrument of science, 329-30
  12944. Sigwart, 287 _note_
  12945. Silurian epoch, failure of certain species to evolve since, 102
  12946. Similarity among individuals of same species the type of generality,
  12947. 224-6, 228-9, 230-1
  12948. and mechanical causality, 44, 45
  12949. Simultaneity, to measure time is merely to count simultaneities, 9,
  12950. 336, 337, 341
  12951. Sinuousness of evolution, 71, 98, 102, 212-3
  12952. Sitaris, unconscious knowledge of, 146, 147
  12953. Situation and magnitude, problems of, 211
  12954. Sketching movements, function of consciousness, 207-8
  12955. Sleep, 129-31, 135, 181
  12956. Snapshot, in illustration of intellectual representation of motion,
  12957. 305, 306, 313, 315, 344
  12958. _See_ View of reality, Cinematographical character, etc.
  12959. form defined as a, of transition, 301-2, 317, 318, 321-2, 345
  12960. Social instinct, 101, 140, 158, 171-2
  12961. life, 138, 140, 158, 265
  12962. and pedagogical character of negation, 287-97
  12963. Societies, 101, 131-2, 158, 171-2, 259
  12964. Society and the individual, 260, 265
  12965. Solar energy stored by plants, released by animals, 246, 254
  12966. systems, 241-4, 246 _note_, 256, 270
  12967. systems, life in other, 256
  12968. Solid, concepts analogous to solids, ix
  12969. intellect as a solid nucleus, 193, 194
  12970. the material of construction and the object of the intellect, 153,
  12971. 154, 161, 162, 251
  12972. Solidarity between brain and consciousness, 180, 262
  12973. of the parts of matter, 203, 207-8, 241, 271
  12974. Solidification operated by the understanding, 249
  12975. [Greek: sôma] in Aristotle, 350
  12976. Somnambulism and consciousness, 144, 145, 159
  12977. Soul and body, 350
  12978. and cell, 269
  12979. creation of, 270
  12980. Space and action, 203
  12981. in ancient philosophy, 318, 319
  12982. and concepts, 160-1, 163, 174-5, 176-7, 188-9, 257-9
  12983. geometrical, 203
  12984. homogeneity of, 156, 212
  12985. and induction, 216
  12986. in Kant's philosophy, 205, 206, 207, 244
  12987. in Leibniz's philosophy, 351
  12988. and matter, 189, 202-13, 244, 257, 264, 361-2, 368
  12989. and time in Kant's philosophy, 205-6
  12990. unity and multiplicity determinations of, 357-9
  12991. _See_ Extension
  12992. Spatiality atmosphere of, bathing intelligence, 205
  12993. degradation of the extra-spatial, 207
  12994. and distinctness, 203, 207, 244, 250, 257-9
  12995. and geometrical space, 203, 211, 213, 218
  12996. and mathematical order, 208, 209
  12997. Special instincts and environment, 138, 168, 192-3, 194
  12998. and recollections, 167, 168, 180
  12999. as variations on a theme, 167, 172, 264
  13000. Species, articulate, 133
  13001. evolution of, 247, 255, 269
  13002. and external finality, 128-9, 130-1, 132, 266
  13003. fossil, 102
  13004. human, as goal of evolution, 266, 267
  13005. human, styled _homo faber_, 139
  13006. and instinct, 140, 167, 170-2, 264
  13007. and life, 167
  13008. similarity within, 223-6, 228-9, 230-1
  13009. Speculation, dead-locks in, xii, 155, 156, 312, 313-4
  13010. object of philosophy, 44, 152, 196, 198, 220, 225-6, 227, 251, 270-1,
  13011. 273, 297-8, 306-7, 317, 347-8
  13012. Spencer, Herbert, xi, xiv, 78-9, 153, 188, 189, 190, 364, 365
  13013. Spencer's evolutionism, correspondence between mind and matter in, 368
  13014. cosmogony in, 188
  13015. imprint of relations and laws upon consciousness in, 188
  13016. matter in, 365, 367
  13017. mind in, 365, 367
  13018. Spheres, concentric, in Aristotle's philosophy, 328
  13019. Sphex, paralyzing instinct in, 172-5
  13020. Spiders and paralyzing hymenoptera, 172
  13021. Spinal cord, 110
  13022. Spinoza, the adequate and the inadequate, 353
  13023. cause, 277
  13024. dogmatism, 356, 357
  13025. eternity, 353
  13026. extension, 350
  13027. God, 351, 357
  13028. intuitionism, 347
  13029. mechanism, 348, 352, 355, 356
  13030. time, 362
  13031. Spirit, 251, 269, 270
  13032. Spirituality and materiality, 128-9, 201-3, 316-7, 208-9, 210-1, 212-3,
  13033. 217, 218, 219, 222-3, 237, 238, 245, 247-8, 249, 251, 254, 256, 257,
  13034. 259, 261, 267, 270-1, 272, 276, 343
  13035. Spontaneity of life, 86, 237. _See_ Freedom
  13036. and mechanism, 40
  13037. in vegetables, 109
  13038. and the willed order, 224
  13039. Sport (biol.), 63
  13040. Starch, in the function of vegetable kingdom, 114
  13041. States of becoming, 1, 13, 163, 247-8, 299, 300, 307
  13042. Static character of the intellect, 155-6, 163, 274, 298
  13043. views of becoming, 273
  13044. Stehasny, 124 _note_
  13045. Steam-engine and bronze, parallel as epoch-marking, 138-9
  13046. Stentor and individuality, 260
  13047. Stoics, 316
  13048. Storing of solar energy by plants, 246, 253-6
  13049. Strain of bow and indivisibility of motion, 308
  13050. Stream, duration as a, 39, 338
  13051. Structure and function. _See_ Function and structure
  13052. identical, in divergent lines of evolution, 55, 60, 61-2, 63, 69, 73-4,
  13053. 75, 76-7, 83, 86, 87, 118-9
  13054. Subject and attribute, 147-8
  13055. Substance, albuminoid, 120-1
  13056. continuity of living, 162
  13057. organic, 121, 131, 140, 142, 149, 162-3, 195-7 _note_, 255, 267
  13058. in Spinoza's philosophy, 350
  13059. ternary substances, 121
  13060. Substantives, adjectives, verbs, correspond to the three classes of
  13061. representation, 302-4
  13062. Substitution essential to representation of the Nought, 281, 283-4,
  13063. 289-90, 291, 294, 296
  13064. Success of physics, 218, 219-20
  13065. and superiority, 133, 264-5
  13066. Succession in time, 10, 339, 340, 341, 345. Cf. Juxtaposition
  13067. Successors of Kant, 363, 364
  13068. Sudden mutations, 28, 62-3, 64-5, 68-9
  13069. Sun, 115, 241, 323
  13070. Superaddition of existence upon nothingness, 276
  13071. of order upon disorder, 236, 275
  13072. Superimposition. _See_ Measurement of qualities, in induction, 216
  13073. Superiority, evolutionary, 133-5, 173, 174-5
  13074. Superman, 267
  13075. Supraconsciousness, 261
  13076. Survival of the fit, 169.
  13077. _See_ Natural selection
  13078. Swim, learning to, as instinctive learning, 193, 194
  13079. Symbol, the concept is a, 161, 209, 341-2
  13080. of reality, xi, 30-1, 71, 88-9, 93, 195-6, 210, 240, 342, 360-1, 369-70
  13081. Symbolic knowledge of life, 199, 342, 360
  13082. Symbolism, 176, 180, 360
  13083. Sympathetic or intuitive knowledge, 209, 210, 342
  13084. Sympathy, instinct is, 164, 168, 172-8, 342-3.
  13085. _See_ Divination, Feeling, Inspiration
  13086. Systematic metaphysics, dilemma of, 195, 196, 230-1
  13087. contrasted with intuitional, 191-2, 193-4, 238, 269, 270, 277, 346-8
  13088. postulate of, 190, 195
  13089. Systematization of physics, Liebniz's philosophy, 347
  13090. Systems, isolated, 9-13, 203, 214, 215, 241, 242, 342, 347-9
  13091. Tangent and curve, analogy with deduction and the moral sphere, 214
  13092. analogy with physico-chemistry and life, 31
  13093. Tarakevitch, 124 _note_
  13094. Teleology. _See_ Finalism
  13095. Tendency, antagonistic tendencies of life, 13, 98, 103, 113, 135, 150
  13096. antagonistic tendencies in development of nervous system, 124-5
  13097. complementary tendencies of life, 51, 103, 135, 150, 168, 246
  13098. to dissociation, 260
  13099. divergent tendencies of life, 54, 89, 99, 101, 107-8, 109-10, 112,
  13100. 116-8, 134, 135, 150, 181, 246, 254-8
  13101. to individuation, 13
  13102. life a tendency to act on inert matter, 96
  13103. toward mobility in animals, 109, 110, 113, 127-8, 129-33, 135, 181, 182
  13104. the past exists in present tendency, 5
  13105. to reproduce, 13
  13106. of species to change, 85-86
  13107. mathematical symbols of tendencies, 22, 23
  13108. toward systems, in matter, 10
  13109. transmission of, 80-1
  13110. a vital property is a, 13
  13111. Tension and extension, 236, 245
  13112. and freedom, 200-2, 207-8, 223, 237, 239, 300-2
  13113. matter the inversion of vital, 239
  13114. of personality, 199-200, 201, 207-8, 237, 239, 300
  13115. Ternary substances, 121
  13116. Theology consequent upon philosophy of ideas, 316
  13117. Theoretic fallacies, 263, 264
  13118. knowledge and instinct, 177, 268
  13119. knowledge and intellect, 155, 177, 179, 238, 270, 342, 343
  13120. Theorizing not the original function of the intellect, 154-5
  13121. Theory of knowledge, xiii, 178, 180, 184-5, 197, 204, 207-8, 209,
  13122. 228-9, 231
  13123. of life, xiii, 178, 180, 197
  13124. Thermodynamics, 241-2.
  13125. _See_ Conservation of energy, Degradation of energy
  13126. Thesis and antithesis, 205
  13127. Thing as distinguished from motion, 187, 202, 247-8, 249, 299-300
  13128. as distinguished from relation, 147, 148, 150, 152, 158-9, 159-60,
  13129. 161, 187, 202, 352, 356-7
  13130. and mind, 206
  13131. as solidification operated by understanding, 249
  13132. Thing-in-itself, 205, 206, 230-1, 312
  13133. Timaeus, 318 _note_
  13134. Time and the absolute, 240, 241, 297-8, 339, 343-4
  13135. abstract, 21, 22, 37, 39
  13136. articulations of real, 331-3
  13137. as force, 16, 45-6, 47, 51, 103, 339
  13138. homogeneous, 17, 18, 163-4, 331-3
  13139. as independent variable, 20, 335-7
  13140. interval of, 9, 22, 23
  13141. as invention, 341-2
  13142. in Leibniz's philosophy, 351, 352, 362
  13143. and logic, 4, 277
  13144. and simultaneity, 9, 336, 337, 341
  13145. in modern science 321-37, 341-5
  13146. and space in Kant, 205
  13147. and space in ancient philosophy, 318, 319.
  13148. _See_ Duration
  13149. Tools and intellect, 137-41, 150-1.
  13150. _See_ Implement
  13151. Torpor, in evolution, 109, 111, 113, 114 _note_, 120, 128-35, 181, 292
  13152. Tortoise, Achilles and the, in Zeno, 311
  13153. Touch, science expresses all perception as touch, 168
  13154. is to vision as intelligence to instinct, 169
  13155. Track laid by motion along its course, 309-12, 337
  13156. Transcendental Aesthetic, 203
  13157. Transformation, 32, 72, 73, 131, 231, 263
  13158. Transformism, 23-5
  13159. Transition, form a snapshot view of, 301-2, 316-7, 318, 321, 344-5
  13160. Transmissibility of acquired characters, 75-84, 87, 168, 169, 172-3,
  13161. 225-6, 230-1
  13162. Transmission of the vital impetus, 26, 27, 79, 85, 87, 88, 93-4, 110,
  13163. 126-7, 128, 230, 231, 246, 255, 256, 257, 259, 270
  13164. Trigger-action of motor mechanisms, 272
  13165. Triton, Regeneration in, 75
  13166. Tropism and psychical activity, 35 _note_
  13167. Truth seized in intuition, 318-20
  13168. Unconscious effort, 170
  13169. instinct, 142-3, 144, 145-6, 147, 166
  13170. knowledge, 145-8, 150-1
  13171. Unconsciousness, two kinds of, 144
  13172. Undefinable, reality, 13, 48
  13173. Understanding, absoluteness of, 153-4, 190-1, 197-8, 199, 200
  13174. and action, ix, xi, 179
  13175. genesis of the, ix-xv, 49, 189, 207-8, 257-9, 359, 361-2
  13176. and geometry, ix, xii
  13177. and innateness of categories, 147, 148-9
  13178. and intuition, 46-7
  13179. and life, ix-xv, 13, 32-3, 46-50, 88-9, 101, 147-8, 149, 152, 162-5,
  13180. 173-4, 176-7, 178, 195-201, 213, 220, 222-3, 224, 226, 257-9, 261,
  13181. 266, 270, 271, 313, 361-2, 365
  13182. and inert matter, 166, 168, 179, 194-5, 198, 205-6, 207, 219, 355
  13183. and the ready-made, xiii, 48, 237, 250, 251, 273, 311, 321, 328-9,
  13184. 354, 358
  13185. and the solid, ix
  13186. unlimited scope of the, 149, 150, 152
  13187. _See_ Intellect, Intelligence, Concept, Categories, Frames
  13188. of the understanding, Logic
  13189. Undone, automatic and determinate evolution is action being, 249
  13190. Unfolding cause, 73, 74
  13191. Unforeseeableness of action, 47
  13192. of duration, 6, 164, 340-2
  13193. of evolution, 47, 48, 52, 86, 224
  13194. of invention, 164
  13195. of life, 164, 184
  13196. and the willed order, 224, 342-3
  13197. _See_ Foreseeing
  13198. Unification as the function of the intellect, 152, 154, 357-8
  13199. Uniqueness of phases of duration, 164
  13200. Unity of extension, 154
  13201. of knowledge, 195-6
  13202. of life, 106-7, 250, 268, 271
  13203. of mental life, 268
  13204. and multiplicity as determinations of space, 351-3
  13205. of nature, 104-5, 189-90, 191, 195-6, 197, 199, 322, 352, 356-8
  13206. of the organism, 176-7
  13207. of science, 195-6, 197, 228-9, 230, 321, 322, 344-5, 347, 359-60, 362-3
  13208. Universal interaction, 188, 189
  13209. life, consciousness coextensive with, 186, 257, 270
  13210. Universe, continuity of, 346
  13211. Descartes's, 346
  13212. physical, and the idea of disorder, 233, 275
  13213. duration of, 10, 11, 241
  13214. evolution of, 241, 246 _note_
  13215. growth of, 342-3, 344
  13216. movement of, in Aristotle, 323
  13217. mutability of, 244, 245
  13218. as organism, 31, 241
  13219. as realization of plan, 40
  13220. rhythm of, 337, 339, 346-7
  13221. states of, considered by science, 336, 337
  13222. as unification of physics, 348-9, 357
  13223. Unknowable, the, of evolutionism, xi
  13224. the, in Kant, 204, 205, 206
  13225. Unmaking, the nature of the process of materiality, 245, 248, 249,
  13226. 251, 272, 342-3
  13227. Unorganized bodies, 7-8, 14, 20, 21, 186.
  13228. _See_ inert matter
  13229. instruments, 137-9, 140-1, 150-1
  13230. matter, cleft between, and the organized, 190, 191, 196, 197-9
  13231. matter, imitation of the organized by, 33-4, 35, 36
  13232. matter and science, 194-6
  13233. matter. _See_ inert matter
  13234. Unwinding cause, 73
  13235. of immutability in Greek philosophy, 325, 352
  13236. Upspringing of invention, 164
  13237. Utility, 4-5, 150, 152, 154-5, 158-9, 160, 168, 187, 195-6, 247-8,
  13238. 297-8, 328-9, 330
  13239. _Vanessa levana_ and _Vanessa prorsa_, transformation of, 72
  13240. Variable, time as an independent, 20, 336
  13241. Variation, accidental, 55, 63-4, 68, 85, 168-9
  13242. of color, in lizards, 72, 74
  13243. by deviation, 82-3, 84
  13244. of evolutionary type, 23-4, 72 _note_, 131-2, 137-8, 167, 169, 171-2, 264
  13245. insensible, 63, 68
  13246. interest as cause of, 131-2
  13247. in plants, 85-86
  13248. Vegetable kingdom. _See_ Plants
  13249. Verb, relation expressed by, 148
  13250. Verbs, substantives and adjectives, 303
  13251. Verse and prose, in illustration of the two kinds of order, 221, 232
  13252. Vertebrate, ix, 126, 130, 131-4, 141
  13253. Vibrations, matter analyzed into elementary, 201
  13254. Vicious circle, apparent, of intuitionism, 192-4, 196-7
  13255. of intellectualism, 194, 197, 318-9, 320
  13256. View, intellectual, of becoming, 4, 90-1, 273, 298-9, 304, 305, 310, 326-7
  13257. intellectual, of matter, 203, 240, 250, 254, 255
  13258. of reality, 206
  13259. Vignon, P., 35 _note_
  13260. Virtual actions, 12.
  13261. _See_ Possible action
  13262. geometry, 212
  13263. Vise, consciousness compressed in a, 179
  13264. Vision of God, in Alexandrian philosophy, 322
  13265. in molluscs. See Eye of molluscs, etc.
  13266. in _Salamandra maculata_, 75
  13267. Vital activity, 134-6, 139, 140, 166-9, 246, 247-8
  13268. current, 26, 27, 53-5, 80, 85, 87, 88, 96-105, 118-9, 120, 230-1,
  13269. 232, 239, 257, 266, 270
  13270. impetus, 50-1, 53-5, 85, 87, 88, 98-105, 118-9, 126-7, 128, 131-2,
  13271. 141-2, 148-9, 150, 218, 230-1, 232, 247-8, 250, 252, 254-5, 261
  13272. order, cause in, 34, 35, 94-5, 164
  13273. order, finality and, 223-5, 226
  13274. order, generalization in the, and in the mathematical order contrasted,
  13275. 225, 226, 230-1
  13276. order, and the geometrical order, 222-3, 225, 226, 230, 231, 235,
  13277. 236, 330-1
  13278. order, imitation of physical order by vital, 230
  13279. principle, 42, 43, 225, 226
  13280. order, repetition in the vital and the mathematical orders contrasted,
  13281. 225, 226, 230, 231
  13282. process, 166-7
  13283. Vitalism, 42, 43
  13284. Void, representation of, 273, 274, 275, 277-8, 281, 283-4, 289-90,
  13285. 291, 292, 294, 296, 298
  13286. Voisin, 80
  13287. Volition and cerebral mechanism, 253-4
  13288. Voluntary activity, 110, 252
  13289. Vries (de), 24, 63 _note_, 85
  13290. Wasps, instinct in, 140, 172
  13291. Weapons and intellect, 137
  13292. Weismann, 26, 78, 80-1
  13293. Will and caprice, 47
  13294. and cerebral mechanism, 252
  13295. current of, penetrating matter, 237
  13296. insertion of, into reality, 305-6, 307
  13297. and relaxation, 201, 207-8
  13298. and mechanism in disorder, 233
  13299. tension of, 199, 201, 207-8
  13300. Willed order, mutual contingency of willed order and mathematical
  13301. order, 231-3
  13302. unforeseeability in the, 224, 342-3
  13303. Willing, coincidence of seeing and, in intuition, 237
  13304. Wilson, E.B., 36
  13305. Wolff, 75 _note_
  13306. Words and states, 4, 302-3
  13307. three classes of, corresponding to three classes of representation,
  13308. 302-3, 313-4
  13309. World, intelligible, 162-3
  13310. principle: conciousness, 237, 261
  13311. Worms, in illustration of ambiguity of primitive organisms, 130
  13312. Yellow-winged sphex, paralyzing instinct in, 172
  13313. Zeno on motion, 308-13
  13314. Zone of potentialities surrounding acts, 179-80, 181, 264
  13315. Zoology, 128-9
  13316. Zoospores of algae, in illustration of mobility in plants, 112
  13317. End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Creative Evolution, by Henri Bergson
  13318. *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CREATIVE EVOLUTION ***
  13319. ***** This file should be named 26163-8.txt or 26163-8.zip *****
  13320. This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
  13321. http://www.gutenberg.org/2/6/1/6/26163/
  13322. Produced by Rick Niles, Graeme Mackreth and the Online
  13323. Distributed Proofreading Team at http://www.pgdp.net
  13324. Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
  13325. will be renamed.
  13326. Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
  13327. one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
  13328. (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
  13329. permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
  13330. set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
  13331. copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
  13332. protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
  13333. Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
  13334. charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
  13335. do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
  13336. rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
  13337. such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
  13338. research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
  13339. practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
  13340. subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
  13341. redistribution.
  13342. *** START: FULL LICENSE ***
  13343. THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
  13344. PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
  13345. To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
  13346. distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
  13347. (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
  13348. Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
  13349. Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
  13350. http://gutenberg.org/license).
  13351. Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
  13352. electronic works
  13353. 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
  13354. electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
  13355. and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
  13356. (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
  13357. the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
  13358. all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
  13359. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
  13360. Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
  13361. terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
  13362. entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
  13363. 1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
  13364. used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
  13365. agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
  13366. things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
  13367. even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
  13368. paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
  13369. Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
  13370. and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
  13371. works. See paragraph 1.E below.
  13372. 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
  13373. or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
  13374. Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
  13375. collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an
  13376. individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
  13377. located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
  13378. copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
  13379. works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
  13380. are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
  13381. Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
  13382. freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
  13383. this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
  13384. the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
  13385. keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
  13386. Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.
  13387. 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
  13388. what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
  13389. a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
  13390. the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
  13391. before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
  13392. creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
  13393. Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
  13394. the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
  13395. States.
  13396. 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
  13397. 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
  13398. access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
  13399. whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
  13400. phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
  13401. Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
  13402. copied or distributed:
  13403. This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
  13404. almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
  13405. re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
  13406. with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org
  13407. 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
  13408. from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
  13409. posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
  13410. and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
  13411. or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
  13412. with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
  13413. work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
  13414. through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
  13415. Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
  13416. 1.E.9.
  13417. 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
  13418. with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
  13419. must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
  13420. terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked
  13421. to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
  13422. permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
  13423. 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  13424. License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
  13425. work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
  13426. 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
  13427. electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
  13428. prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
  13429. active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
  13430. Gutenberg-tm License.
  13431. 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
  13432. compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
  13433. word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
  13434. distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
  13435. "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
  13436. posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org),
  13437. you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
  13438. copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
  13439. request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
  13440. form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  13441. License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
  13442. 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
  13443. performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
  13444. unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
  13445. 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
  13446. access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
  13447. that
  13448. - You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
  13449. the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
  13450. you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
  13451. owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
  13452. has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
  13453. Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
  13454. must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
  13455. prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
  13456. returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
  13457. sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
  13458. address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
  13459. the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
  13460. - You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
  13461. you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
  13462. does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
  13463. License. You must require such a user to return or
  13464. destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
  13465. and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
  13466. Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  13467. - You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
  13468. money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
  13469. electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
  13470. of receipt of the work.
  13471. - You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
  13472. distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
  13473. 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
  13474. electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
  13475. forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
  13476. both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
  13477. Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the
  13478. Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
  13479. 1.F.
  13480. 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
  13481. effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
  13482. public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
  13483. collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
  13484. works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
  13485. "Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
  13486. corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
  13487. property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
  13488. computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
  13489. your equipment.
  13490. 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
  13491. of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
  13492. Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
  13493. Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
  13494. Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
  13495. liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
  13496. fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
  13497. LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
  13498. PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
  13499. TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
  13500. LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
  13501. INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
  13502. DAMAGE.
  13503. 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
  13504. defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
  13505. receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
  13506. written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
  13507. received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
  13508. your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with
  13509. the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
  13510. refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
  13511. providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
  13512. receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy
  13513. is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
  13514. opportunities to fix the problem.
  13515. 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
  13516. in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER
  13517. WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
  13518. WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
  13519. 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
  13520. warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
  13521. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
  13522. law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
  13523. interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
  13524. the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
  13525. provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
  13526. 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
  13527. trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
  13528. providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
  13529. with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
  13530. promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
  13531. harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
  13532. that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
  13533. or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
  13534. work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
  13535. Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
  13536. Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
  13537. Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
  13538. electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
  13539. including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists
  13540. because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
  13541. people in all walks of life.
  13542. Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
  13543. assistance they need, is critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
  13544. goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
  13545. remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
  13546. Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
  13547. and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
  13548. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
  13549. and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
  13550. and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.
  13551. Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
  13552. Foundation
  13553. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
  13554. 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
  13555. state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
  13556. Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
  13557. number is 64-6221541. Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
  13558. http://pglaf.org/fundraising. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
  13559. Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
  13560. permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
  13561. The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
  13562. Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
  13563. throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at
  13564. 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
  13565. business@pglaf.org. Email contact links and up to date contact
  13566. information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
  13567. page at http://pglaf.org
  13568. For additional contact information:
  13569. Dr. Gregory B. Newby
  13570. Chief Executive and Director
  13571. gbnewby@pglaf.org
  13572. Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
  13573. Literary Archive Foundation
  13574. Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
  13575. spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
  13576. increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
  13577. freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
  13578. array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
  13579. ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
  13580. status with the IRS.
  13581. The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
  13582. charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
  13583. States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
  13584. considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
  13585. with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
  13586. where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To
  13587. SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
  13588. particular state visit http://pglaf.org
  13589. While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
  13590. have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
  13591. against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
  13592. approach us with offers to donate.
  13593. International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
  13594. any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
  13595. outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
  13596. Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
  13597. methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
  13598. ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations.
  13599. To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate
  13600. Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
  13601. works.
  13602. Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
  13603. concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
  13604. with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
  13605. Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
  13606. Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
  13607. editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
  13608. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily
  13609. keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
  13610. Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
  13611. http://www.gutenberg.org
  13612. This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
  13613. including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
  13614. Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
  13615. subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.